Skip to main content

Notes on Revisiting Klappholz and Agassi’s “Methodological Prescriptions in Economics”

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Encouraging Openness

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science ((BSPS,volume 325))

  • 329 Accesses

Abstract

I reconsider the paper ‘Methodological Prescriptions in Economics’, Economica, February 1959, by Kurt Klappholz and Joseph Agassi. I criticise the thesis that “there is only one generally applicable methodological rule, and that is the exhortation to be critical […].” I compare the methodology of physics with that of economics, and discuss whether typical economic ‘laws’ are testable hypotheses. I consider whether an approach to economic policy based on welfare economics is biassed. In conclusion, I sketch an approach to economic methodology and suggest some rules of method that may be useful to the working economist.

I am indebted for comments on an earlier draft to Adam Ostaszewski , Sven Rady, Jörn Rothe and Carol Foldes (Carol Hewlett).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 119.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Agassi (1993) pp. 170–171. The passage quoted is repeated with unimportant changes at p. 212 in Agassi (2008).

  2. 2.

    In this connection it is amusing to recall Poincaré’s discussion (Poincaré 1905, Ch. IX) of Carlyle’s statement (Past and Present, Ch. 1, book II) that ‘Nothing but facts are of importance. John Lackland passed by here. Here is something that is admirable. Here is a reality for which I would give all the theories in the world.’ Poincaré comments that ‘this is the language of the historian. The physicist (Bacon) would most likely have said ‘John Lackland passed by here. It is all the same to me, for he will not pass this way again.’’ Where does the economist stand on this? Maybe King John’s journey was the one on which he lost his treasure in The Wash, in which case it would be relevant to the economic history of England, and its effect on the money supply might call for discussion. On the other hand this unique event is hardly of significance for the validity of any law of economics.

  3. 3.

    However, one apparent error should be noted. K&A assert (p. 61) that ‘a law, to be true, must correctly refer to all the relevant factors (affecting its validity), which must of course be finite in number (since otherwise we could not mention them all).’ This runs counter to the common practice of lumping together in an ‘error’ term a set (possibly infinite) of ‘small’ factors which are assumed collectively to follow a particular statistical distribution. More generally, I am rather persuaded by a remark of Imre Lakatos (made in connection with mathematical theorems) that there is always an infinite number of ‘hidden lemmas’. Be that as it may, I leave the reader to whet his critical teeth on this one.

  4. 4.

    Robbins (1945), p. 78–79. To quote Poincaré again, (Poincaré 1902, Ch.IX): ‘L’expérience est la source unique de le verité: elle seule peut nous apprendre quelque chose de nouveau; elle seule peut nous donner la certitude. Voilà deux points que nul ne peut contester.’ Leaving aside whether this assertion is really incontestable, the reason for quoting it in French is that ‘expérience’ can mean either ‘experiment’ or ‘experience’. Given the physical context, the English translation naturally chooses the former rendering. However the quotation from Robbins suggests that, in economics at least, the wider concept is more appropriate for deciding the acceptability of a law.

  5. 5.

    ‘The law of demand is to the effect that the utility afforded by any increment of any kind of desired object diminishes with increase of the amount possessed’, W.E.Johnson in Palgrave’s Dictionary of Political Economy, quoted in J. N. Keynes (1917), p. 245. Johnson regards this ‘law’ as a psychological datum rather than as a theorem of economics.

  6. 6.

    The possibility that the income effects may outweigh the substitution effect, so that demand increases with price, is often presented as paradoxical, but it may be quite natural for some ‘commodities’, e.g. saving or leisure. Thus saving (=demand for future goods) may well fall as the rate of interest rises. Again, demand for leisure (=hours not worked) may well increase if the wage rate (opportunity cost of idleness) falls, i.e. if the supply curve of labour is downward sloping.

  7. 7.

    This procedure may be regarded as comparable to the usual interpretation of the results of an experiment which seems to violate the law of conservation of energy, cf. Poincaré (1905), esp. pp. 185 and 159–160, also the articles “Poincaré” and “conventialism” in the Oxford Companion to Philosophy.

  8. 8.

    For a brief survey , see J. N. Keynes (1917), Ch. I.

  9. 9.

    Compare the discussion by Poincaré (1905), p. 160.

References

  • Agassi, Joseph. 1993. A philosopher’s apprentice: In Karl Popper’s workshop, 1st ed. Amsterdam/Atlanta: Editions Rodopi B.V.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2008. A philosopher's apprentice: In Karl Popper's workshop, 2nd edition. Amsterdam/New York: Editions Rodopi B.V.

    Google Scholar 

  • De Finetti, Bruno. 1937. La prévision: ses lois logiques, ses sources subjectifs. Annales de l’Institut Henri Poincaré 7 (1): 1–68.

    Google Scholar 

  • Honderich, Ted, ed. 1995. Oxford companion to philosophy. Oxford: OUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keynes, J.N. 1917. The Scope and Method of Political Economy. 4th ed. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klappholz, Kurt, and Joseph Agassi. 1959. Methodological prescriptions in economics. Economica XXVI (101): 60–74.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Poincaré, Henri. 1902. La Science et l’Hypothèse. Editions Ebooks libres et gratuits.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1905. Science and hypothesis. London/Newcastle-on-Tyne: Walter Scott Publishing Co, Ltd. Project Gutenberg EBook.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K.R. 1959. The logic of scientific discovery. London: Hutchinson.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1963. Conjectures and refutations. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Robbins, Lionel. 1945. An essay on the nature and significance of economic science. 2nd ed. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Lucien Foldes .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Foldes, L. (2017). Notes on Revisiting Klappholz and Agassi’s “Methodological Prescriptions in Economics”. In: Bar-Am, N., Gattei, S. (eds) Encouraging Openness. Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science, vol 325. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-57669-5_36

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics