Skip to main content

The Nature of Economics

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 1169 Accesses

Part of the book series: Contributions to Economics ((CE))

Abstract

Unrealisticness is one of the key challenges to Neoclassical Uncertainty Paradigm. In this chapter I discuss the Critique Realist’s approach to uncertainty. I begin by clarifying the meaning of critical Realism and argue that it is not about realisticness per se. Instead, Critical Realism aims at understanding the problem of phenomenon under study, by analysing its ontological structure. Based on these ontological analyses, methods appropriate to the problem need to be identified. Therefore, the Critical Realists Approach of uncertainty begins with an ontological analysis of the structure of economic reality. It is argued that the economy has to be understood as an open and complex system with emergent properties, which is structured and in which demi-regularities can be identified. Furthermore, economic reality is mutable, so that the degree of uncertainty, which originates from the ontological structure of economic reality, may be different in any two economic situations. From my point of view four stages of uncertainty, which vary in their degree of uncertainty, can be differentiated. Though Critical realism allows for this, compared to neoclassical economics rather detailed analysis of economic reality, it also gives no sufficient answer to the question, of how economic analysis should proceed in the face of Fundamental Uncertainty, which is according to Critical Realism the standard case in economics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Realism has many different faces in economic and the many faces of realism are now emerging within the methodological literature Hands (2001: 53). Boylan and O’Gorman (1995: 89–93) list four stereotypes of scientific realism thought to be broadly acceptable to those who regard themselves as scientific realists: “(1) The minimum criterion is that the statements of a theory are (or may be) either true or false (contrary to instrumentalism). (2) Furthermore, the statements have to be true or false apart from ourselves that is that although a theorist creates such statements their truth or falsehood is independent of the mind that created them (contrary to relativism). (3) At the ontological level, this can be taken to mean the view that the world exists independently of us, that the world really is this way rather than that, and what we think or feel about it makes no difference (contrary to constructivism). (4) Moreover, it is possible to know what the independently existing objects and their properties in the world truly are (contrary to Kantian idealism). Thus in principle there is no impenetrable veil between such objects, even if they are not directly observable, and their access to the human mind. It is the task of science and the role of theory to discover more precisely what the objects and their essential properties are. The main differences between scientific realism and other philosophies of science concern the role of theories as regards description, prediction and explanation. A theory may do all three things but an empiricist’s basic instinct is to describe, an instrumentalist’s is to predict and the scientific realist’s is to explain.” E.g.: Mäki (1998, 2012) and Hands (2001).

  2. 2.

    E.g.: Dow (2012: 14): “Faced with uncertainty, however, economists have developed conventions as to how best to reduce it. The dominant convention, which has gained force over the last 50 years, is to build theory within a formal deductivist framework. This framework builds up formal deductivist models on the basis of axioms about optimising behaviour on the part of individual agents, where knowledge is held with certainty (or certainty equivalence) although specific knowledge may be concealed (asymmetric information). The theoretical system is closed in the sense that variables are classified as endogenous or exogenous. Endogenous variables interact in a predetermined way within a given structure, while exogenous variables are known to be random. There is no place for uncertainty in the form of unquantifiable risk. If addressed at all, uncertainty is understood as an impediment to rational choice.”

  3. 3.

    For Lawson (1997, 2003, 2004), a closed system is fully identified by the occurrence of event regularities. Conversely, openness is equated with an absence of event regularities. The latter, he argues, corresponds to reality as we know it.

  4. 4.

    In practice the endogeneity of variables is not always obvious. Van der Lecq argued (2000: 161), “[c]onfusingly, in [mainstream] economics the terms closed and open are applied to formal models. A model which consists of only endogenous variables is called a closed model, whereas a model in which exogenous variables are included in order to solve it, is called an open model. The term open model reflects the idea that the model would be indeterminate without information from outside […] In the terminology [of systems], both closed and open models are examples of a closed system approach.”

  5. 5.

    See also Loasby (2003), drawing on Potts (2000).

  6. 6.

    Chick (2004: 5) argues that the particular set of connections and absence of connection, “is what differentiates one system from another and gives them a sense of both character and order”, and concludes: “A system is a network, a structure with connections, within which agents act, mostly in ways which reproduce and reinforce the system, but sometimes in ways which lead the system to evolve.”

  7. 7.

    Lawson (2003: 79): “According to the concept I defend, social reality is open in a significant way. Patterns in events do occur. But where the phenomena being related are highly concrete (such as movements in actual prices, quantities of materials or outputs, and most of the other typical concerns of modern economic modellers), such patterns as are found tend to take the form of demi-regularities or demi-regs, that is, of regularities that are not only highly restricted but also somewhat partial and unstable.” Italic is in the original. See also Lawson (1997: 204–221).

  8. 8.

    Lawson (1997: 210) argues: “In each case, an explanation considered to be satisfactory will identify at least one systematic difference between the causal history of the primary component and that of the chosen contrast, or which would appear to be essential for the contrast if (…) it is only an imagined situation. In each case, the set of causal factors is responsible is likely to be different.”

  9. 9.

    Esposito (2013: 104–105) argues: “Economic decisions are never random. They are guided by motives and projects. They often disappoint and behave unpredictably. This unpredictability, however, can be expected.”

  10. 10.

    Imperfect information is the physiological condition and reason of markets Esposito (2013: 110). The most relevant information does not relate to the features of goods, but to the orientation and expectations of others. This information is not contained in prices, but is produced by the behaviour of operators who are oriented to prices Grossman (1976, 1989), Grossman and Stiglitz (1980), and Stiglitz (2003). This information cannot be known in advance because it does not yet exist. E.g.: Esposito (2013: 111): “The critical reflections within economics, however, say more. They introduce elements of complexity that the theory of performativity failed to highlight with the same clarity, in a certain sense radicalizing criticism, as an attempt to offer a way out of the stalemate of their own discipline. The key word is uncertainty, understood in a positive sense as a resource. Uncertainty is the basic resource of economic behaviour and of the possibility for obtaining profits. The world of the economy, Shackle (1970: 164) says, feeds on uncertainty. It is an unavoidable and uncontrollable uncertainty, one that is produced by the very behaviour of operators. Without uncertainty, the economy could not function or exist. In a world of rational and efficient markets, one would not be able to earn or invent anything, because any novelty would be neutralized in advance by the perfect distribution of information. However, a genuine entrepreneur produces surprises, invents novelties which could not be predicted in advance because they introduce a point of discontinuity, a ‘crucial moment’ in history that creates opportunities which did not exist previously. These possibilities cannot be planned, and they produce the persistent uncertainty of time as well as the creativity and dynamism of economic behaviour.”

  11. 11.

    Cf. Esposito (2013: 112): “A decision does not only choose between pregiven possibilities, establishing which ones are the most convenient, but creates new opportunities which prove unobtainable from the available data.”

  12. 12.

    Cf. (ibid.: 110): “The decision exploits uncertainty, without which there would be no freedom, and at the same time reproduces it, regenerating the unpredictability of the future Davidson (1978: 5 and 10), Snowdon et al. (1994: 300 ff.). Uncertainty, we could say, is the other side of creativity and innovation. This fact should be both understood and appreciated.”

  13. 13.

    This conceptualisation has a dramatic impact on the concept of the individual in economics, which becomes morally responsible.

  14. 14.

    Cf. (ibid.: 112): “There is always a reason. In fact, there are many reasons and they all have consequences. However, this does not mean that things will go as one wishes. Without a reference to motives, predictions and expectations, one cannot explain what is going on (even when such goings-on deviate from these expectations) and cannot prepare to react properly. If there are reasons, however, then there is no randomness. People do not decide by chance, they decide on the basis of the available information. How can we abandon randomness without giving up structures, describing a world that is unpredictable without being random, which is produced by the motives and decisions of operators but is always surprising? Can we describe the economy by starting from uncertainty and its forms?”

  15. 15.

    Beside the LIBOR, Esposito (2013: 6) also discussed the performativity of the Black-Scholes formula (the formula calculates the uncertainty of the future though the indirect calculation of the implied volatility and builds the basis for option pricing). She writes: “The Black-Scholes formula promises to calculate the reality that it had itself produced, and not reality as such. This is shown by the fact that, in the beginning (when the formula was proposed in 1973), the procedure appeared utterly implausible, based on a series of absolutely unrealistic assumptions about the functioning of markets (as the authors themselves remarked). It was admittedly a flawed formula, which became valid when the markets (…) began to adopt it, “believing” in the future reality promised by the formula, and, thereby, making it real in the present. The formula produced the reality which validated the formula.”

  16. 16.

    According to Esposito (2013: 7) dominant theories of uncertainty in mainstream economics, such as the Efficient Market Hypothesis Fama (1970) or Random Walk Hypothesis Malkiel (1999), Lo and MacKinlay (1999) fail to reflect is own reflexivity and proceed as if economic reality is independent of economic theory. These economic theories treat economic reality “as if” they describe it and neglect the fact that they are unrealistic and performative and therefore anything but descriptions of economic reality. Instead they are analytical instruments Hausman (1992), which have to be used with caution, as they have an impact to the phenomenon they analyse.

  17. 17.

    See also Baecker (1988: 52–53).

  18. 18.

    E.g.: “The trend towards mathematization rests on imprecise assumptions and leads researchers to lose sight of the complexity and interdependencies of the real world. […] Economics would be plagued by an excess of formalism without theory, which makes it all the more abstract and detached from its object. The result is the “crisis of vision” of an “esoteric” theory speaking about an imaginary hypothetical reality which does not face the data of reality, but merely demonstrates that the real world confirms its predictions Blaug (1992). The detachment from reality is explicit, given that economic theories refer to variables that must be few in number, homogeneous, permanent, and isolated from the rest of the universe, which never is the case Shackle (1979: 74 ff.) These theories are inevitably subject to errors and ambiguities Hicks (1979: Chap. 1), if they are not outright false Zamagni (1982: 13), only serving to remove or neutralise the social factors which generate uncertainty and instability, putting rigor before relevance.” Heilbroner and Milberg (1995: 101–105).

  19. 19.

    See also Shackle (1955: 91), Rizzo (1979: 5) and Clark and Juma (1987: 5).

References

  • Baecker D (1988) Information und Risiko in der Marktwirtschaft. Suhrcamp, Frankfurt am Main

    Google Scholar 

  • Blaug M (1992) The methodology of economics: or how economists explain. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Boylan TA, O’Gorman PF (1995) Beyond rhetoric and realism in economics. Towards a reformulation of economic methodology. Routledge, London

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chick V (2004) On open systems. Braz J Polit Econ 24(1):3–16

    Google Scholar 

  • Chick V, Dow SC (2005) The meaning of open systems. J Econ Methodol 12(3):363–381

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clark N, Juma C (1987) Long-run economics: an evolutionary approach to economic growth. Pinter Publisher, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Colander D, Föllmer H, Haas A, Goldberg M, Juselius K, Kirman A, Lux T et al (2009) The financial crisis and the systemic failure of academic economics. Institute for the World Economy, Kiel

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson P (1978) Money and the real world. Palgrave Macmillan

    Google Scholar 

  • Dow SC (2012) Uncertainty-denial. University of Victoria Department Discussion Paper DDP1204, November, pp 1–33

    Google Scholar 

  • Esposito E (2007) Die Fiktion der wahrscheinlichen Realität. Suhrkamp, Berlin

    Google Scholar 

  • Esposito E (2011) The future of futures: the time of money in financing and society. Edward Elgar, Cheltenham

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Esposito E (2013) The structures of uncertainty: performativity and unpredictability in economic operations. Econ Soc 42(1):102–129

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fama EF (1970) Efficient capital markets: a review of theory and empirical work. J Fin 25(2):383–417

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman M (1953) The methodology of positive economics. In: Friedman M (ed) In positive economics. Chicago University Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Grossmann SJ (1976) On the efficiency of competitive stock markets where traders have diverse information. J Fin 31(May):573–585

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Grossmann SJ (1989) The informational role of prices. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Grossman SJ, Stiglitz JE (1980) On the impossibility of informationally efficient markets. Am Econ Rev 70(3):393–408

    Google Scholar 

  • Hands WD (2001) Reflection without rules: economic methodology and contemporary science theory. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hausman DM (1992) The inexact and separate science of economics. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hausman DM (1998) Problems with realism in economics. Econ Philos 14(2):185–213

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hayek FA (1937) Economics and knowledge. University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Heilbroner R, Milberg WS (1995) The crisis of vision in modern economic thought. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Hicks JR (1979) Causality in economics. Basil Blackwell, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Keynes JM (1936) The general theory of employment, interest and money. Palgrave Macmillan, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Klamer A (2007) Speaking of economics: how to get in the conversation. Routledge, London

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lawson T (1995) A realist perspective on contemporary “Economic Theory”. J Econ Iss XXIX(1):1–32

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawson T (1997) Economics and reality. Routledge, London

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lawson T (2003) Reorienting economics. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawson T (2004) A conception of ontology. Cambridge Ontology group, (December), 1–24.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawson T (2009) Contemporary economics and the crisis. Real-World Econ Rev 50:122–131

    Google Scholar 

  • Lawson T, Collier A, Bhaskar R, Archer M, Norrie A (1998) Critical realism: Essential readings. Routledge, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Lo A, MacKinlay C (1999) A non-random walk down wall street. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Loasby BJ (2003) Closed models and open systems. J Econ Methodol 10(3):285–306

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lucas RE (1972) Expectations and the neutrality of money. J Econ Theor 4:103–124

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacKenzie D (2006a) Is economics performative? Option Theor Construct Derivat Market 28:29–55

    Google Scholar 

  • MacKenzie D (2006b) An engine, not a camera: How financial models shape markets. MIT Press, Cambridge

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mäki U (1988) On the problem of realism in economics. Fundamenta Scientiae 9:343–362

    Google Scholar 

  • Mäki U (1989) On the problem of realism in economics. Ricerche Economiche 43(1–2):176–198

    Google Scholar 

  • Mäki U (1994) Reorienting the assumptions issue. In: Backhouse RE (ed) New directions in economic methodology. Routledge, London, pp 236–256

    Google Scholar 

  • Mäki U (1998) Is Coase a realist? Philos Soc Sci 28(5):31

    Google Scholar 

  • Mäki U (2002) The dismal queen of the social sciences. In: Mäki U (ed) Fact and fiction in economics: realism, models, and social construction. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 307–321

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Mäki U (2008) Method and appraisal in economics: 1976–2006. J Econ Methodol 15(4):409–423

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mäki U (2009) Realistic realism about unrealistic models. In: Kincaid H, Ross D (eds) The Oxford handbook of philosophy of economics. Oxford University Press, Oxford, pp 69–98

    Google Scholar 

  • Mäki U (2012). Economics for real: Uskali Mäki and the place of truth in economics. Routledge

    Google Scholar 

  • Mäki U, Dilworth C (1992) On the method of isolation in economics. In: Idealization IV: intelligibility in science. Poznan Stud Philos Sci Humanit (special issue) 26:319–354

    Google Scholar 

  • Mäki U, Mooslechner P, Schuberth H, Schurtz M (2004) Some truths about truth for economists, their critics and clients. In: Economic policy-making under uncertainty: the role of truth and accountability in policy advice. Edward Elgar, Cheltenham, pp 9–39

    Google Scholar 

  • Malkiel B (1999) A random walk down Wall Street: the time-tested strategy for successful investing. W.W. Norton, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Marzetti S, Scazzieri R (2011) Fundamental uncertainty: rationality and plausible reasoning. Palgrave Macmillan, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • McKenna EJ, Zannoni DC (2001) Post-Keynesian economics and nihilism. J Post Keynesian Econ 23:331–347

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mearman A (2014) How should economics curricula be evaluated? Int Rev Econ Educ 16(Part B):73–86

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mirowski P (2012) From Mandelbrot to Chaos in economic theory. South Econ J 57(2):289–307

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Potts J (2000) Uncertainty, complexity, and imagination. In: Earl P, Frowen S (eds) Economics as an art of thought: essays in memory of G.L.S Shackle. Routledge, London, pp 162–184

    Google Scholar 

  • Rebonato R (2001). Theory and practice of model risk management. Quantitative Research Centre (QUARC) of the Royal Bank of Scotland Oxford Financial Research Centre – Oxford University

    Google Scholar 

  • Rizzo MJ (1979) Time, uncertainty, and disequilibrium. Lexington Books, Lexington

    Google Scholar 

  • Shackle GLS (1955) Uncertainty in economics and other reflections. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Shackle GLS (1970) Expectation enterprise and profit: the theory of the firm (studies in economics). Allen & Unwin, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Shackle GLS (1972) Epistemics and economics: a critique of economic doctrines. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, p 162

    Google Scholar 

  • Shackle GLS (1979) Imagination and the nature of choice. Columbia University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Smelser NJ, Swedberg R (1994) The handbook of economic sociology. Princeton University Press, Princeton

    Google Scholar 

  • Snowdon B, Vane H, Wynarczyk P (1994) A modern guide to macroeconomics. Edward Elgar, Aldershot

    Google Scholar 

  • Stiglitz JE (2003) Globalization and its discontents. W. W. Norton & Company

    Google Scholar 

  • van der Lecq SG (2000) Money, coordination, and prices. Edward Elgar, Cheltenham

    Google Scholar 

  • Witt U (2007) Novelty and the bounds of unkowledge in economics. Papers on Economics and Evolution 7

    Google Scholar 

  • Zamagni S (1982) Saggi die filosofia della scienza economica. NIS, Roma

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Köhn, J. (2017). The Nature of Economics. In: Uncertainty in Economics. Contributions to Economics. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-55351-1_9

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics