Skip to main content

Four Approaches to the Reference Class Problem

  • Conference paper
  • First Online:
Making it Formally Explicit

Part of the book series: European Studies in Philosophy of Science ((ESPS,volume 6))

Abstract

We present and analyse four approaches to the reference class problem. First, we present a new objective Bayesian solution to the reference class problem. Second, we review Pollock’s combinatorial approach to the reference class problem. Third, we discuss a machine learning approach that is based on considering reference classes of individuals that are similar to the individual of interest. Fourth, we show how evidence of mechanisms, when combined with the objective Bayesian approach, can help to solve the reference class problem. We argue that this last approach is the most promising, and we note some positive aspects of the similarity approach.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The entropy of a probability function P defined on a set of logically independent propositions {E 1, , E n } is defined by \(-\sum \limits _{i=1}^{n}P(E_{i})\log P(E_{i})\).

  2. 2.

    See Wallmann and Kleiter (2014a,b) for a general procedure for generating the relevant optimization problem.

  3. 3.

    Let pe be a point. It is called peaking point with probability 1 iff for all δ > 0, PROB( | P (A | S) − pe | < δ) = 1, i.e., for all ε > 0, PROB( | P (A | S) − pe | < δ) > 1 −ε. If we think of δ being very small, for instance, 0. 000001, then this means that almost all subsets S are such that pe − 0. 000001 ≤ P (A | S) ≤ pe + 0. 000001. Note that probability 1 does not mean that there are no exceptions, i.e., even if PROB( | P (A | S) − pe | < δ) = 1, there are S such that | P (A | S) − pe | > δ. However, such S are comparably few.

  4. 4.

    For a related but more sophisticated similarity measure see Davis et al. (2010).

References

  • Benfante, R., K. Yano, L.-J. Hwang, J.D. Curb, A. Kagan, and W. Ross. 1994. Elevated serum cholesterol is a risk factor for both coronary heart disease and thromboembolic stroke in hawaiian Japanese men. Implications of shared risk. Stroke 25(4): 814–820.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clarke, B., D. Gillies, P. Illari, F. Russo, and J. Williamson. 2014. Mechanisms and the evidence hierarchy. Topoi 33(2): 339–360.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Davis, D.A., N.V. Chawla, N.A. Christakis, and A.-L. Barabási. 2010. Time to care: A collaborative engine for practical disease prediction. Data Mining and Knowledge Discovery 20(3): 388–415.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gower, J.C. 1971. A general coefficient of similarity and some of its properties. Biometrics 27(4): 857–871.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haybittle, J., R. Blamey, C. Elston, J. Johnson, P. Doyle, F. Campbell, R. Nicholson, and K. Griffiths. 1982. A prognostic index in primary breast cancer. British Journal of Cancer 45(3): 361.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hosseinpoor, A.R., L.A. Parker, E.T. d’Espaignet, and S. Chatterji. 2011. Social determinants of smoking in low-and middle-income countries: Results from the world health survey. PLoS One 6(5): e20331.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Illari, P.M., and J. Williamson. 2012. What is a mechanism? Thinking about mechanisms across the sciences. European Journal for Philosophy of Science 2: 119–135.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jaynes, E.T. 1957. Information theory and statistical mechanics. The Physical Review 106(4): 620–630.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jerez, J.M., I. Molina, P.J. García-Laencina, E. Alba, N. Ribelles, M. Martín, and L. Franco. 2010. Missing data imputation using statistical and machine learning methods in a real breast cancer problem. Artificial intelligence in medicine 50(2): 105–115.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Landes, J., and J. Williamson. (2016). Objective Bayesian nets from consistent datasets. In Proceedings of the 35th International Workshop on Bayesian Inference and Maximum Entropy Methods in Science and Engineering, ed. A. Giffin, and K.H. Knuth, vol. 1757. American Institute of Physics Conference Proceedings, Potsdam

    Google Scholar 

  • Mozaffarian, D., E.J. Benjamin, A.S. Go, D.K. Arnett, M.J. Blaha, M. Cushman, S. de Ferranti, J.-P. Despres, H.J. Fullerton, V.J. Howard, et al. 2015. Heart disease and stroke statistics-2015 update. A report from the American Heart Association. Circulation 131(4): E29–E322.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parkkinen, V.-P., and J. Williamson. 2017. Extrapolating from model organisms in pharmacology. In Uncertainty in pharmacology: Epistemology, methods, and decisions, ed. B. Osimani. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pearl, J. 1988. Probabilistic reasoning in intelligent systems: Networks of plausible inference. San Mateo: Morgan Kaufmann.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pollock, J.L. 2011. Reasoning defeasibly about probabilities. Synthese 181(2): 317–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pollock, J.L. 2016. LISP code for OSCAR. http://johnpollock.us/ftp/OSCAR-web-page/oscar.html. Accessed 19 Sept 2016.

  • Russo, F., and J. Williamson 2007. Interpreting causality in the health sciences. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 21(2): 157–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shinton, R., and G. Beevers. 1989. Meta-analysis of relation between cigarette smoking and stroke. BMJ 298(6676): 789–794.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Statistik, Austria. 2016. Smoking statistics in Austria 2014. http://www.statistik.at/web_de/statistiken/menschen_und_gesellschaft/gesundheit/gesundheitsdeterminanten/rauchen/index.html. Accessed 28 Sept 2016.

  • Steel, D. 2008. Across the boundaries: Extrapolation in biology and social science. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Venn, J. 1888. The logic of chance, 3rd ed. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallmann, C. 2017. A Bayesian solution to the conflict of narrowness and precision in direct inference. Journal for General Philosophy of Science.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallmann, C., and G.D. Kleiter 2014a. Degradation in probability logic: When more information leads to less precise conclusions. Kybernetika 50(2): 268–283.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wallmann, C., and G.D. Kleiter 2014b. Probability propagation in generalized inference forms. Studia Logica 102(4): 913–929.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wang, X., Y. Dong, X. Qi, C. Huang, and L. Hou. 2013. Cholesterol levels and risk of hemorrhagic stroke. A systematic review and meta-analysis. Stroke 44(7): 1833–1839.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wannamethee, S.G., A.G. Shaper, and S. Ebrahim. 2000. HDL-cholesterol, total cholesterol, and the risk of stroke in middle-aged British men. Stroke 31(8): 1882–1888.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, J. 2005a. Bayesian nets and causality: Philosophical and computational foundations. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, J. 2005b. Objective Bayesian nets. In We will show them! essays in Honour of Dov Gabbay, ed. S. Artemov, H. Barringer, A.S. d’Avila Garcez, L.C. Lamb, and J. Woods, vol. 2, 713–730. London: College Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, J. 2010. In defence of objective Bayesianism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, J. 2013. Why frequentists and Bayesians need each other. Erkenntnis 78(2): 293–318.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, J. 2017a. Lectures on inductive logic. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, J. 2017b. Models in systems medicine. Disputatio. In press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The research for this paper has been funded by the Arts and Humanities Research Council via grant AH/M005917/1.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Christian Wallmann .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this paper

Cite this paper

Wallmann, C., Williamson, J. (2017). Four Approaches to the Reference Class Problem. In: Hofer-Szabó, G., Wroński, L. (eds) Making it Formally Explicit. European Studies in Philosophy of Science, vol 6. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-55486-0_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics