Skip to main content

Conceptual Framework of the Methodology of Prediction and Preconditions for Rational Prediction

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 285 Accesses

Part of the book series: European Studies in Philosophy of Science ((ESPS))

Abstract

Following a pragmatic setting, Rescher’s methodology of scientific prediction is connected with his general methodological approach. Prediction has a fundamental role in it, since it is one of the main indicators of methodological efficacy. In order to clarify the conceptual framework of the methodology of prediction, this chapter follows several steps. First, the focus is on Rescher’s methodological pragmatism as a framework for the analysis of scientific prediction from a methodological perspective. Second, the attention shifts to the roles of prediction in scientific activity. Third, the different groups of empirical sciences (the natural sciences, the social sciences, and the sciences of the artificial) are considered.

Thereafter, the preconditions for rational prediction are analyzed. In Rescher’s judgment, these preconditions are three: data availability, pattern discernability, and pattern stability. In his approach, preconditions are necessary and sufficient conditions for predictability, so they are especially relevant in his methodological proposal about scientific prediction.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    “Proposition” is used here with the meaning of the content expressed by a statement, a content that can be evaluated regarding truth or truthlikeness .

  2. 2.

    The three types of sciences are analyzed here, although Rescher is mainly interested in the natural sciences (above all, in physics ).

  3. 3.

    In this regard, see Margolis (2002), Bacon (2012), Burke (2013), and Caamaño (2013).

  4. 4.

    It should be highlighted that frequently pragmatism goes hand in hand with another complementary philosophical approach, above all regarding epistemological matters. For example, Philip Kitcher combines realism with pragmatism. Cf. Gonzalez (2011c).

  5. 5.

    “A noteworthy—and distinctly curious—aspect of contemporary American philosophy relates to the fate of ‘pragmatism,’ which has undergone a remarkable deformation from its original conception. Many—indeed most—philosophers nowadays think of pragmatism as something radically different from what was originally at issue with this conception. And, oddly enough, this latter-day sort of pragmatism is not a ‘new improved version’ but a markedly inferior product,” Rescher (2012b), p. 1.

  6. 6.

    “On such a view, pragmatism is not so much a philosophical doctrine as a position that urges the abandonment of philosophy and recommends finding something else to do instead,” Rescher (2000, p. xi).

  7. 7.

    Although Rescher uses many times the term “instrumental” regarding his methodological approach, it is certainly not an instrumentalist approach in the sense of a subordination of theory to practice in terms of importance. In his judgment, practical rationality (which allows us to decide about the rationality of the processes) also encompasses a theoretical dimension. Practice and theory are equally important. However, “it takes considerations of purposive effectiveness to provide the test-standard for the adequacy of the operative principles of human endeavor—alike in theoretical and in practical matters. Effective implementation is its pervasive standard of adequacy,” Rescher (2004, pp. 43–44).

  8. 8.

    On the problem of the methodological universalism, see Gonzalez (2012c).

  9. 9.

    Rescher considers that a method consists of a series of general rules or patterns in order to perform a task, so it is possible to use a method on successive occasions. However, there are different levels of generality or abstraction regarding methods, depending on the general or specific character of the matter at issue. Hence, he assumes that different levels of scales of reality (macro, meso, and micro) require different methods. Cf. Rescher, Personal communication , 10.6.2014.

  10. 10.

    About the role of consensus in other contexts from a broad perspective, see Rescher (1993).

  11. 11.

    In this regard, Rescher notes that “on the standard ‘inductive’ model of scientific method, the predictions of science are generated by logico-mathematical derivations that apply general theories to situation-specific facts so as to preindicate future observations . Then, insofar as the actual observations agree with those predictions, the theories at issue are confirmed and thereby evidentially substantiated, and insofar as they diverge, the theories are disconfirmed and evidentially undermined,” Rescher (1998a, p. 161).

  12. 12.

    Usually, Rescher does not distinguish between the subject matters of the natural sciences , the social sciences , and the sciences of the artificial. His approach seeks to be as general as possible.

  13. 13.

    “‘Progress’ is a normative or goal-relative—rather than purely descriptive—term,” Niiniluoto (1980, p. 427). See also Niiniluoto (1984).

  14. 14.

    Changes might be positive or negative as well as developments, which might be positive or negative.

  15. 15.

    This can be clearly seen in Rescher’s “thesis of harmony,” according to which explanation and prediction are not symmetrical processes, but are closely interrelated as crucial goals of science. See, in this regard, Sect. 3.4.2 of this book.

  16. 16.

    On the role of prediction in the applied sciences , see, for example, Gonzalez (2007) and Simon (1990).

  17. 17.

    On the predictive procedure Delphi, see Ayyub (2001) and Bell (2003).

  18. 18.

    “Prediction, in sum, is our instrument for resolving our meaningful questions about the future, or at least of endeavoring to solve them in a rationally cogent manner,” Rescher (1998a, p. 39).

  19. 19.

    In this regard, Rescher’s view is quite different from M. Friedman ’s (1953).

  20. 20.

    On the differences between basic science and applied science , see Niiniluoto (1993, 1995) and Gonzalez (2005, 2013a).

  21. 21.

    On the distinction between basic science, applied science , and the application of science , see Gonzalez (2013a, pp. 11–40; especially, pp. 17–18).

  22. 22.

    There is also a third possibility: heuristic novelty . See Gonzalez (2014, pp. 1–25; especially, pp. 14–16).

  23. 23.

    On the controversy about the methodological weight of “prediction” and “accommodation ,” see Gonzalez (2010, pp. 288–292). A defense of the predictivist position is in White (2003). Rescher’s account in this regard is further developed in Chap. 8, Sect. 8.3.2 of this book.

  24. 24.

    This is a clear expression of his rejection of the instrumentalist predictivism without realism of the assumption, which was defended by M. Friedman (1953).

  25. 25.

    On this issue, see Sect. 3.1 of this book.

  26. 26.

    These ethical features are analyzed in-depth in Chap. 9.

  27. 27.

    On the discussions about determinism and freedom, see Gonzalez (2012d).

  28. 28.

    “As many writers see it, complexity is determined by the extent to which chance, randomness, and lack of lawful regularity in general is absent. But this cannot be the whole story, since law systems themselves can clearly be more or less complex,” Rescher (1998b, p. 8).

  29. 29.

    On the differences between science and technology, see Gonzalez (2005, pp. 11–12).

  30. 30.

    Since Simon emphasizes the connections between sciences of design and technology, his approach to the notion of design is somewhat ambiguous, insofar as it does not make it possible to distinguish “design” form “scientific design.” Cf. Gonzalez (2007, p. 11).

  31. 31.

    Of course, the outcomes attained could differ from the stated aims. This can happen commonly when the possible problems are not correctly anticipated.

  32. 32.

    On the role of prediction and prescription in the sciences of the artificial, see Gonzalez (2008, sect. 4, pp. 179–183).

  33. 33.

    Creativity as an ontological limit to predictability , which affects above all the social sciences and the sciences of the artificial, is analyzed in Chap. 7, Sect. 7.3.3 of this book.

  34. 34.

    It should be noted that Rescher does not consider “relevance,” as such, as a criterion regarding the data that is required in order to predict. However, he offers a series of criteria that the relevant data for prediction should meet, such as accuracy or reliability.

  35. 35.

    According to Rescher, we are not really interested in prediction as such; but our interest is in reliable predictions. In his judgment, the reliability of a prediction might rest partly on the evidence and partly on the kind of phenomenon at issue (for example, if it is stable or volatile). In this case, the ontological aspect involves the attention to the context, which may influence the behavior of the phenomena. Rescher, Personal communication , 2.6.2015.

  36. 36.

    On the implications of anarchy for predictability, see Sect. 7.3.1 of this monograph.

  37. 37.

    Rescher’s proposal regarding complexity is analyzed in Chap. 7, Sect. 7.4.

  38. 38.

    The epistemological and ontological limits to predictability are analyzed in more detail in Chap. 4, Sect. 4.4 and Chap. 7, Sect. 7.3.

  39. 39.

    On the dynamic dimension of complexity and the role of historicity , especially in the social sciences and the sciences of the artificial, see Chap. 7, Sect. 7.4.3 of this monograph.

References

  • Ayyub, B.M. 2001. Elicitation of expert opinions for uncertainty and risks. Boca Raton: CRC Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bacon, M. 2012. Pragmatism: An introduction. Cambridge/Malden: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Batitsky, V., and Z. Domotor. 2007. When good theories make bad predictions. Synthese 157 (1): 79–103.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bell, W. 2003. Foundations of futures studies. History, purposes, and knowledge, human science for a new era, vol. 1. Piscataway: Transaction Publishers (5th rep. 2009; 1st ed. 1997).

    Google Scholar 

  • Bereijo, A. 2011. The category of “Applied Science.” An analysis of its justification from ‘Information Science’ as design science. In Scientific realism and democratic society: The philosophy of Philip Kitcher, Poznan studies in the philosophy of the sciences and humanities, vol. 101, ed. W.J. Gonzalez: 329–353. Amsterdam/New York: Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burke, F.Th. 2013. What pragmatism was. Bloomington: Indiana University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Caamaño, M. 2013. Pragmatic norm in science: Making them explicit. Synthese 190: 3227–3246.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dasgupta, S. 1994. Creativity in invention and design. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. 1953. The methodology of positive economics. In Essays in positive economics, M. Friedman, 3–43. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press (6th reprint, 1969).

    Google Scholar 

  • Gonzalez, W.J. 1997. Progreso científico e innovación tecnológica: La ‘Tecnociencia’ y el problema de las relaciones entre Filosofía de la Ciencia y Filosofía de la Tecnología. Arbor 157 (620): 261–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1999. Ciencia y valores éticos: De la posibilidad de la Ética de la Ciencia al problema de la valoración ética de la Ciencia Básica. Arbor 162 (638): 139–171.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2005. The philosophical approach to science, technology and society. In Science, technology and society: A philosophical perspective, ed. W.J. Gonzalez, 3–49. A Coruña: Netbiblo.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007. Análisis de las Ciencias de Diseño desde la racionalidad limitada, la predicción y la prescripción. In Las Ciencias de Diseño: Racionalidad limitada, predicción y prescripción, ed. W.J. Gonzalez, 3–38. A Coruña: Netbiblo.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2008. Rationality and prediction in the sciences of the artificial. In Reasoning, rationality, and probability, ed. M.C. Galavotti, R. Scazzieri, and P. Suppes, 165–186. Stanford: CSLI Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2010. La predicción científica. Concepciones filosófico-metodológicas desde H. Reichenbach a N. Rescher. Barcelona, Montesinos.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2011a. Conceptual changes and scientific diversity: The role of historicity. In Conceptual revolutions: From cognitive science to medicine, ed. W.J. Gonzalez, 39–62. A Coruña: Netbiblo.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2011b. Complexity in economics and prediction: The role of parsimonious factors. In Explanation, prediction, and confirmation, ed. D. Dieks, W.J. Gonzalez, S. Hartman, Th. Uebel, and M. Weber, 319–330. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • ———., ed. 2011c. Scientific realism and democratic society: The philosophy of Philip Kitcher, Poznan studies in the philosophy of the sciences and the humanities. Amsterdam: Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2012a. La vertiente dinámica de las Ciencias de la Complejidad. Repercusión de la historicidad para la predicción científica en las Ciencias Diseño. In Las Ciencias de la Complejidad: Vertiente dinámica de las Ciencias de Diseño y sobriedad de factores, ed. W.J. Gonzalez, 73–106. A Coruña: Netbiblo.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2012b. Complejidad estructural en Ciencias de Diseño y su incidencia en la predicción científica: El papel de la sobriedad de factores (parsimonious factors). In Las Ciencias de la Complejidad: Vertiente dinámica de las Ciencias de Diseño y sobriedad de factores, ed. W.J. Gonzalez, 143–167. A Coruña: Netbiblo.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2012c. Methodological universalism in science and its limits. Imperialism versus complexity. In Thinking about provincialism in thinking, Poznan studies in the philosophy of the sciences and the humanities, vol. 100, eds. K. Brzechczyn and K. Paprzycka, 155–175. Amsterdam/New York: Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2012d. New reflections on an old problem: Freedom and determinism in the scientific context. In Freedom and determinism: Social sciences and natural sciences, monographic volume of Peruvian Journal of Epistemology, vol. 1, ed. W.J. Gonzalez, 3–20. Cambre: Imprenta Mundo.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013a. The roles of scientific creativity and technological innovation in the context of complexity of science. In Creativity, innovation, and complexity in science, ed. W.J. Gonzalez, 11–40. A Coruña: Netbiblo.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013b. The sciences of design as sciences of complexity: The dynamic trait. In New challenges to philosophy of science, ed. H. Andersen, D. Dieks, W.J. Gonzalez, Th. Uebel, and G. Wheeler, 299–311. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. The evolution of Lakatos’s repercussion on the methodology of economics. HOPOS: The Journal of the International Society for the History of Philosophy of Science 4 (1): 1–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2015. Philosophico-methodological analysis of prediction and its role in economics. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Guillán, A. 2013. Analysis of creativity in the sciences of design. In Creativity, Innovation, and Complexity in Science, ed. W.J. Gonzalez, 125–139. A Coruña: Netbiblo.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hendry, D.F. 2003. How economists forecast. In Understanding economic forecasts, ed. D.F. Hendry and N.R. Ericsson, 15–41. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howson, C. and Urbach, P. 1989. Scientific reasoning: The Bayesian approach. La Salle: Open Court (reprinted in 1990; 2nd edition in 1993).

    Google Scholar 

  • Margolis, J. 2002. Reinventing pragmatism. American philosophy at the end of the twentieth century. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martínez Solano, J. F. 2012. La complejidad en la Ciencia de la Economía: De F. A. Hayek a H. A. Simon. In Las Ciencias de la Complejidad: Vertiente dinámica de las Ciencias de Diseño y sobriedad de factores, ed. W.J. Gonzalez, 233-266. A Coruña: Netbiblo.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mellor, D.H. 1975. The possibility of prediction. Proceedings of the British Academy 65: 207–223.

    Google Scholar 

  • Niiniluoto, I. 1980. Scientific progress. Synthese 45: 427–462.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1984. Is science progressive? Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1993. The aim and structure of applied research. Erkenntnis 38 (1): 1–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1995. Approximation in applied science. Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of Sciences and the Humanities 42: 127–139.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1997. Límites de la Tecnología. Arbor 157 (620): 391–410.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, N. 1973. The Primacy of Practice. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1977. Methodological pragmatism. A systems-theoretic approach to the theory of knowledge. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1990. Our science as o-u-r science. In A useful inheritance. Evolutionary aspects of the theory of knowledge, N. Rescher, 77–104. Savage: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1993. Pluralism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1997. Pragmatism in crisis. In Profitable speculations. essays on current philosophical themes, N. Rescher, 27–48. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1995. Predictive incapacity and rational decision. European Review 3 (4): 327–332. Compiled in Rescher, N. 2003. Sensible decisions. Issues of rational decision in personal choice and public policy, 39–47. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield..

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1996. Process metaphysics. An introduction to process philosophy. New York: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1998a. Predicting the future. An introduction to the theory of forecasting. New York: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1998b. Complexity: A philosophical overview. N. Brunswick: Transaction Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1998c. Collective responsibility. Journal of Social Philosophy 29: 44–58. Compiled in Rescher, N. 2003. Sensible decisions. Issues of rational decision in personal choice and public policy, 125–138. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1999a. The limits of science, revised ed. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1999b. Risking democracy (some reflections on contemporary problems of political decision). Public Affairs Quarterly 12: 297–308.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1999c. Razón y valores en la Era científico-tecnológica. Barcelona: Paidós.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2000. Realistic pragmatism. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2003. Technology, complexity, and social decision. In Sensible decisions. Issues of rational decision in personal choice and public policy. N. Rescher, 81–98. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2004. Pragmatism and practical rationality. Contemporary Pragmatism 1 (1): 43–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2009a. Free will: A philosophical reappraisal. New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2009b. Ignorance. On the wider implications of deficient knowledge. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2012a. The problem of future knowledge. Mind and Society 11 (2): 149–163.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2012b. Pragmatism at the crossroads. Pragmatism. The Restoration of its Scientific Roots, N. Rescher, 1–19. New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers. (Originally published as Rescher, N. 2005. Pragmatism at the crossroads. Transactions of the C. S. Peirce Society 41 (2): 355–365.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2012c. Political pragmatism. In Pragmatism. The restoration of its scientific roots, N. Rescher, 205–215. New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, R. 1982. Consequences of pragmatism. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H.A. 1989. The state of economic science. In The state of economic science. Views of six Nobel laureates, ed. W. Sichel, 97–110. Kalamazoo: W. E. Upjohn Institute for Employment Research.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1990. Prediction and prescription in systems modeling. Operations Research 38: 7–14. Compiled in Models of bounded rationality. Vol. 3: empirically grounded economic reason, ed. H.A. Simon, 115–128. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1995. Problem forming, problem finding, and problem solving in design. In Design and systems: General applications of methodology, ed. A. Collen and W.W. Gasparski, vol. 3, 245–257. New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1996. The sciences of the artificial. 3rd ed. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press. (1st ed., 1969; 2nd ed., 1981).

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2001. Science seeks parsimony, not simplicity: Searching for pattern in phenomena. In Simplicity, inference and modeling. Keeping it sophisticatedly simple, ed. A. Zellner, H.A. Keuzenkamp, and M. McAleer, 32–72. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2002. Forecasting the future or shaping it? Industrial and Corporate Change 11 (3): 601–605.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • White, R. 2003. The epistemic advantage of prediction over accommodation. Mind 112 (448): 653–683.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Guillán, A. (2017). Conceptual Framework of the Methodology of Prediction and Preconditions for Rational Prediction. In: Pragmatic Idealism and Scientific Prediction. European Studies in Philosophy of Science. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-63043-4_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics