Skip to main content

Animal Research and the Political Theory of Animal Rights

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Ethical and Political Approaches to Nonhuman Animal Issues

Abstract

In his chapter, Gardar Arnason argues that if we accept the citizenship framework of nonhuman animal rights, as it is presented by Sue Donaldson and Will Kymlicka in Zoopolis (2011), then we cannot be abolitionist about nonhuman animal research. To show this, Arnason outlines three further implications of the citizenship framework: (1) the interests of nonhuman citizens must be taken into account in our science policy, (2) the moral constraints on the use of nonhuman animals for research must be on par with the moral constraints on the use of humans for research, and (3) in so far as there is a duty to participate in research, that duty will apply, perhaps indirectly, to nonhuman citizens as well.

This research was supported by the German Research Foundation (DFG) research unit grant FOR 1847.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    By “the radical abolitionist view”, I, following Donaldson and Kymlicka, refer to views such as Gary Francione’s (2008) abolitionism. There are less radical abolitionist views, which would allow some nonexploitative use of nonhuman animals. Most prominent of the moderate abolitionist views is that of Tom Regan (1983), which focuses the abolitionist claim on the use of nonhuman animals in agriculture, science, and sport (in particular hunting and trapping).

  2. 2.

    Since most domestic animals cannot survive independently in the wild, there is no ethical point in liberating them. All that we could do, according to extinctionists such as Gary Francione (2008), is to make sure they do not reproduce and eventually go extinct.

  3. 3.

    Their main target here is Gary Francione (2008), who has advocated strongly for the abolition of all use of nonhuman animals and the controlled extinction of domesticated animals.

  4. 4.

    To be fair, Donaldson and Kymlicka note that “most of” controlled lab experiments on nonhuman animals are unethical, implying that some of them may be ethical, and that learning about nonhuman animals “through careful observation and ethical interaction” is possible (Donaldson & Kymlicka, 2011, p.31, n.24).

  5. 5.

    Alasdair Cochrane (2007) comes to a similar conclusion, by way of arguing that an interest-based account of nonhuman animal rights would not provide sufficient grounds for a right to liberty for nonhuman animals.

  6. 6.

    See also Donaldson and Kymlicka’s discussion of nonhuman animal representation in society (2011, p.154).

  7. 7.

    It is not a novel idea to consider nonhuman research subjects vulnerable; see for example Johnson, 2013 and Johnson & Barnard, 2014.

  8. 8.

    Arguments have been made to the effect that some nonhuman animals are moral agents with (limited) moral obligations (Shapiro, 2006) or at least have moral abilities, which are expressed in moral behaviour (de Waal, 1997). Still, I will assume here the more common view that nonhuman animals are not moral agents and cannot have duties.

  9. 9.

    If participation in biomedical research is merely supererogatory, then the guardian (in both the human and nonhuman case) should only take the interests of her subject into account (and the subject’s previous wishes, if applicable). If research participation is a duty, the guardian must also consider the moral implications of not allowing the participation of her subject in research. The guardian would in that case be morally blameworthy for not allowing that participation, provided that the greater interests of the subject are not violated. I am not arguing for a duty to participate in research, but rather that if there is a good case for such a duty, then it applies to nonhuman subjects as well as human subjects.

Bibliography

  • Cochrane, A., 2007. Animal Rights and Animal Experiments: An Interest-Based Approach. Res Publica, 13(3), pp. 293–318.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Waal, F., 1997. Good Natured: The Origins of Right and Wrong in Humans and Other Animals. Boston: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Donaldson, S. & Kymlicka, W., 2011. Zoopolis: A Political Theory of Animal Rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fenton, A., 2014. Can a Chimp Say “No”? Reenvisioning Chimpanzee Dissent in Harmful Research. Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics, 23(2), pp. 130–139.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Francione, G., 2008. Animals as Persons: Essays on the Abolition of Animal Exploitation. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris, J., 2005. Scientific Research is a Moral Duty. Journal of Medical Ethics, 31(4), pp. 242–248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, J., 2013. Vulnerable Subjects? The Case of Nonhuman Animals in Experimentation. Journal of Bioethical Inquiry, 10(4), pp. 497–504.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, J. & Barnard, N. D., 2014. Chimpanzees as Vulnerable Subjects in Research. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics, 35(2), pp. 133–141.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kantin, H. & Wendler, D., 2015. Is There a Role for Assent or Dissent in Animal Research? Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics, 24(4), pp. 459–472.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P., 2001. Science, Truth and Democracy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Regan, T., 1983. The Case for Animal Rights. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rhodes, R., 2008. In Defense of the Duty to Participate in Biomedical Research. American Journal of Bioethics, 8(10), pp. 37–38.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schaefer, G. O., Emanuel, E. J. & Wertheimer, A., 2009. The Obligation to Participate in Biomedical Research. JAMA, 302(1), pp. 67–72.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, P., 2006. Moral Agency in Other Animals. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics, 27(4), pp. 357–373.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gardar Arnason .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Arnason, G. (2017). Animal Research and the Political Theory of Animal Rights. In: Woodhall, A., Garmendia da Trindade, G. (eds) Ethical and Political Approaches to Nonhuman Animal Issues. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-54549-3_14

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics