Skip to main content

Introduction

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Morphogenesis of the Sign

Part of the book series: Lecture Notes in Morphogenesis ((LECTMORPH))

  • 166 Accesses

Abstract

The issues addressed in these pages, the various positions that are defended within, and, more broadly, the main theoretical perspectives which will be pursued find their unity with respect to a morphodynamic model of the Saussurean sign, which, to put it as such, constitutes their center of gravity or intersection point.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    All translations of citations which are referenced in French in the bibliography are our own unless otherwise specified.

  2. 2.

    Petitot (1985), p. 290.

  3. 3.

    Auroux (1998), pp. 210–211.

  4. 4.

    Ibid., p. 210.

  5. 5.

    Martin (2002), p. 16.

  6. 6.

    “Existence is the absolute position of a thing and thereby differs from any sort of predicate, which, as such, is posited at each time merely relatively to another thing” (Kant in Walford and Meerbote 2003, p. 119), also quoted in Philonenko (1989, p. 39), or “the subtlest of concepts never abolish or produce an existing something” (Kempf, Introduction to Kant (1972/1763, p. 10).

  7. 7.

    “The recovery of a thing by a representation would only be possible if the thing were, also, a representation” (Frege 1971, p. 172).

  8. 8.

    “Natural reflection [‘natural’ understood here in the sense of ‘naive realism’] on the relation between knowledge, its sense, and its object almost inevitably makes [mistakes]” (Husserl 1999, p. 18) because it is impossible to understand “what it could mean for a being to be known in itself and yet be known in knowledge” (Ibid., p. 23).

  9. 9.

    “[I]t was […] rightly felt that statements can be logically justified [and refuted] only by statements” (Popper 2005, p. 21).

  10. 10.

    “The object is not given in advance of the viewpoint: far from it. Rather, one might say that it is the viewpoint adopted which creates the object” (Saussure 2013/1916, p. 9).

  11. 11.

    To cite but a few of them, beginning with illustrious figures: Hjemslev, who almost replicates the Saussurean formulation: “Is it the object which determines and affects the theory, or is it the theory which determines and affects its object?” (Hjelmslev 1968, p. 23). Moreover: “as long as the method has not been applied, no so-called obvious facts will exist (those which some philosophers of language like to use as a starting point by appealing to naive realism, which, as we know, does not hold up to scientific examination” (Hjelmslev 1985, p. 72). Likewise, Benveniste (1966, p. 119): “[D]escription first of all necessitates specification of adequate procedures and criteria, and that, finally, the reality of the object is inseparable from the method given for its description” (Benveniste 1971, p. 101). Then, among our contemporaries: Reflecting upon what is a linguistic fact, Martin (2002, p. 22) notes that “the linguistic fact never goes beyond more or less conventional decisions.”

  12. 12.

    Location of the faulty component, introduction or adjustment of ad hoc protective concepts, conventional core….

  13. 13.

    The falsifiability requirement, in its most general principle, is admitted as a character of intellectual probity: “most philosophers appear to now be persuaded that there exists no universal criteria of scientificity […] though it is not uncommon to hear the same people complain that a theory […] is not clearly testable, which presupposes that they accept the idea that if testability does not represent a necessary and sufficient condition of scientificity, it constitutes at least a desirable methodological ideal […] testability being a virtue, and irrefutability, a vice” (Boyer 2000, p. 166).

  14. 14.

    More precisely exposed in Piotrowski (2009, pp. 112–121).

  15. 15.

    Terminology borrowed from Granger (1992, pp. 267–268).

  16. 16.

    Which correspond to the “data models” of contemporary epistemology, cf. Bitbol (1998, p. 47).

  17. 17.

    Auroux (1998, p. 168).

  18. 18.

    Ibid., p. 215.

  19. 19.

    Regarding this point, the consensus is obvious, as stated namely by Dalbéra (2002, p. 9): “The corpus can only be a construct and […] its construction forms an integral part of the theoretical lens through which the linguist intends to apprehend reality.”

  20. 20.

    Lazard (2001, p. 17).

  21. 21.

    Ibid.

  22. 22.

    Ibid.

  23. 23.

    Ollivier (2000, p. 27).

  24. 24.

    Ibid.

  25. 25.

    Ibid., p. 20.

  26. 26.

    Boyer (2000, p. 181).

  27. 27.

    Granger (1979, p. 200).

References

  • Auroux, S. (1998). La raison, le langage et les normes. Paris: PUF, coll. Sciences, Modernités, Philosophies.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Benveniste, E. (1966). Problèmes de linguistique générale I. Paris: Gallimard, coll. Tel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Benveniste, E. (1971). Problems in general linguistics (M.E. Meek, Trans.). Coral Gables: University of Miami Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bitbol, M. (1998). L’aveuglante proximité du réel. Paris: Flammarion, coll. Champs.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boyer, A. (2000). Philosophie des sciences. In P. Engel (Ed.), Précis de philosophie analytique. Paris: PUF.

    Google Scholar 

  • Culioli, A. (1999). Pour une linguistique de lénonciation; Formalisation et opérations de repérage, T. 2. Paris: Ophrys.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dalbéra, J.-P. (2002). Le corpus entre données, analyse et théorie. Corpus (1), 1–10.

    Google Scholar 

  • de Saussure, F. (2013). Course in general linguistics (R. Harris, Trans.). London: Bloomsbury Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ducrot, O. (1995). In Cahier “Livres” de Libération, 21 septembre 1995.

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege, G. (1971). Ecrits logiques et philosophiques. Paris: Le Seuil, coll. L’ordre Philosophique.

    Google Scholar 

  • Granger, G.-G. (1979). Langage et épistémologie. Paris: Klincksieck, coll. Horizons du langage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Granger, G.-G. (1992). La vérification. Paris: O. Jacob.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hjelmslev, L. (1968). Prolégomènes à une théorie du langage (p. 35). Paris: Éditions de Minuit, coll. Arguments.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hjelmslev, L. (1985). Nouveaux essais. Paris: PUF, coll. Formes sémiotiques.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, E. (1999). The idea of phenomenology (L. Hardy, Trans.). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, E. (1972). Essai pour introduire en philosophie le concept de grandeur négative. Paris: Vrin, coll. Bibliothèque des textes philosophiques.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lazard, G. (2001). De l’objectivité en linguistique. Bulletin de la Société de linguistique de Paris, XCVI(1), 9–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martin, R. (1978). La notion de recevabilité en linguistique. Paris: Klincksieck, coll. Bibliothèque française et romane.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, R. (2002). Comprendre la linguistique. Paris: PUF, coll. Quadrige.

    Google Scholar 

  • Milner, J.-C. (1989). Introduction à une science du langage. Paris: Le Seuil, coll. Des Travaux.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ollivier, B. (2000). Observer la communication, Naissance d’une interdiscipline. Paris: CNRS Editions, coll. CNRS Communication.

    Google Scholar 

  • Petitot, J. (1985). Morphogenèse du sens: 1, Pour un schématisme de la structure. Paris: PUF, coll. Formes Sémiotiques.

    Google Scholar 

  • Philonenko, A. (1989). L’oeuvre de Kant (Vol. 1). Paris: Vrin, coll. A la Recherche de la Vérité.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piotrowski, D. (1997). Dynamiques et structures en langue. Paris: CNRS Éditions, coll. Sciences du Langage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piotrowski, D. (2009). Phénoménalité et Objectivité Linguistiques. Paris: Champion, Collection Bibliothèque de Grammaire et de Linguistique.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piotrowski, D. (2010). Morphodynamique du signe; I – L’architecture fonctionnelle. Cahiers Ferdinand de Saussure, 63, 185–203.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piotrowski, D. (2011). Morphodynamique du signe; II – Retour sur quelques concepts saussuriens. Cahiers Ferdinand de Saussure, 64, 101–118.

    Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. (2005). The logic of scientific discovery. London & New-York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walford, D., & Meerbote, R. (Eds.). (2003). Kant, I., Theoretical Philosophy, 1755-1770. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to David Piotrowski .

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Piotrowski, D. (2017). Introduction. In: Morphogenesis of the Sign. Lecture Notes in Morphogenesis. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-55325-2_1

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-55325-2_1

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-55323-8

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-55325-2

  • eBook Packages: Social SciencesSocial Sciences (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics