Skip to main content

Who Are We Are and What Are We Doing When It Comes to New Atheism?

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
New Atheism: Critical Perspectives and Contemporary Debates
  • 753 Accesses

Abstract

One of the great difficulties about considering New Atheism is that many of the names associated with the movement have come from the scholarly ranks. This raises some difficult questions for how it is we, as academics and scholars, respond to them and treat their treatment of religion. In this reflective final chapter I look back over the previous contributions to the volume from the perspective of philosophy of social science—positioning myself halfway between our philosophical contributors and our social scientific contributors. Looking at what it is the New Atheists themselves might be trying to achieve, I investigate the ways in which we have responded to them and what this might say about us as a “scholarly group”. Ultimately the fact that some of the New Atheists come from the ranks and engage so willingly with the general public we must address the fundamental questions of what it is to do philosophy and what it is to do social science.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    My paper came midway through a series of panels on the topic of ‘non-ordinary beings’ in the study of religion, and I effectively told the speakers before me that they were wrong.

  2. 2.

    This is giving rise to a situation in which young academics, particularly those recently out of their PhDs and struggling to find employment in the current economic climate, are forced into announcing an affiliation with a university in order to gain admittance through publication. The side-effect of this is that the university is then able to gain credit for a piece of work that they did not contribute to. The young academic would have received as much support as if they had listed their affiliation as the Unseen University!

  3. 3.

    Lacking an affiliation myself, I too fail at this norm.

  4. 4.

    Barnes et al. point to the case of Robert Chambers (1802–1871) showing how specialization became a mark of authority and that scholars have been historically denounced for commenting on other specializations (1996, 156–162).

  5. 5.

    Note, this pertains to ‘science’ as an activity and may be extraneous to the aims of university ‘Science’ departments.

  6. 6.

    Following the above footnote, it is worth mentioning how Aristotle regarded ‘politics’ to be a ‘practical science’—i.e. philosophical and therefore constituting various norms. Such an understanding is still taken as the guiding principle behind departments of ‘Politics’ which are often found within Social Science departments in universities. This raises a separate point about the ideological impact of calling something ‘science’ which cannot be explored here.

  7. 7.

    Indeed, one of the key questions of the philosophy of sport has been what makes a sport ‘sport’ (Meier 1981).

  8. 8.

    This may be a too rigid view on what the university does. And I will certainly not claim that this is its primary, or even intended, function.

  9. 9.

    In point of fact, I will add anecdotally, within Religious Studies any sort of public engagement, whether qualified or not, is often viewed as a drop in academic standards.

  10. 10.

    The address turned out to be so important it was published in several journals: American Sociological Review, Sociale Welt and The British Journal of Sociology (all 2005). Social Problems, Social Forces, Critical Sociology, The American Sociologist and The British Journal of Sociology (all 2005–2006) then dedicated special issues to it.

  11. 11.

    Developed by Schutz (1962, 246) .

  12. 12.

    This point is drawn from Heidegger ’s distinction between the ready-to-handness and present-at-handness of tools (Heidegger 2010, 72–73).

  13. 13.

    This observation led to much editorial debate as to which chapter should come first.

References

  • Barnes, Barry, et al. 1996. Scientific Knowledge: A Sociological Analysis. London: Athlone.

    Google Scholar 

  • Burawoy, Michael. 2005a. For Public Sociology. American Sociological Review 70: 4–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2005b. The Return of the Repressed: Recovering the Public Face of U.S. Sociology, a Hundred Years On. The Annals of the American Academy of Political and Social Science 600: 68–85.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2009. The Public Sociology Wars. In Handbook of Public Sociology, ed. V. Jeffries, 449–473. Lanham: Rowman and Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Delanty, Gerard, and Piet Strydom, eds. 2003. Philosophies of Social Science: The Classic and Contemporary Readings. Maidenhead: Open University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Geertz, Armin W. 2009. New Atheistic Approaches in the Cognitive Science of Religion: On Daniel Dennett, Breaking the Spell (2006) and Richard Dawkins the God Delusion (2006). In Contemporary Theories of Religion: A Critical Companion, ed. Michale Stausberg, 242–263. Abingdon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gordon, S. 1991. The History and Philosophy of Social Science. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gregory, Brad. 2012. The Unintended Reformation: How a Religious Revolution Secularised Society. London: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gurwitsch, Aaron. 1974. In Phenomenology and the Theory of Science, ed. L. Embree. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin. 2010. Being and Time. trans. by J. Stambaugh. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, Edmund. 1965. Phenomenology and the Crisis of Philosophy. Ed. and trans. By Q. Lauer. London: Harper Torchbooks.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1970. The Crisis of European Science and Transcendental Phenomenology: An Introduction to Phenomenological Philosophy. Trans. D. Carr. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1988. Cartesian Meditations: An Introduction to Phenomenology. trans. by D. Cairns. Kluwer. London: Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, Luther, and Donald Wiebe. 2012a. Religious Studies as a Scientific Discipline: The Persistence of a Delusion. Religion 2: 9–18.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2012b. Why the Possible Is Not Impossible but Is Unlikely: A Response to Our Colleagues. Religion 20: 63–72.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCutcheon, Russell. 2001. Critics Not Caretakers: Redescribing the Public Study of Religion. Albany: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2012. A Direct Question Deserves a Direct Answer: A Response to Atalia Omer’s “Can A Critic be a Caretaker too?”. Journal of the American Academy of Religion 80: 1077–1082.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Meier, Klaus. 1981. On the Inadequacies of Sociological Definitions of Sport. International Review for the Sociology of Sport 16: 79–102.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merton, Robert. 1973. In The Sociology of Science: Theoretical and Empirical Investigations, ed. N. Storer. London: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruane, Frances. 2012. Public Intellectuals in Times of Crisis: The Role of Academia. In Reflections on Crisis: The Role of the Public Intellectual, ed. M.P. Corcoran and K. Lalor. Royal Irish Academy: Dublin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scheler, Max. 1989. Sociology and the Study and Formulation of Weltanschauung. Trans by R. Speirs. In P. Lassman and I. Velody Max Weber’s “Science as a Vocation”, 87–91. London: Unwin Hyman.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schutz, Alfred. 1962. Collected Papers I: The Problem of Social Reality. ed. by M. Natanson. The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tuckett, Jonathan. 2014. Alfred Schutz’s Postulates of Social Science: Clarification and Amendments. Human Studies 37: 469–488.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2015. The Contradiction of Democracy and Science. BASR Bulletin 127: 16–22.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. forthcoming. Orthodoxy Is Not Scientific: A Phenomenological Critique of Naturalism. In J. Blum (ed.) The Role of Methodological Naturalism in Religious Studies. Brill

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, Max. 1946. In From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology, ed. H. Gerth and G. Wright Mills. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wiebe, Donald. 1999. The Politics of Religious Studies. New York: Palgrave.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jonathan Tuckett .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Tuckett, J. (2017). Who Are We Are and What Are We Doing When It Comes to New Atheism?. In: Cotter, C., Quadrio, P., Tuckett, J. (eds) New Atheism: Critical Perspectives and Contemporary Debates. Sophia Studies in Cross-cultural Philosophy of Traditions and Cultures, vol 21. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-54964-4_12

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics