Skip to main content

Ambivalence of Power: Heidegger’s das Man and Arendt’s Acting in Concert

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Part of the book series: Studies in the Philosophy of Sociality ((SIPS,volume 10))

Abstract

This essay analyses how Arendt transforms Heidegger’s critique of the anyone (das Man) in Being and Time into the philosophical concept of power as acting in concert in The Human Condition. The essay highlights the similarities as well as the differences of both concepts by focusing on their inherent ambivalences. In Heidegger’s critique of das Man, this ambivalence derives from the combination of an existential and a historical perspective, which turn social life into both a condition for and a fallenness from authentic existence. Arendt aims to overcome this ambiguity with her concept of Acting in Concert as a condition for political empowerment, freedom and new beginning. In her Denktagebuch, the emphasis on beginning as an event is inspired by a heterodox reading of Heidegger’s mature thought. But despite Arendt’s attempt to overcome the negative aspects of das Man as a form of conventionalism by stressing instead the elements of plurality and freedom, the ambivalence of Heidegger’s das Man reappears in Arendt’s concept of acting in concert the very moment it is identified as political, i. e. democratic, power. It is the necessity of gaining majorities that expose democratic interactions to the threat of conformism. Turning Arendt against Heidegger and Heidegger against Arendt, this essay offers an understanding of democracy that encompasses this ambivalence of das Man.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The references to Heidegger’s Being and Time are based on the translation by John Macquarrie and Edward Robinson (Heidegger 1962), which renders the German expression das Man as “the they”. However, in order to draw attention to the specific meaning of Heidegger‘s expression, the original term das Man will be kept in this text.

  2. 2.

    See the note in the text “The image of Hell”, from 1946, stating that Heidegger made the Nazism openly respectable in the elite of German universities (Arendt 1994, 202).

  3. 3.

    All notes are accessible via http://www.bard.edu/arendtcollection/marginalia.htm, weblinks accessed 9th June 2015.

  4. 4.

    In her lecture “Concern with Politics”, Arendt states that Heidegger’s concept of the world “constitutes a step out of this difficulty”, and she thereby alludes to the problem of philosophical solipsism (Arendt 1994, 443).

  5. 5.

    Kisiel (1993, 386) refers on Heidegger’s lecture “Logic” from 1925/26, where Heidegger developed his concept of solicitude in its authentic and inauthentic forms, and insinuates that Heidegger might have had his student Hannah Arendt in mind: „Such a solicitude treats the other (Let us call her ‚Johanna A.’: it was her last semester in Marburg) as a nothing vis-à-vis her Dasein.“

  6. 6.

    See Arendt‘s letter to her doctoral student Calvin Schrag from 31 December 1955, cited in (Grunenberg 2006, 267): „I have to warn you about my essay about existentialism, particularly about the part concerning Heidegger which is not only inappropriate, but simply wrong in some parts. Please just forget about this.“ (translation S.B.)

  7. 7.

    However, Arendt’s thesis that labor means the satisfaction of natural needs, which do not, in contrast to technical-artistic work and practical-political „action“, individualise or socialise people, is highly problematic. Ultimately, this thesis undermines Arendt’s own critique of the identification of freedom with sovereignty because she qualifies forms of dependence on needs in the household as unfreedom (Meyer 2011).

  8. 8.

    The term natality as a metaphor for the beginning was influenced centrally by Augustinus; see Arendt (1998, 177) about Augustinus: „that there be a beginning, man was created“. This motif has already been present in Arendt’s dissertation; also see (Arendt 2002, 66).

  9. 9.

    My thoughts are mostly based on the quote above from Denktagebuch. However, it would be possible to suggest a different reading of the beginning by refering to other statements: „Acting (politically): a) Deed: Distinction of a single individual before all others. b) Acting in concert: Power and the beginning of something (archein) that needs the help of others (prattein) in order to be accomplished” (Arendt 2002, 548; translation S.B.; archein and prattein in Greek letters). Margaret Canovan (1992, 136) shows that in a lecture manuscript Arendt defines the beginning as a power limited to the king. There, Arendt associates the heroical act of beginning with the Homeric era. This elitarian notion of the beginning can still be seen in The Human Condition, where Arendt defines power as a fragile relation between the one who starts alone and the many who accomplish something together (Arendt 1998, 189) (see also below Sect. 9.5 for these incoherences).

  10. 10.

    Thus Arendt states in May 1951 that plurality “has been standing in the way of the human ever since Plato (and up until Heidegger) in the sense that it does not want him to keep his sovereignty”. (Arendt 2002, 80; translation S.B.)

  11. 11.

    “Das Selbe ist nicht das Einerlei des Gleichen, sondern das Einzige im Verschiedenen und das verborgene Nahe im Fremden” (Arendt 2002, 65).

  12. 12.

    “Von hier aus wäre ein neuer Gleichheitsbegriff zu entwickeln, der den Schrecken, die ursprüngliche Angst vor der Menschheit sowohl wie die Notwendigkeit ihrer bewahren könnte. Wir können uns mit der Nähe (dem Gemeinsamen) nur abfinden, weil sie im Fremden verborgen ist und als Fremdes sich präsentiert. Wir können uns mit dem Fremden nur abfinden, weil es Nahes verbirgt, Gemeinsames ankündigt.” (Arendt 2002, 65)

  13. 13.

    See Arendt’s note from January 1951: “Heidegger was wrong in Being and Time: The voice of the conscience is precisely ‘the Man’ on the peak of its domination. Thus the ‘conscience’ could be used very well by the Nazis or anyone else” (Arendt 2002, 181, translation S.B.).

  14. 14.

    Heidegger follows the tradition of Nietzsche in thinking power only in extreme and opposing relations of superior power and powerlessness. Thus, his description of the authentic Dasein is a description of continuous turns in which powerlessness and superior power alternate. See Heidegger’s conclusion in Being and Time: Only if Dasein “lets death become powerful in itself” and recognises its own “powerlessness”, it “understands itself in its own superior power, the power of its finite freedom” (BT 384).

References

  • Arendt, H. (1951). The origins of totalitarianism. New York: Harcourt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, H. (1970). On violence. New York: Harcourt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, H. (1973). Men in dark times. Harmondsworth: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, H. (1978a). The life of the mind (Vol. 2 vol). New York: Harcourt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, H. (1978b). Martin Heidegger at eighty. [1971]. In M. Murray (Ed.), Heidegger and modern philosophy. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, H. (1994). In J. Kohn (Ed.), Essays in understanding 1930–1954. New York/San Diego/London: Harcourt Brace & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, H. (1996). In J. V. Scott & J. C. Stark (Eds.), Love and Saint Augustine [1929]. Chicago/London: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, H. (1998). The human condition [1958] (2nd ed.). Chicago/London: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, H. (2002). Denktagebuch. 1950–1973 (U. Ludz & I. Nordmann, Eds., 2 Vol.). München/Zürich: Piper.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, H. (2006). On revolution [1963]. New York: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arendt, H., & Heidegger, M. (2004). Letters 1925–1975 (U.Ludz, Ed., A. Shields, Trans.). Orlando: Harcourt, Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barash, J. A. (1996). The political dimension of the public world: On hannah arendts’ interpretation of Martin Heidegger. In L. May & J. Kohn (Eds.), Hannah arendt: Twenty years later (pp. 251–268). Cambridge/London: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benhabib, S. (1992). Models of public space. In Situating the self. Gender, community and postmodernism in contemporary ethics (pp. 89–120). Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benhabib, S. (1996). The reluctant modernism of Hannah Arendt. Thousands Oaks: Sage Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Canovan, M. (1992). Hannah Arendt: A reinterpretation of her political thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Grunenberg, A. (2006). Hannah Arendt und Martin Heidegger. Geschichte einer Liebe. München/Zürich: Piper.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1962). Being and time. (J. Macquarrie & E. Robinson, Trans.). San Francisco: Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, M. (1990). Vorträge und Aufsätze. Pfullingen: Günther Neske.

    Google Scholar 

  • Honig, B. (1992). Toward an agonistic feminism. Hannah Arendt and the politics of identity. In J. Butler & J. W. Scott (Eds.), Feminists theorize the political (pp. 215–238). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kisiel, T. (1993). The genesis of Heidegger’s being and time. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lukes, Steven. 2005. Power. A radical view [1974], 2nd. exp. edition. New York: Palgrave.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marchart, O. (2005). Neu beginnen. Hannah Arendt, die Revolution und die Globalisierung. Wien: Turia+Kant.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meyer, K. (2002). Die Kritik des souveränen Menschen und ihre Grenzen. Deutsche Zeitschrift für Philosophie, 52(3), 492–496.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meyer, K. (2011). Kritik der Postdemokratie. Rancière und Arendt über die Paradoxien von Macht und Gleichheit. Leviathan, 39, 21–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meyer, K. (2013). Ordnung jenseits von Souveränität. Arendts Verständnis demokratisch geteilter Macht. In J. S. Wessel, C. Volk, & S. Salzborn (Eds.), Ambivalenzen der Ordnung. Der Staat im Denken Hannah Arendts (pp. 235–257). Wiesbaden: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nancy, J.-L. (2000). Being singular plural. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Passerin d’Entrèves, M. (1994). The political philosophy of Hannah Arendt. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlapbach, K. (2014). ‚Under the full impact of a catastrophic end’ – Augustine and the fall of Rome in Hannah Arendt’s reading. In M. Formisano & T. Fuhrer (Eds.), Décadence. ‚Decline and Fall’ or ‚Other Antiquity’?, 97–112. Heidelberg: Universitätsverlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmid, H. B. (2005). Wir-Intentionalität. Kritik des ontologischen Individualismus und Rekonstruktion der Gemeinschaft. Freiburg: Alber.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taminiaux, J. (1997). The Thracian maid and the professional thinker. Arendt and Heidegger. New York: SUNY Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tocqueville, A. d. (1994). Democracy in America. London: Campbell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Villa, D. R. (1996). Arendt and Heidegger: The fate of the political. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Villa, D. (2008). Public freedom. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wolin, R. (2001). Heidegger’s Children: Hannah Arendt, Karl Löwith, Hans Jonas, and Herbert Marcuse. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Young-Bruehl, E. (1982). Hannah Arendt. For love of the world. New Haven: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I am grateful to Sophie Bürgi, Karin Schlapbach and the anonymous referee for their helpful comments on this text.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Katrin Meyer .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Meyer, K. (2017). Ambivalence of Power: Heidegger’s das Man and Arendt’s Acting in Concert . In: Schmid, H., Thonhauser, G. (eds) From Conventionalism to Social Authenticity. Studies in the Philosophy of Sociality, vol 10. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-56865-2_9

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics