Skip to main content

Surely, It Is Just a Fantasy!

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Law of Desire

Part of the book series: The Palgrave Lacan Series ((PALS))

  • 721 Accesses

Abstract

This Chapter focuses on the seventh section of Lacan’s essay ‘Kant with Sade’, in which Lacan reconsiders the elements of the Sadean fantasy in terms of Freud’s controversial concept of the death drive, and in which he also explores the relevance of the classic opposition between sadism and masochism. Nobus explains why Lacan refuses to take the Sadean fantasy as a blueprint for Sade’s own mental economy, and what it means for Sade not to have been duped by his (literary) fantasy. In addition, he extends Lacan’s discussion of the object as object (cause) of desire, and he opens up a new perspective on the vexed issue of the relationship between creative writers and their written creations.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Neither in the Critique, nor in the 1966 Sade-version of ‘Kant with Sade’ does this part of Lacan’s text constitute a separate section.

  2. 2.

    This is also why, in the same paragraph, Lacan referred to Freud’s death drive as a ‘death demand’—not, as Fink has translated it, a demand for death, but as a demanding death drive, similar to how Freud referred to the demands (Ansprüchen) of the drives (Triebe) (Freud, 1955c, p. 11).

  3. 3.

    Of course, Lacan always claimed that he was only ever rendering explicit what Freud had already surmised. Lacan’s symbolic inscription of the death drive could therefore be seen, in this context, as a rearticulation of Freud’s view that, even in animal life, ‘instincts are historically determined’, insofar as they seem to respond to a mechanism of trans-generational memory (Freud, 1955c, p. 37).

  4. 4.

    Many post-Freudian psychoanalysts, including Anna Freud, rejected Freud’s death drive on the grounds that it was superfluous—an immaterial and unnecessary speculation—or simply morally objectionable (Fenichel, 1954). For his part, Lacan believed that Freud’s critics had failed to understand the precise effects of language, especially in their clinical practice, and were happy to just use Freud ‘at conventions’, i.e. in a purely academic, intellectual sense (p. 655).

  5. 5.

    The interpersonal and social relations movement in psychoanalysis was inaugurated by Karen Horney and rose to prominence by virtue of Harry Stack Sullivan, Erich Fromm and Clara Thompson. In her influential critical survey of psychoanalytic theories, Thompson wrote: ‘Serious destructiveness seems to be developed by malevolent environments…or as a result of destructive cultural patterns…In short, far from being a product of the death instinct, it is an expression of the organism’s attempt to live…[Freud] sees man predominantly as an instinct ridden animal and does not give adequate weight to the overwhelming importance of social factors in moulding as well as distorting man’s potentialities’ (Thompson, 1952, pp. 52–55). For a discussion of Lacan’s critique of the notion of eternity, see Allouch (2009).

  6. 6.

    Starting from his work on the authoritarian personality, Fromm had argued that sadism and masochism invariably go together, and that one should always refer to the ‘sado-masochistic character’, even if one or the other component tends to prevail. See Fromm (1974), which summarizes and expands ideas he had been developing since the early 1940s.

  7. 7.

    See, for example, the work of Daniel Lagache on aggressivity, in which the ‘sadomasochistic scene’ is interpreted as a complementarity of erogenous tensions (Lagache, 1993). In 1967, Gilles Deleuze formulated the most trenchant critique of this type of ‘sadomasochistic entity’, in his influential introduction to Sacher-Masoch’s Venus in Furs. Whilst acknowledging that the Sadean libertines may enjoy pain, and that Sacher-Masoch’s hero Severin eventually declares himself cured of his masochism, if only to enter the sexual sphere of sadism, Deleuze was extremely sceptical of the reversibility between the two: ‘[W]hat we have in each case is a paradoxical by-product, a kind of sadism being the humorous outcome of masochism, and a kind of masochism the ironic outcome of sadism. But it is very doubtful whether the masochist’s sadism is the same as Sade’s, or the sadist’s masochism the same as Masoch’s’ (Deleuze, 1991, p. 40).

  8. 8.

    At this point in his text, Lacan employed a number of sartorial metaphors, which have unfortunately disappeared in Fink’s translation. Lacan stated that amongst those who strive for ‘tidier appearances’ (une toilette plus soignée), and argue that the sadist ‘denies the Other’s existence’, some may draw on the ‘bon faiseur existentialiste’ and others on the ‘ready-made personnaliste’. The expression ‘bon faiseur’ does not refer to a ‘do-gooder’, as Fink has rendered it, but to a ‘good tailor’, as opposed to the mass-market, factory-produced clothing of the ready-made. In addition, ‘existentialiste’ and ‘personnaliste’ are the adjectives rather than the nouns, so that the expressions may be rendered more accurately as ‘fine existentialist tailoring’ and ‘personalist ready-made wear’. All of this does not explain, of course, who exactly Lacan had in mind, here. To the best of my knowledge, the idea that the sadist denies the Other’s existence does not feature in any of the existentialist and personalist texts, but it does come fairly close to what Sartre (as the quintessential representative of ‘fine existentialist tailoring’) argued in his lengthy analysis of sadism in Being and Nothingness (Sartre, 2003, pp. 401–434), and to how Emmanuel Mounier—the founder of the philosophical doctrine of personalism—described the sadist in his Introduction aux existentialismes (Mounier, 1962, p. 126).

  9. 9.

    If the idea that the sadists transfer their own pain of existence onto the Other does not emanate directly from Lacan’s schema of the Sadean fantasy, then it is definitely embedded in the text of Philosophy in the Boudoir. After Madame de Mistival has been whipped back into consciousness, she screams: ‘Oh, my heavens! Why have you summoned me back from the depths of graves? Why have you brought me back to the horrors of life?’ (Sade, 2006, p. 169).

  10. 10.

    Fink has translated ‘Mais pourquoi ne nous ferait-il [the eternal object] pas bien commun?’ as ‘But why wouldn’t it belong to both of us?’ (p. 656), which raises the question as to who ‘both of us’ would be in this instance. Perhaps the phrase could be rendered more accurately as ‘But why wouldn’t it be a common good for us?’, or ‘Why wouldn’t it be our common good?’.

Bibliography

  • Allouch, J. (2009). Contre l’éternité: Ogawa, Mallarmé, Lacan, Paris: Epel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Deleuze, G. (1991). ‘Coldness and Cruelty’ (1967), trans. J. McNeil, in Masochism, New York: Zone Books, pp. 7138.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fenichel, O. (1954). ‘A Critique of the Death Instinct’ (1935), in The Collected Papers of Otto Fenichel, First Series, London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, pp. 363372.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freud, S. (1953b). ‘Three Essays on the Theory of Sexuality’ (1905), in The Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud, ed. J. Strachey, Vol. 7, London: The Hogarth Press and the Institute of Psycho-Analysis, pp. 123–243.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freud, S. (1955c). ‘Beyond the Pleasure Principle’ (1920), in The Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud, ed. J. Strachey, Vol. 18, London: The Hogarth Press and the Institute of Psycho-Analysis, pp. 164.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freud, S. (1957c). ‘Instincts and their Vicissitudes’ (1915), in The Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud, ed. J. Strachey, Vol. 14, London: The Hogarth Press and the Institute of Psycho-Analysis, pp. 109140.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freud, S. (1961a). ‘The Economic Problem of Masochism’ (1924), in The Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud, ed. J. Strachey, Vol. 19, London: The Hogarth Press and the Institute of Psycho-Analysis, pp. 155170.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freud, S. (1961b). ‘The Future of an Illusion’ (1927), in The Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud, ed. J. Strachey, Vol. 21, London: The Hogarth Press and the Institute of Psycho-Analysis, pp. 156.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freud, S. (1966). ‘Project for a Scientific Psychology’ (1950), in The Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud, ed. J. Strachey, Vol. 1, London: The Hogarth Press and the Institute of Psycho-Analysis, pp. 281397.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fromm, E. (1974). The Anatomy of Human Destructiveness, London: Jonathan Cape.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klossowski, P. (1992). Sade my Neighbour (1967), trans. A. Lingis, London: Quartet Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lacan, J. (1988b). The Seminar. Book II: The Ego in Freud’s Theory and in the Technique of Psychoanalysis (1978), trans. S. Tomaselli, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lacan, J. (1992). The Seminar. Book VII: The Ethics of Psychoanalysis (1986), trans. D. Porter, ed. J.-A. Miller, New York/London: W.W. Norton & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lagache, D. (1993). ‘Aggressivity’ (1960), in The Work of Daniel Lagache: Selected Writings, trans. E. Holder, London: Karnac Books, pp. 207–236.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mounier, E. (1962). Introduction aux existentialismes, Paris: Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Renan, E. (1886). Studies in Religious History (1884), London: Richard Bentley and Son.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sade, Marquis de. (2006). Philosophy in the Boudoir (1795), trans. J. Neugroschel, London: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, J.-P. (1989). ‘No Exit’ (Huis clos) (1943), in No Exit and Three Other Plays, trans. S. Gilbert, New York/London: Vintage, pp. 1–46.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, J.-P. (2003). Being and Nothingness: An Essay on Phenomenological Ontology (1943), trans. H.E. Barnes, London/New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schopenhauer, A. (2014). The World as Will and Representation (1818), trans. J. Norman & A. Welchman, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schopenhauer, A. (2004). ‘On the Suffering of the World’ (1851), in Essays and Aphorisms, trans. R.J. Hollingdale, Harmondsworth: Penguin, pp. 41–50.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, C. (1952). Psychoanalysis: Evolution and Development, London: Allen and Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Whitehead, A. N. (1978). Process and Reality: An Essay in Cosmology (1929), corrected edition, eds. D. R. Griffin & D. W. Sherburne, New York: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Žižek, S. (2014). The Most Sublime Hysteric: Hegel with Lacan (2011), trans. T. Scott-Railton, Cambridge: Polity.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Nobus, D. (2017). Surely, It Is Just a Fantasy!. In: The Law of Desire. The Palgrave Lacan Series. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-55275-0_7

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics