Skip to main content

Not Everything in Scientific Cognition Is Evidence-Based

The Epistemology of Evidentially Inert Knowledge Enhancing

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 391 Accesses

Part of the book series: Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics ((SAPERE,volume 37))

Abstract

Peirce provides various justifications of the knowledge enhancing role of abduction, even when abduction is not considered an inference to the best explanation in the classical sense of the expression, that is an inference necessarily characterized by an empirical evaluation phase, or inductive phase.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   79.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    That is not inferences to the best explanation in the classical sense of the expression, involving an empirical evaluation phase.

  2. 2.

    Poincaré says that these principles are “deduced” from experimental truths, but it is unlikely to think of them as fruit of deduction instead of abduction. I think that the use of the word deduction is just a way adopted by Poincaré to refer to a generic kind of scientific inference.

  3. 3.

    Computer and AI scientists have suggested an interesting technique for negating hypotheses and accessing new ones: negation as failure (Clark 1978). I consider this kind of logical account of negation, studied by researchers into logic programming, to be very important also from the epistemological point of view. Negation as failure is active as a “rational” process of withdrawing previously-abduced hypotheses in everyday life, but also in certain subtle kinds of diagnostic (analytic interpretations in psychoanalysis—cf. Chap. 4, Sect. 4.2, this book) and other epistemological settings. Contrasted with classical negation, with the double negation of intuitionistic logic, and with the philosophical concept of Aufhebung (Toth 1991), negation as failure shows how a subject can decide to withdraw her hypotheses, while maintaining the “rationality” of her argumentations, in contexts where it is impossible to find contradictions or falsifications. Negation as failure in query evaluation process for a logical database is more extensively illustrated in (Magnani 2009, Chap. 2).

  4. 4.

    Please keep in mind I am making an analogy between “not provable” and “not empirically fecund”.

  5. 5.

    See Chap. 1, footnote 14.

  6. 6.

    I have firstly introduced the problem of epistemological fictionalism in the previous chapter.

  7. 7.

    In this last sense the capacity of scientific models to constitute new empirical domains and so new empirical knowability is ideally related to the emphasis that epistemology, in the last century, put on the theory-ladenness of scientific facts (Hanson, Popper, Lakatos, Kuhn): in this light, the formulation of observation statements presupposes significant knowledge, and the search for new observability in science is guided by scientific modeling.

  8. 8.

    It has to be added that Suárez does not conflate scientific modeling with literary fictionalizing. He distinguishes scientific fictions from other kinds of fictions—the scientific ones are constrained by both the logic of inference and, in particular, the requirement to fit in with the empirical domain (Suárez 2009, 2010)—in the framework of an envisaged compatibility of “scientific fiction” with realism. This epistemological acknowledgment is not often present in other followers of fictionalism.

  9. 9.

    I discussed the role of chance-seeking in scientific discovery in (Magnani 2007).

  10. 10.

    Which, by the way, is the key topic of epistemology at least since Karl Popper and Thomas Kuhn.

  11. 11.

    It is worth mentioning that the metaphor of “detonation” originated as a characterization of what happens when in an inconsistent theory ex falso is true. “Detonation” is also a catching play on the words of Russell’s famous 1905 paper “On denoting”, published in Mind. The phrase derives from Schotch and Jennings’ contribution to the paraconsistency volume of 1989, edited by Priest, Routley and Norman, as a paper entitled “On detonating” (Schotch and Jennings 1989). The point they were making (quite rightly) is that if ex falso is true then negation detonates in inconsistent theories; their every sentence has a validly derivable negation. In Woods’ appropriation of it in the passages I am quoting, the property that detonates is the property of being fictional.

  12. 12.

    On the related problem of resemblance (similarity, isomorphism, homomorphism, etc.) in scientific modeling see Chap. 4, this book.

  13. 13.

    In this eco-cognitive perspective we can even more strongly agree with Morrison’s when she is pretty clear about the excessive habit of labeling fictional scientific models simply because they are superficially seen as “unrealistic”: “Although there is a temptation to categorize any type of unrealistic representation as a ‘fiction’, I have argued that this would be a mistake, primarily because this way of categorizing the use of unrealistic representations tells us very little about the role those representations play in producing knowledge” (Morrison 2009, p. 133).

  14. 14.

    Cf. above, Chap. 1, Sect. 1.3, this book.

  15. 15.

    Cf. also p. 38, Sect. 2.3 of the previous chapter of this book.

  16. 16.

    The reason of my skepticism about the vision of models in terms of the pretence theory can be illustrated taking advantage of some classical but still astounding theses derived from Kantian philosophy and Thom’s mathematical semiophysics, I will treat in the following chapter, Sect. 4.2.

References

  • Clark, K. L. (1978). Negation as failure. In Gallaire, H. and Minker, J., editors, Logic and Data Bases, pages 94–114. Plenum, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coopersmith, J. (2010). Energy, the Subtle Concept: The Discovery of Feynman’s Blocks from Leibniz to Einstein. Oxford University Press, Oxford/New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frigg, R. (2010). Models and fiction. Synthese, 172:251–268.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gabbay, D. M. and Woods, J. (2005). The Reach of Abduction. North-Holland, Amsterdam.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giedymin, J. (1982). Science and Convention. Essays on Henri Poincaré’s Philosophy of Science and the Conventionalist Tradition. Pergamon Press, Oxford.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka, J. (2007). Socratic Epistemology. Explorations of Knowledge-Seeking by Questioning. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lakatos, I. (1970). Falsification and the methodology of scientific research programs. In Lakatos, I. and Musgrave, A., editors, Criticism and the Growth of Knowledge, pages 365–395. The MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnani, L. (2001). Abduction, Reason, and Science. Processes of Discovery and Explanation. Kluwer Academic/Plenum Publishers, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnani, L. (2007). Abduction and chance discovery in science. International Journal of Knowledge-Based and Intelligent Engineering, 11:273–279.

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnani, L. (2009). Abductive Cognition. The Epistemological and Eco-Cognitive Dimensions of Hypothetical Reasoning. Springer, Heidelberg/Berlin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morrison, M. (2009). Fictions, representations, and reality. In Suárez, M., editor, Fictions in Science: Philosophical Essays on Modeling and Idealization, pages 110–135. Routledge, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poincaré, H. (1902). La science et l’hypothèse. Flammarion, Paris. English translation by W. J. G. [only initials indicated], 1958, Science and Hypothesis, with a Preface by J. Larmor, The Walter Scott Publishing Co., New York, 1905. Also reprinted in Essential Writings of Henri Poincaré, Random House, New York, 2001.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poincaré, H. (1905). La valeur de la science. Flammarion, Paris. English translation by G.B. Halsted, 1958, The Value of Science, Dover Publications, New York). Also reprinted in Essential Writings of Henri Poincaré, Random House, New York, 2001.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (1959). The Logic of Scientific Discovery. Hutchinson, London, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (1963). Conjectures and Refutations. The Growth of Scientific Knowledge. Routledge and Kegan Paul, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schotch, P. K. and Jennings, R. E. (1989). On detonation. In Priest, G., Routley, R., and Norman, J., editors, Paraconsistent Logic. Essays on the Inconsistency, pages 326–327. Philosophia Verlag, München.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suárez, M. (2009). Scientific fictions as rules of inference. In Suárez, M., editor, Fictions in Science: Philosophical Essays on Modeling and Idealization, pages 158–178. Routledge, London.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suárez, M. (2010). Fictions, inference, and realism. In Woods, J., editor, Fictions and Models: New Essays, pages 225–245. Philosophia Verlag, Munich.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toth, I. (1991). Essere e non essere: il teorema induttivo di Saccheri e la sua rilevanza ontologica. In Magnani, L., editor, Conoscenza e Matematica, pages 87–156. Marcos y Marcos, Milan. Translated from German by A. Marini.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woods, J. (2013). Against fictionalism. In Magnani, L., editor, Model-Based Reasoning in Science and Technology. Theoretical and Cognitive Issues, pages 9–42. Springer, Heidelberg/Berlin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woods, J. and Rosales, A. (2010). Unifying the fictional. In Woods, J., editor, Fictions and Models: New Essays, pages 345–388. Philosophia Verlag, Munich.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Lorenzo Magnani .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Magnani, L. (2017). Not Everything in Scientific Cognition Is Evidence-Based. In: The Abductive Structure of Scientific Creativity. Studies in Applied Philosophy, Epistemology and Rational Ethics, vol 37. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-59256-5_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics