Skip to main content

Analysis of Prediction from Ethics of Scientific Research

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 292 Accesses

Part of the book series: European Studies in Philosophy of Science ((ESPS))

Abstract

Among the values that modulate scientific prediction there are ethical values. This chapter clarifies the ethical factors that modulate prediction in the context of scientific activity and science as activity. To do this, two perspectives of analysis are considered: (a) the endogenous ethics, which is oriented towards scientific activity by itself; and (b) the exogenous ethics, which analyses science as an activity connected with other activities (social, cultural, political, economic, ecological, etc.).

The starting point is the study of Rescher’s ethics of science, which gives primacy to the internal perspective. This leads to going more deeply into the exogenous perspective, which is also important for the problem of prediction. After that, the research is oriented towards the reflection about the problems posed by the relation between scientific prediction and ethical values. Thus, the repercussions on scientific prediction of the ethical limits of science are considered first. Second, the study of the ethical values of scientific prediction is developed from the dynamic viewpoint, which deals with the evaluation of the aims, processes, and results of the research. In this regard, the differences between basic science, applied science, and the application of science must be taken into account.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    This characteristic can be seen in the large number of publications that Rescher has devoted to the study of the ethics of science. Among then, some can be highlighted here: Rescher (1996, 1999a, 2003a).

  2. 2.

    This feature of Rescher’s approach does not mean that he is an eclectic philosopher, but rather that he has his own system of thought. See Chap. 1, Sect. 1.2.

  3. 3.

    “Anthropology” here might refer to social anthropology , so the goal of ethics is not merely the description of social uses and traditions.

  4. 4.

    Regarding this issue, the pragmatic aspect of his thought prevails, insofar as it goes from the actions to the subjects of those actions. He thinks of the person as one who unifies the processes, which are developed in the “personhood ,” which makes the features of that entity possible. In effect, he maintains that “once we conceptualize the core ‘self’ of a person as a unified manifold of actual and potential process—of action, and of capacities and dispositions to action (both physical and psychic)—then we have a concept of personhood that renders the self or ego experientially accessible. (After all, experiencing itself simply consists of such processes.),” Rescher (1994, p. 178). On the concept of “personhood ” in Rescher, see Moutafakis (2007, ch. 2, pp. 63–83; and ch. 6, pp. 139–160). An analysis of the concept of “person” is in Gonzalez (1983).

  5. 5.

    The Kantian influence is highlighted here. As Rescher admits, “this aspect of the present account is thoroughly Kantian. The governing idea of Kant ’s moral theory is that of universality; that when an action is wrong or right it is so always and for everyone,” Rescher (1997b, p. 167).

  6. 6.

    On the characteristics of ethical consequentialism there is an influential paper by Elisabeth Anscombe (1958).

  7. 7.

    On the theoretical framework of the ethics of science, see Gonzalez (1999b, pp. 147–151).

  8. 8.

    These are the three steps that configure the internal dynamics of scientific research. Cf. Gonzalez (2012, pp. 8–9).

  9. 9.

    The external dimension is addressed by Rescher in several publications; of note is Rescher (1996).

  10. 10.

    It should be emphasized that each one of those steps poses ethical questions. From this perspective, science should not be reduced to “general” ethical problems, since there are specific problems within each one of those realms (basic, applied, and of application). Ethics of science must be able to go in depth into each one, taking into account how these realms are interrelated. In this regard, ethics is not reduced to the structural dimension of scientific research, since it also affects the dynamics over time. Thus, there are ethical factors in the historicity that have to do with the relation of the agent with the context (natural, social, or artificial) and other factors that deal with the historicity of the very relations among the researchers (for example, in the research centers). Gonzalez, Personal communication , 2.1.2015.

  11. 11.

    The view of truth as an ethical value appears in philosophers like Karl Popper . On this topic, see Martinez Solano (2005, pp. 282–294).

  12. 12.

    A good example of the combination of these factors is provided by John Worrall when he analyzes clinical trials. See, in this regard, Worrall (2006).

  13. 13.

    This problem also has implications regarding the limits of science as barriers (Shranken), insofar as the distinction between science and non-science (or pseudoscience) is at stake. Cf. Rescher (2006b, p. 215). See, in this regard, Gonzalez (2016).

  14. 14.

    Ethical problems that have to do with the publication, dissemination, and authorship of the research results are analyzed in Resnik (1998, pp. 96–121).

  15. 15.

    His interest in ethical problems related with the application of science can be seen in several of his publications. Among them, Rescher (1996, 2003a)

  16. 16.

    This means that, in this regard, agents’ historicity is twofold: the relations between the researches have features of variability over time that make those relations different from the relations between the agents and the context (natural, social, or artificial). Frequently, the relations of the former case are intense and revisable, possibly to a larger extent than in the latter case. This type of variability can be seen in the changes in the groups of research and in the internal dynamic of the research centers. History of science selects the representative actions of both types of historicity , insofar as they are important for the development of the scientific activity . Gonzalez, Personal communication , 2.1.2015.

  17. 17.

    In Rescher’s approach, the cognitive content of basic science as such (that is, considered by itself) is not susceptible of ethical evaluation. Ethical evaluation appears when basic science is seen as related with human activity (where ends, means, and results with their consequences are at stake).

  18. 18.

    This projection has been clear during the last decades in the realm of communications (for example, between the signal theory and mobile telephony devices). But this feature does not involve reducing technology to applied science or considering that technology is a pure application of science . The relation between science and technology was emphasized in chapter one of this book, and it is described by Rescher as two legs of the same body (1999a, p. 100).

  19. 19.

    This can be seen in the successive international meetings on climate change, where the meeting in Río de Janeiro (1992), Kyoto (1997), Copenhagen (2009), and Paris (2015) can be highlighted.

  20. 20.

    The concept of “intentionality ” is understood as a feature of a human activity, a feature which is developed in the action of an agent or a group of agents, so it is not equivalent to “intention” as a simple mental act (and, therefore, unobservable). On this issue, see Elskamp (1986).

  21. 21.

    The problem of how historicity can be compatible with objectivity is analyzed in Gonzalez (2008b).

  22. 22.

    Niiniluoto is a philosopher who has insisted especially on the autonomy of science as a characteristic feature of what science is or should be. In his judgment, “the community of investigators ceases to be a scientific community if it gives up—or is forced to give up—this principle of autonomy,” Niiniluoto (1984, p. 6). On the concept of “autonomy,” see Gonzalez (1990, pp. 100–104 and 108–109, 2015, pp. 25–28) and O’Neill (2003).

  23. 23.

    Rescher considers that autonomy is a defining feature of science. In his judgment, “the acceptability of the scientific proposals is an issue that should be completely resolved at the level of internal considerations to scientific endeavor. A ‘science’ subject to external criteria of correctness is simply not worthy of that name,” (1999a, p. 115). The search for a balance between the autonomy of science and the limits due to ethical issues is a main concern in the recent literature on the ethics of science. See, for example, Douglas (2007, pp. 126–131).

  24. 24.

    This is expressly accepted by Rescher. In his judgment, “one very pervasive problem at this institutional level is the classical issue of pure, or basic, versus applied, or practical, research. This problem is always with us and is always difficult, for the more ‘applied’ the research contribution, the more it can yield immediate benefits to man; the more ‘fundamental’, the deeper is its scientific significance and the more it can contribute to the development of science itself,” (2006b, p. 204).

  25. 25.

    On the problems related to the prediction of future science, see Rescher (2012a).

  26. 26.

    On how historicity is compatible with objectivity , see Gonzalez (2008b).

  27. 27.

    These three cases should be taken into account in the development of the axiology of research as well. See Chap. 8, Sect. 8.5 of this book.

  28. 28.

    Gonzalez, Personal communication , 2.1.2015.

  29. 29.

    See, in this regard, Mearns (2010) and Parker (2011, 2014).

  30. 30.

    This kind of problems is also frequent in professional practices (for example, when several physicians disagree about the best way of treating a patient).

References

  • Agazzi, E. 1992. Il bene, il male e la scienza. Le dimensioni etiche dell’impresa scientifico-tecnologica. Milán: Rusconi. Spanish version of Ramón Queraltó: El bien, el mal y la Ciencia. Las dimensiones éticas de la empresa científico-tecnológica 1996. Madrid: Tecnos.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1999. Límites éticos del quehacer científico y tecnológico. In Ciencia y valores éticos, ed. W.J. Gonzalez. Monographic issue of Arbor 162 (638): 241–262.

    Google Scholar 

  • Anscombe, G.E.M. 1958. Modern moral philosophy. Philosophy 33: 1–19. Reprinted in Wallace, G. and Walker, A. D. M. eds. 1970. The Definition of Morality, 211–234. London: Mathuen.

    Google Scholar 

  • Balmer, B. 2015. The social dimension of technology: The control of chemical and biological weapons. In New perspectives on technology, values, and ethics: Theoretical and practical. Boston studies in the philosophy of science, ed. W.J. Gonzalez, 167–182. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Cranor, C.F. 1994. Public health rsearch and uncertainty. In Ethics of scientific research, ed. K.S. Shrader-Frechette, ch. 10, 169–185. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Douglas, H. 2007. Rejecting the ideal of value-free science. In Value-free science? Ideals and illusions, ed. H. Kincaid, J. Dupré, A. Wylie, 120–139. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Elskamp, R.G. 1986. Intención e intencionalidad: Estudio comparativo. Anales de Filosofía 4: 147–156.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gonzalez, W.J. 1983. La primitividad lógica del concepto de persona. Anales de Filosofía 1: 79–118.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1990. Progreso científico, autonomía de la Ciencia y realismo. Arbor 135(532): 91–109.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1999a. Racionalidad científica y actividad humana: Ciencia y valores en la Filosofía de Nicholas Rescher. In Razón y valores en la Era científico-tecnológica, N. Rescher, 11–44. Barcelona: Paidós.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1999b. Ciencia y valores éticos: De la posibilidad de la Ética de la Ciencia al problema de la valoración ética de la Ciencia Básica. In Ciencia y valores éticos, ed. W.J. Gonzalez. Monographic issue of Arbor 162 (638): 139–161.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2005. The philosophical approach to science, technology and society. In Science, technology and society: A philosophical perspective, ed. W.J. Gonzalez, 3–49. A Coruña: Netbiblo.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007. La contribución de la predicción al diseño en las Ciencias de lo Artificial. In Las Ciencias de Diseño: Racionalidad limitada, predicción y prescripción, ed. W.J. Gonzalez, 183–202. A Coruña: Netbiblo.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2008a. Rationality and prediction in the sciences of the artificial. In Reasoning, rationality and probability, ed. M.C. Galavotti, R. Scazzieri, and P. Suppes, 165–186. Stanford: CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2008b. El enfoque cognitivo en la Ciencia y el problema de la historicidad: Caracterización desde los conceptos. Letras 114 (79): 51–80.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2012. Las Ciencias de Diseño en cuanto Ciencias de la Complejidad: Análisis de la Economía, Documentación y Comunicación. In Las Ciencias de la Complejidad: Vertiente dinámica de las Ciencias de Diseño y sobriedad de factores, ed. W.J. Gonzalez, 7–30. A Coruña: Netbiblo.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013a. Value ladenness and the value-free ideal in scientific research. In Handbook of the philosophical foundations of business ethics, ed. Ch. Lütge, 1503–1521. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013b. The roles of scientific creativity and technological innovation in the context of complexity of science. In Creativity, innovation, and complexity in science, ed. W.J Gonzalez, 11–40. A Coruña; Netbiblio.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2015. Philosophico-Methodological Analysis of Prediction and its Role in Economics, Springer, Dordrecht, 2015.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2016. Rethinking the limits of science: From the difficulties for the frontiers to the concern on the confines. In The limits of science: An analysis from “barriers” to “confines”, Poznan studies in the philosophy of the sciences and the humanities, ed. W.J. Gonzalez, 3–30. Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martinez Solano, J.F. 2005. El problema de la verdad en K. R. Popper: Reconstrucción histórico-sistemática. A Coruña: Netbiblo.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mearns, L.O. 2010. Quantification of uncertainties of future climate change: Challenges and applications. Philosophy of Science 77 (5): 998–1011.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moutafakis, N.J. 2007. Rescher on rationality, values, and social responsibility. A philosophical portrait. Heusenstamm: Ontos Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Neira, P. 2015. Values regarding results of the information and communication technologies: Internal values. In New perspectives on technology, values, and ethics: Theoretical and practical.Boston studies in the philosophy and history of science, ed. W.J. Gonzalez, 47–60. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto, I. 1984. Is science progressive? Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1993. The aim and structure of applied research. Erkenntnis 38 (1): 1–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Neill, O. 2003. Autonomy: The Emperor’s new clothes. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 77: 1–21.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parker, W.S. 2011. When climate models agree: The significance of robust model predictions. Philosophy of Science 78 (4): 579–600.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. Values and uncertainties in climate prediction, revisited. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, Part A 46: 24–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K.R. 1984. Auf der Suche nach einer besseren Welt. Munich: Piper. English translation by Laura J. Bennett and reviewed by K. Popper and M. Mew. 1992. In Search of a Better World. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prichard, H.A. 1912. Does Moral Philosophy Rest on a Mistake? Mind 21: 21–37.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, N. 1988. Rationality. A philosophical inquiry into the nature and the rationale of reason. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1989. Moral absolutes. An essay on the nature and rationale of morality. New York: Peter Lang.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1990. Our science as O-U-R science. In A useful inheritance. Evolutionary aspects of the theory of knowledge, N. Rescher, 77–104. Savage: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1993a. Moral objectivity (Are there moral facts?). In A system of pragmatic idealism. Vol. II: The validity of values: Human values in pragmatic perspective, N. Rescher, 173–186. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1993b. Moral values as immune to relativism. In A system of pragmatic idealism. Vol. II: The validity of values: Human values in pragmatic perspective, N. Rescher, 187–205. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1993c. Moral rationality: Why be moral? In A system of pragmatic idealism. Vol. II: The validity of values: Human values in pragmatic perspective, N. Rescher, 206–232. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1994. Philosophy in process. In A system of pragmatic idealism. Vol. III: Metaphilosophical Inquires, N. Rescher, 168–181. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1996. Public concerns. Philosophical studies of social issues. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1997a. Against moral relativism. In Objectivity. The obligations of impersonal reason, N. Rescher, 124–150. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1997b. Moral objectivity: The rationality and universality of moral principles. In Objectivity. The obligations of impersonal reason, N. Rescher, 151–171. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1998. Predicting the future. An introduction to the theory of forecasting. New York: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1999a. Razón y valores en la Era científico-tecnológica. Barcelona: Paidós.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1999b. The limits of science. Revised ed. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press. 1st ed. 1984.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2003a. Sensible decisions. Issues of rational decision in personal choice and public policy. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2003b. Technology, complexity, and social decision. In Sensible decisions, issues of rational decision in personal choice and public policy, N. Rescher, 81–98. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2003c. Risking democracy (Some reflections on contemporary problems of political decision). In Sensible decisions. Issues of rational decision in personal choice and public policy, N. Rescher, 113–124. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2003d. Collective responsibility. In Sensible decisions. Issues of rational decision in personal choice and public policy, N. Rescher, 125–138. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2006a. Credit for making a discovery. In Studies in the philosophy of science, N. Rescher, 181–200. Heusenstamm: Ontos Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2006b. The ethical dimension of scientific research. In Studies in the philosophy of science, N. Rescher, 201–218. Heusenstamm: Ontos Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2008. Moral objectivity. Social Philosophy and Policy Foundation 25 (1): 393–409.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2012a. The problem of future knowledge. Mind and Society 11 (2): 149–163.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2012b. Political pragmatism. In Pragmatism. The restoration of its scientific roots, N. Rescher, 205–215. N. Brunswick: Transaction Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Resnik, D.B. 1998. The ethics of science. An introduction. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. 1986. Prediction and economic theory. In Predictability in Science and Society, ed. J. Mason, P. Mathias, and J.H. Westcott, 3–23. London: The Royal Society and The British Academy.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shrader-Frechette, K.S. 1994. Ethics of scientific research. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H.A. 1990. Prediction and prescription in systems modeling, Operations Research 38: 7–14. Compiled in Simon, H.A., Models of bounded rationality. Vol. 3: Empirically grounded economic reason, The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, 1997, pp. 115–128.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wendler, D. 2014. The ethics of clinical research. In The Stanford Encyclopedia of philosophy, ed. E.N. Zalta (fall edition 2014), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2012/entries/clinical-research. Accessed on 20 Jan 2015.

  • Worrall, J. 2006. Why randomize? Evidence and ethics in clinical trials. In Contemporary perspectives in philosophy and methodology of science, ed. W.J. Gonzalez and J. Alcolea, 65–82. A Coruña: Netbiblo.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Guillán, A. (2017). Analysis of Prediction from Ethics of Scientific Research. In: Pragmatic Idealism and Scientific Prediction. European Studies in Philosophy of Science. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-63043-4_9

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics