Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Crossroads of Knowledge ((CROKNOW))

  • 607 Accesses

Abstract

Introducing Husserl’s phenomenology of the body, the author argues that this approach can negotiate the different—and sometimes conflicting—manners in which we experience sexual embodiment. Following through several levels of embodiment as evident in Husserl’s analyses, the author argues that different aspects of the body’s materiality, sexuality, and sensory and concrete experience are constituted within each level. Thus, although the experiences of each level filter into and influence the others, we can understand our embodiment in very different ways in spite of (and along with) any apparent conflicts. The body is a unified whole of these experiential levels, from fundamental sensory experience through the social and discursive constitutions of sexual embodiment.

Excerpts from Sullivan’s diaries accompany the theoretical discussion in a way that Sullivan himself might engage in the theory.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    I have published an earlier version of this example elsewhere (Rodemeyer 2008).

  2. 2.

    This division is more complex than I make it out here, although my analyses in this chapter begin to break down this simple distinction. See also Rodemeyer (2014). Once again, I apologize for my reference to “the transsexual,” as well as “the intersexual,” in this article. I hope to have avoided repeating such egregious errors in this book.

  3. 3.

    All pagination refers to the translation of Husserl’s Ideas II (1989) by R. Rojcewicz and A. Schuwer.

  4. 4.

    A more extended and technical version of the following analyses was presented at the University of Graz, in a paper entitled “Phenomenological Gymnastics: An Analysis of Levels of Embodiment,” December 10, 2015. I thank the coordinators and the participants of that workshop for their feedback.

  5. 5.

    See Al-Saji (2010) for a critical assessment of Merleau-Ponty’s interpretation of Husserl’s example: “Merleau-Ponty reads the touching-touched experience as a relation of subject and object—of for-itself and in-itself which are mutually exclusive to one another. In this context, my hand can be either absolute subject, ‘alive and mobile,’ touching and exploring the world; or it can be touched by my other hand, and descend into a passivity that does not even feel itself as such. It seems that the touched hand loses its affectivity; it cannot feel its being touched while my other hand consciously palpates it. At that moment, the touched hand becomes an object, a ‘bundle of bones and muscles.’ Its power to touch, and its awareness of itself, is there only in memory and anticipation, waiting for the next instant when it can regain this power and, touching the other hand, reduce it to the status of an object.” (Al-Saji 2010, 21).

  6. 6.

    To elaborate, in the formation of my embodiment, I feel the surface of my fingers while touching an object, and I also feel the thickness and movement of my fingers, hand, and arm as I slide my fingers along. These sensations group together since they are distinguished from all experiences of objects that do not have this inner sense of thickness, movement, and sensation. The body begins to appear, then, as a particular object—the only one that is sensed in this way. This is the “primordial” formation of the body as Leib. This formation is then unified with my sense of self, a perceptual perspective that is mine.

  7. 7.

    Husserl’s analysis is not without its difficulties. However, the issue of solipsism is not the topic of these analyses. Moreover, the topic has been dealt with extensively in the secondary literature, from Martin Heidegger and Alfred Schutz to Simone de Beauvoir, and many more in phenomenology as well as feminist theory and other areas.

  8. 8.

    Husserl understands the term “perspective” quite literally here. It is a spatial perspective, not a personal one. Simply put, I do not gain insight into another person’s experiences, history, culture, embodiment, etc. by imagining myself in her place; rather I simply understand that her spatial position provides another angle on the world than the one I have. Husserl makes clear that I cannot access the other person’s thoughts or her direct experiences (see, e.g., Husserl 1989, 171–2).

  9. 9.

    The objectification of women and people of color is usually a background presumption in most theories in the humanities and social sciences today. De Beauvoir’s seminal text, The Second Sex (1953), was a crucial work that launched such discussions from the perspective of feminist philosophy; Franz Fanon’s Black Skin, White Masks (1968) was similarly influential with regard to critical race theory. Butler (1999) and Foucault (1980), as we have been discussing, developed this notion with regard to sex, gender, and embodiment in general, which resulted in subsequent focused areas, such as queer theory, transgender studies, and disability theory.

  10. 10.

    This argument also parallels specific arguments made by Namaste (2000), some of which we have already discussed in Chap. 2.

References

  • Al-Saji, A. (2010). Bodies and sensings: On the uses of Husserlian phenomenology for feminist theory. Continental Philosophy Review, 43(1), 13–37.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Benjamin, H. (1966). The transsexual phenomenon. New York: Julian.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bornstein, K. (1994). Gender outlaw: On men, women, and the rest of us. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Butler, J. (1999). Gender trouble: Feminism and the subversion of Identity (10th anniversary edition). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cromwell, J. (2006). Queering the binaries: Transsituated identities, bodies, and sexualities. In S. Stryker & S. Whittle (Eds.), The transgender studies reader (pp. 509–520). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Beauvoir, S. (1953). The second sex. New York: Knopf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fanon, F. (1968). Black skin, white masks. New York: Grove.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M. (1980). The history of sexuality: Volume I: An introduction (R. Hurley, Trans.). New York: Vintage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M. (1995). Discipline and punish: The birth of the prison (A. Sheridan, Trans.). New York: Vintage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Green, J. (2006). Look! No, don’t!: The visibility dilemma for transsexual men. In S. Stryker & S. Whittle (Eds.), The transgender studies reader (pp. 499–508). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1989). Ideas pertaining to a pure phenomenology and to a phenomenological philosophy, second book (Ideas II) (R. Rojcewicz & A. Schuwer, Trans.). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jorgenson, C. (1967). Christine Jorgenson: A personal autobiography. New York: Paul S. Erikson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (1962). Phenomenology of perception (C. Smith, Trans.). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meyerowitz, J. (2002). How sex changed: A history of transsexuality in the United States. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Namaste, V. K. (2000). Invisible lives: The erasure of transsexual and transgendered people. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prosser, J. (2004). Light in the dark room: Photography and loss. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rodemeyer, L. (2008). ‘I don’t have the words’: Considering language (and the lack thereof) through the phenomenological paradigms of temporality and corporeality. In P. Mattens (Ed.), Meaning and language: Phenomenological perspectives (Phaenomenologica 187, pp. 195–212). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rodemeyer, L. (2014). Feminism, phenomenology, and hormones. In K. Zeiler & L. Käll (Eds.), Feminist phenomenology and medicine (pp. 183–199). Albany: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Salamon, G. (2010). Assuming a body: Transgender and rhetorics of materiality. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Valentine, D. (2007). Imagining transgender: An ethnography of a category. Durham: Duke University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wilchins, R. A. (2006). What does it cost to tell the truth? In S. Stryker & S. Whittle (Eds.), The transgender studies reader (pp. 547–551). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2018 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Rodemeyer, L.M. (2018). A Phenomenology of Embodiment. In: Lou Sullivan Diaries (1970-1980) and Theories of Sexual Embodiment. Crossroads of Knowledge. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-63034-2_6

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-63034-2_6

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-63033-5

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-63034-2

  • eBook Packages: Social SciencesSocial Sciences (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics