Skip to main content

The Self-Generation of Models

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Introduction to Anticipation Studies

Part of the book series: Anticipation Science ((ANTISC,volume 1))

  • 542 Accesses

Abstract

One major issue remains unaddressed in the picture so far presented. While I have cited extensive scientific experience on how to deal with the encoding and decoding between natural and formal systems (what amounts to most of contemporary science), and I have briefly mentioned the encoding and decoding between formal systems (through functors), still largely unaddressed is the question of encoding and decoding between natural systems. What are the conditions for one natural system to behave as a model of another natural system? To gain an initial grasp of the profound importance of encoding and decoding between natural systems, consider the capacity of an organism to navigate in its environment, e.g. through its perceptions. The organism’s percepts work as models of the environment (and of the perceiving system as well). In this regard, two major options compete. They may be called the ‘representational’ and the ‘presentational’ perspectives. The former is the mainstream position adopted by most practitioners of cognitive science, and it branches into many other fields, including computer science and the social sciences. The main problem for the representational position is explaining the origin of the modeling capacity of the representational system. The alternative position – called ‘presentational’ – introduces two divides. The first is the distinction between the processes pertaining to the mind and the processes of the brain that underlie, make possible, or bear mental processes. The second divide is between first-level and higher-order cognitive processes. From the point of view of the perceptor, the former are naturally endowed with meaning since their first appearances whilst the latter are higher-order re-codifications of the formers’ outcomes. The difference between first-level and higher-order cognitive processes depends on processes unfolding in the ‘time of presentness’, also known as ‘specious present’ or ‘moment now’, and processes unfolding in wider temporal windows.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Hartmann (1935, 1940). Strictly speaking, Hartmann was not a pupil of Brentano and pertains more to the phenomenological movement at large than to the School of Brentano. See Spiegelberg (1984). On Hartmann see Werkmeister (1990), Poli (2012), Poli, Scognamiglio, and Tremblay (2011), Poli (2012), Cicovacki (2014), Peterson and Poli (2016).

  2. 2.

    Visual perceptions require a slightly different wording. See Albertazzi (2003).

References

  • Albertazzi, L. (2001). Vittorio Benussi (1878–1927). In L. Albertazzi, D. Jacquette, & R. Poli (Eds.), The school of Alexius Meinong (pp. 95–129). Aldershot, UK: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Albertazzi, L. (2003). From Kanizsa back to Benussi: Varieties of intentional reference. Axiomathes, 13(3–4), 239–259.

    Google Scholar 

  • Albertazzi, L. (2006). Immanent realism. Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Albertazzi, L. (2015). A science of qualities. Biological Theory, 10, 188. doi:10.1007/s13752-015-0213-3

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Albertazzi, L. (Ed.). (2013). Handbook of experimental phenomenology. Visual perception of shape, space and appearance. Chichester, UK: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Albertazzi, L., Canal, L., Dadam, J., & Micciolo, R. (2014). The semantics of biological forms. Perception, 43(12), 1365–1376.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Albertazzi, L., Da Pos, O., Canal, L., Micciolo, R., Malfatti, M., & Vescovi, M. (2012). The hue of shapes. Journal of Experimental Psychology: Human Perception and Performance, 39(1), 37–47. doi:10.1037/a0028816

    Google Scholar 

  • Albertazzi, L., Jacquette, D., & Poli, R. (Eds.). (2001). The school of Alexius Meinong. Aldershot, UK: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Albertazzi, L., & Louie, A. H. (2016). A mathematical science of qualities: A sequel. Biological Theory, 11, 192. doi:10.1007/s13752-016-0248-0

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Albertazzi, L., & Poli, R. (2014). Multi-leveled objects: Color as a case study. Frontiers in Psychology, 5(592). doi:10.3389/fpsyg.2014.00592

  • Albertazzi, L., Visvanath, D., & Van Tonder, G. (Eds.). (2010). Perception beyond inference. The information content of visual processes. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bateson, G. (1972). Steps to an ecology of mind. Northvale, NJ: Jason Aronson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benussi, V. (1927). La suggestione e l’ipnosi come mezzi di analisi psichica reale. Bologna, Italy: Zanichelli.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard, M. H. (2009). The interactivist model. Synthese, 166(3), 547–591.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard, M. H. (2015a). Toward a model of functional brain processes I: Central nervous system functional micro-architecture. Axiomathes, 22(3), 217–238.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard, M. H. (2015b). Toward a model of functional brain processes II: Central nervous system functional macro-architecture. Axiomathes, 22(4), 377–407.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bickhard, M. H., & Terveen, L. (1995). Foundational issues in artificial intelligence and cognitive science. Impasse and solution. Amsterdam, The Netherlands: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, D. T. (1958). Common fate, similarity, and other indices of the status of aggregates of persons as social entities. Behavioral Science, 3(1), 14–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cicovacki, P. (2014). The analysis of wonder: An introduction to the philosophy of Nicolai Hartmann. New York: Bloomsbury.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hartmann, N. (1935). Zur Grundlegung der Ontologie. Berlin, Germany: De Gruyter.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hartmann, N. (1940). Der Aufbau der realen Welt. Grundriss der allgemeinen Kategorienlehre. Berlin, Germany: De Gruyter.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kubovy, M., & Wagemans, J. (1995). Grouping by proximity and multistability in dot lattices: A quantitative gestalt theory. Psychological Science, 6(4), 225–234.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lofgren, L. (1968). An axiomatic explanation of complete self-reproduction. Bulletin of Mathematical Biophysics, 30, 415–425.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luhmann, N. (1995). Social systems. Stanford, CL: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Metzger, W. (1966). Allgemeine Psychologie. Goettingen, Germany: Verlag fuer Psychology Hogrefe.

    Google Scholar 

  • Musatti, C. (1964). Condizioni dell’esperienza e fondazione della psicologia. Firenze, Italy: Editrice Universitaria.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peterson, K., & Poli, R. (Eds.). (2016). New research on the philosophy of Nicolai Hartmann. Berlin, Germany: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pinna, B., & Albertazzi, L. (2010). From grouping to visual meaning: A new theory of perceptual organization. In L. Albertazzi, G. van Tonder, & D. Vishwanath (Eds.), Perception beyond inference. The information content of perceptual processes (pp. 287–344). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poli, R. (1996). In itinere. Pictures from Central-European Philosophy. Poznan Studies in the Philosophy of the Sciences and the Humanities, 53, 11–32.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poli, R. (1999). The concept of empirical reality between logic and psychology: The proposals of the young Musatti. Axiomathes, (1–3), 125–160.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poli, R. (2006a). Levels of reality and the psychological stratum. Revue Internationale de Philosophie, 61(2), 163–180.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poli, R. (2006b). Value wholes. In W. Strawinski, M. Grygianiec, & A. Brozek (Eds.), Mysli o jezyku, nauce i wartosciach (pp. 371–385). Warszawa, Poland: Wiedza powszechna.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poli, R. (2010). The structure of motivation. A first introduction. In R. Poli (Ed.), Causality and motivation (pp. 7–22). Heusenstamm, Germany: Ontos Verlag.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Poli, R. (2012). Nicolai Hartmann. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. (Fall 2012 Edition).

    Google Scholar 

  • Poli, R. (Ed.). (1998). The Brentano puzzle. Aldershot, UK: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poli, R., Scognamiglio, C., & Tremblay, F. (Eds.). (2011). The philosophy of Nicolai Hartmann. Berlin, Germany: De Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, R. (1991). Life itself. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, R. (2012). Anticipatory systems. Philosophical, mathematical, and methodological foundations (2nd ed.). New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spiegelberg, H. (1984). The phenomenological movement (3rd revised and enlarged edition ed.). The Hague, The Netherlands: Nijhoff.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thinès, G. (1977). Phenomenology and the science of behaviour. A historical and epistemological approach. London: Allen and Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Werkmeister, W. (1990). Nicolai Hartmann’s new ontology. Tallahassee, FL: Florida State University.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Poli, R. (2017). The Self-Generation of Models. In: Introduction to Anticipation Studies. Anticipation Science, vol 1. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-63023-6_13

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics