Skip to main content

Repetition and Reversibility in Evolution: Theoretical Population Genetics

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Time of Nature and the Nature of Time

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science ((BSPS,volume 326))

Abstract

Repetitiveness and reversibility have long been considered as characteristic features of scientific knowledge. In theoretical population genetics, repetitiveness is illustrated by a number of genetic equilibria realized under specific conditions. Since these equilibria are maintained despite a continual flux of changes in the course of generations (reshuffling of genes, reproduction…), it can legitimately be said that population genetics reveals important properties of invariance through transformation. Time-reversibility is a more controversial subject. Here, the parallel with classical mechanics is much weaker. Time-reversibility is unquestionable in some stochastic models, but at the cost of a special, probabilistic concept of reversibility. But it does not seem to be a property of the most basic deterministic models describing the dynamics of evolutionary change at the level of populations and genes. Furthermore, various meanings of ‘reversibility’ are distinguished. In particular, time-reversibility should not be confused with retrodictability.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 119.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    On the ‘historical turn’, see also Williams (1992), and Griffiths (1996). For a criticism of Beatty (1995), see Sober (1997).

  2. 2.

    Another paper, devoted to experimental biology, will be published separately.

  3. 3.

    In the simple case where the spatial coordinates are chosen so that the origins O and O′ of the two referential systems coincide for space and time. Then the three axes move along a line Ox.

  4. 4.

    In genetics , a locus is a particular position on a chromosome, occupied by a gene , which can itself exist under several alternative versions, named ‘alleles ’. The Hardy-Weinberg equilibrium applies to sexually reproducing and diploid species , where all chromosomes (except fot the sexual chromosome) exist in pairs.

  5. 5.

    Godfrey Harold Hardy did not use his first Christian name with his friends, but rather ‘Harold’ (Anthony Edwards, personal communication).

  6. 6.

    This is why Sober calls the HW principle the “zero force law of population genetics ” (Sober 1984). Gayon (1998) qualifies the Hardy-Weinberg equilibrium as an equivalent of the principle of inertia in classical mechanics (see however the conclusion of the present paper), which challenges this view.

  7. 7.

    Some of these factors modify both the gene and the genotypic composition of the population. Others (homogamy) modify only the genotypic structure.

  8. 8.

    Diallelic locus: refers to a locus with two alleles .

  9. 9.

    A zygote is a diploid cell (two stocks of chromosomes) resulting from the fusion of two haploid cells (spermatozoon and ovum), which have only one stock of chromosomes.

  10. 10.

    This kind of selection favours the mean type.

  11. 11.

    This kind of selection favours the individuals with genotype Aa. A classic example is the better resistance to malaria of individuals who are heterozygotes for the gene responsible for sickle cell anemia. Double recessives aa suffer from severe anemia and most often die at an early age; double dominant AA are much less resistant to malaria than heterozygotes Aa in areas infected by Plamodium falciparum. See Fig. 13.7.

  12. 12.

    In this kind of selection, the selective values of the genotypes depend on the allelic frequencies. This results in an intermediate equilibrium .

  13. 13.

    Here is an example: in the nineteenth century, the proliferation of melanic forms of moths in industrial regions resulted from the darkening of the bark of trees by soot: the dark forms were better protected against predation by birds. With desindustrialization, light forms replaced dark forms. This is a typical case of inversion of selective pressure.

  14. 14.

    We are very much indebted to Jean-Philippe Gayon, Anthony Edwards, Pierre-Henri Gouyon, and Michel Veuille, for their helpful interaction on this subject.

  15. 15.

    As seen in the previous paragraph, the insensitivity of the laws of classical mechanics to an inversion of time is as ‘physical’ as thermodynamic irreversibility is ‘physical’.

  16. 16.

    Strictly speaking, this observation applies to all dynamic models in population genetics , stochastic or deterministic . It is introduced here because it will be useful for a proper understanding of the examples taken in this section.

  17. 17.

    t = log(p t /p 0)/log(1–10−6), with p t  = 0.1, and p 0 = 0,9. This formula can be directly derived from the equation.

  18. 18.

    Roughgarden (1979, p. 29); Jacquard (1971, p. 241); Crow and Kimura (1970, p. 179).

  19. 19.

    Freely accessible on http://cbs.umn.edu/populus/download-populus. This application has been developed by the College of Biological Sciences of the University of Minnesota for pedagogical purposes. We thank Michel Veuille for giving us this information. For some (very) particular cases where Eq. (13.7) is analytically tractable, see Hartl ( 1980, pp. 209–210).

  20. 20.

    The reasoning that follows should be credited to Jean-Philippe Gayon, who is warmly thanked for his help.

  21. 21.

    See Crow and Kimura (1970, pp. 179–180).

  22. 22.

    The additive genetic variance is the fraction of genetic variance attributable to the additive effects of genes , ignoring the inter-allelic and inter-genotypic interactions (For detailed comments on Fisher’s fundamental theorem, see Price (1972) ; from a historical point of view, see Gayon (1998), Chap. 9).

  23. 23.

    It is worth adding that in 1941, Fisher had a controversy with Wright about the meaning of his ‘fitness function’ or ‘adaptive topography’. Commenting on this equation, Fisher wrote: ‘Wright’s conception embodied in equation (6) (Eq. (13.12) in the present paper) that selective intensities are derivable, like forces in a conservative system, from a simple potential function dependent on the gene ratios of the species as a whole, has led him to extensive but untenable speculations.’ (Fisher 1941). Thus Fisher denies that (13.12) is a potential function describing a conservative system—a position also assumed by Crow and Kimura in their 1970 textbook. However Fisher’s objection is formulated in a context where the adaptive topography is supposed to describe the behaviour of the species for all gene ratios. In reality, Wright’s equation is valid only for a diallelic locus with constant selective values (Edwards 2000). Wright acknowledged this when he gave the equation for the first time in 1937, but he eventually extended it to multi-allelic loci without providing proof. He also suggested that this equation could be related to his notion of ‘adaptive landscape’, a notion that takes into account the entire genome. Populations are then seen as pushed towards a ‘peak’ by W, the average selective value, an ever-increasing quantity (For more on this controversy, see Gayon (1998), Chap. 9). However, as noted by Edwards (2000), it is not clear at all that, even in the simplest case of a diallelic locus, W is a potential surface: ‘Wright’s mistake, repeated by Crow and Kimura , was to interpret his non-standard partial derivative ∂w/∂q i as “the slope of w in the direction where the relative frequencies of the other alleles do not change” (Crow and Kimura 1970), whereas in fact it is the rate of change of w in that direction, but with respect to change in q i alone. This is not a gradient on the w-‘surface’ at all, and the analogy of a potential function, already tenuous because of the factor q i (1–q i ), is thus in reality even more remote.’ (Edwards 2000, pp. 68–69).

  24. 24.

    The uncertainty in the age of the mother of a randomly chosen newborn.

  25. 25.

    Darwinian fitness, the efficiency with which a population acquires and converts resources into viable offspring.

  26. 26.

    Just to give an example: “In populations subject to bounded growth constraints, demographically stable states are described by the condition of maximal entropy ; in populations with unbounded growth, demographically stable states are described by the condition of minimal entropy. Under bounded growth conditions, entropy increases; under unbounded growth conditions, large population size, entropy decreases; under unbounded growth conditions, small population size, the change in entropy is random and non-directional ” (Demetrius 2000, p. 7; see also Demetrius 1992, with its explicit title, “ Growth rate, population entropy and evolutionary dynamics ”).

  27. 27.

    Hartl (1980, Figure 25, p. 212) gives a nice graphical representation of this fact, although his intention is not to comment on reversibility . The figure comprises two graphs showing the effect of selection when allele A is favoured and when allele a is favoured. In both cases \( {W}_{12}=\sqrt{W_{22}{W}_{11}} \), and several initial frequencies for A are considered. The trajectories are symmetrical.

References

  • Beatty, J. 1995. The evolutionary contingency thesis. In Concepts, theories, and rationality in the biological sciences, ed. G. Wolters and J. Lennox, 45–81. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Boltzmann, L. 1896. Vorlesungen über Gastheorie. Leipzig: Barth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandon, R. 1997. Does biology have laws? The experimental evidence. Philosophy of Science, 64, Supplement. Biennial Meetings of the Philosophy of Science Association. Part II: Symposia Papers (Dec, 1997), S444–S457.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crow, J., and M. Kimura. 1970. An introduction to population genetics theory. New York/Evanston/ London: Harper & Row, Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darwin, C. 1859. On the origin of species. London: Murray.

    Google Scholar 

  • Demetrius, L. 1992. Growth rate, population entropy and evolutionary dynamics. Theoretical Population Biology 41: 208–223.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2000. Thermodynamics and evolution. Journal of Theoretical Biology 206: 1–16.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Demetrius, L., S. Legendre, and P. Harremöes. 2009. Evolutionary entropy: A predictor of body size, metabolic rate and maximal life span. Bulletin of Mathematical Biology 71(4): 800–818.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dollo, L. 1893. Les lois de l’évolution. Bulletin de la Société Belge de géologie, paleontology, et hydrologie 7:164–166. [English translation in Gould 1970, 210–212].

    Google Scholar 

  • Edwards, A.W.F. 1977. Foundations of mathematical genetics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2000. Sewall Wright’s equation Δq = (q(1 − q)∂w/∂q)2w. Theoretical Population Biology 57: 67–70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ewens, W. 2012. James F. Crow and the stochastic theory of population genetics. Genetics 190 (2): 287–290.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fisher, R.A. 1918. The correlation between relatives on the supposition of Mendelian inheritance. Transactions of the Royal Society of Edinburgh 52: 399–433.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1941. Average excess and average effect of a gene substitution. Annals of Eugenics 11: 53–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fisher, R. 1958 [1930]. The genetical theory of natural selection, 2nd ed. Oxford/New York: Clarendon/Dover.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gayon, J. 1998. Darwinism’s struggle for survival: Heredity and the hypothesis of natural selection. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. De la portée des théories biologiques. In Problèmes théoriques et pratiques en biologie évolutionnaire, ed. T. Martin, 13–52. Besançon: Presses Universitaires de Franche Comté.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S.J. 1970. Dollo on Dollo’s law: Irreversibility and the status of evolutionary laws. Journal of the History of Biology 3 (2): 189–212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goux, J.M. 1979. Les modèles en génétique des populations. In Élaboration et justification des modèles: Applications en biologie, ed. P. Delattre and M. Thellier, vol. II, 565–571. Paris: Maloine.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, P.E. 1996. The historical turn in the study of adaptation. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 47 (4): 511–532.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haldane, J.B.S. 1954. The statics of evolution. In Evolution as a process, ed. J.S. Huxley, A.C. Hardy, and E.B. Ford, 109–121. London: Allen and Unwin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hardy, G.H. 1908. Mendelian proportions in a mixed population. Science 28: 49–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hartl, D.L. 1980. Principles of population genetics. Sunderland: Sinauer Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huneman, P. 2013. Assessing statistical views of natural selection: Is there a room for non local causation? Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences 44: 604–612.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jacquard, A. 1971. Structures génétiques des populations. Paris: Masson. [English translation: The genetic structure of populations. Springer, 1974].

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelly, F.P. 2011. Reversibility and stochastic networks. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kingman, J.F.C. 2000. Origins of the coalescent: 1974–1982. Genetics 56: 1461–1463.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewontin, R.C. 1967. The principle of historicity in evolution. In Mathematical challenges to the Neo-Darwinian interpretation of evolution, ed. P.S. Moorehead and M. Kaplan, 81–94. Philadelphia: Wistar Institute Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Li, C.C. 1955. Population genetics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longo, G., and M. Montévil. 2014. Perspectives on organisms: Biological time, symmetries and singularities. Coll. ‘Lecture notes in morphogenesis’. Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malécot, G. 1948. Les mathématiques de l’hérédité. Paris: Masson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Matthen, M., and A. Ariew. 2009. Selection and causation. Philosophy of Science 76: 201–224.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Montévil, M., and M. Mossio. 2015. Biological organisation as closure of constraints. Journal of Theoretical Biology 372: 179–191.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Price, G.R. 1972. Fisher’s ‘fundamental theorem’ made clear. Annals of Human Genetics 36: 129–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roughgarden, J. 1979. Theory of population genetics and evolutionary ecology: An introduction. New York: MacMillan Publishing Co..

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon, H. 1977. Models of Discovery. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Simpson, G.G. 1964. This view of life. New York: Harcourt, Brace and World.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sober, E. 1984. The nature of selection. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1997. Two outbreaks of lawlessness in recent philosophy of biology. Philosophy of Science, 64, Supplement. Biennial Meetings of the Philosophy of Science Association. Part II: Symposia Papers (Dec, 1997), S458–467.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walsh, D., A. Ariew, and T. Lewens. 2002. The trials of life: Natural selection and random drift. Philosophy of Science 69: 452–473.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Watterson, G.A. 1976. Reversibility and the age of an allele. I. Moran’s infinitely many neutral alleles model. Theoretical Population Biology 10: 239–253.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1977. Reversibility and the Age of an allele. II. Two-allele models, with selection and mutation. Theoretical Population Biology 12: 179–196.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, J.S., D. Depew, and J.D. Smith, eds. 1988. Entropy, information and evolution. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, N. 1908. Ueber den Nachweis der Vererbung beim Menschen. Jahreschriften des Vereins für Vaterländische Naturkunde in Württemburg 64:368–382. Translated in Boyer, S.H. (Ed.), Papers in human genetics, 4–15. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall, 1963.

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams, G.C. 1992. Natural selection: Domains, levels and challenge. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright, S. 1921. Sytems of mating. Genetics 6: 111–178.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1937. The distribution of gene frequencies in populations. Proceedings of the National Academy of Science 23: 307–320.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1940. The statistical consequences of Mendelian heredity. In The new systematics, ed. J. Huxley, 161–183. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Maël Montévil’s work is supported by a grant from the labex “Who am I?”. This paper has benefited from extensive discussion and collaboration with Jean-Philippe Gayon, who has been enormously helpful in clarifying the notion of time reversibility from a mathematical point of view. We also thank Anthony Edwards , Pierre-Henri Gouyon, and Michel Veuille. Their great competence in population genetics has been very fruitful to our understanding of the issue of reversibility in population genetics models. We also thank Edwards and Veuille or their careful reading of the text. We thank Elliott Sober for his careful reading of the paper and for his fruitful comments. Véronique Charrière is warmly thanked for her careful linguistic corrections and suggestions.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jean Gayon .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Appendices

Appendices

Appendix A.1 provides a formal definition of symmetry by time reversal and of retrodictability . Appendix A.2 applies these definitions to some population genetics models. Appendix A.3 contains the Figs. 13.3, 13.4, 13.5, 13.6 and 13.7.

1.1 Time Reversibility

As discussed in the body of the text, time reversibility corresponds intuitively to a situation where the dynamics follow the same law before and after time reversal . Only deterministic dynamics are considered here.

1.1.1 Continuous Time

In continuous time, a dynamic is typically defined by differential equations . A fairly general definition of differential equations is admitted here:

$$ 0=\mathrm{F}\left({\upalpha}_1,\dots, \mathrm{x},\mathrm{dx}/\mathrm{dt},{\mathrm{d}}^2\mathrm{x}/{\mathrm{d}\mathrm{t}}^2,\dots, {\mathrm{d}}^{\mathrm{n}}\mathrm{x}/{\mathrm{d}\mathrm{t}}^{\mathrm{n}}\right) $$
(13.13)

where the α i are parameters .

1.1.1.1 Mathematical Notion of Time Reversibility

Time reversal means substituting –t to t in an equation. Time reversibility describes situations where the equation F is still met after time reversal ; that is to say:

$$ 0=\mathrm{F}\left({\upalpha}_1,\dots, \mathrm{x},-1\times \mathrm{dx}/\mathrm{dt},{\left(-1\right)}^2{\mathrm{d}}^2\mathrm{x}/{\mathrm{d}\mathrm{t}}^2,\dots, {\left(-1\right)}^{\mathrm{n}}{\mathrm{d}}^{\mathrm{n}}\mathrm{x}/{\mathrm{d}\mathrm{t}}^{\mathrm{n}}\right) $$
(13.14)
1.1.1.2 Weaker Time Reversibility

We propose a weaker notion of time reversibility , where F is preserved even though the parameters α i are modified through time reversal . Thus, the criterion becomes:

$$ 0=\mathrm{F}\left({\upalpha}_1^{\hbox{'}},\dots, \mathrm{x},-1\times \mathrm{dx}/\mathrm{dt},{\left(-1\right)}^2{\mathrm{d}}^2\mathrm{x}/{\mathrm{d}\mathrm{t}}^2,\dots, {\left(-1\right)}^{\mathrm{n}}{\mathrm{d}}^{\mathrm{n}}\mathrm{x}/{\mathrm{d}\mathrm{t}}^{\mathrm{n}}\right) $$
(13.15)

A supplementary condition is required for this notion to have a theoretical meaning. The \( {\alpha}_i^{\hbox{'}} \) have to be possible values for the α i . For example if α 1 is a mass \( {\alpha}_1^{\hbox{'}} \) has to be a positive number, but it may be different from α 1.

1.1.1.3 Retrodictability

The Cauchy-Lipschitz theorem also called Picard–Lindelöf theorem, states that under very general hypotheses on the regularity of F, there is only one trajectory which goes through one initial condition. This theorem is the basis of the ability of the differential equation to define a deterministic process, but it also ensures that we can retrodict the past. Increasing or decreasing the time parameter makes no difference in this theorem. Note, however, that solutions to differential equations may be valid only for a limited time interval, either because a variable becomes infinite or takes a value that has no physical or biological meaning.

As mentioned in the main text, the issue of dynamics sensitive to initial conditions, such as the three-body problem in mechanics have not been discussed here. Let us just mention that in these cases, the impossibility of a perfect measurement of the initial conditions prevents empirical long term predictions and retrodictions because small differences have significant consequences.

1.1.2 Discrete Time

Dynamics defined by recurrence will now be discussed: p(t + 1) = g(p(t)).

1.1.2.1 Mathematical Notion of Time Reversibility

The transitions t to t + 1 and t + 1 to t follow the same law, that is:

$$ p(t+1)=g(p(t))\to p(t)=g(p(t+1)). $$
1.1.2.2 Weak Time Reversibility

By analogy with the continuous case, changes in the values of the parameters of g in this weaker notion of time reversibility are allowed:

\( p\left( t+1\right)= g\left( p(t),{\alpha}_i,\dots \right)\to p(t)= g\left( p\left( t+1\right),{\alpha}_i^{\hbox{'}},\dots \right) \).

Note also that the new parameters must have a physical or biological meaning.

Example: p(t + 1) = p(t)/2 → p(t) = 2p(t + 1). In this case α = 1/2 and α  = 2. See the next case for a dynamic that does not meet this criterion.

1.1.3 Retrodictability

Retrodictability corresponds to the fact that the reverse dynamic is deterministic . A system is retrodictable when a function h exists that satisfies:

$$ p\left( t+1\right)= g\left( p(t),\alpha, \dots \right)\to p(t)= h\left( p\left( t+1\right),{\alpha}^{\prime },\dots \right) $$

Function h may be completely different from g (even though they are of course related).

Example: \( p\left( t+1\right)= p{(t)}^2\to p\left( t+1\right)=\sqrt{p(t)} \). This dynamic is retrodictable but not reversible, even in the weak sense.

Counter example: p(t + 1) = 10p(t) − ⌊10p(t)⌋, where ⌊x⌋ is the integer part of x (a digit is lost at every step). For example P(0) = 0.97511 .  . ., P(1) = 0.7511 . ., P(2) = 0.511… But with P ' (0) = 0.87511 .  . ., we get P ' (1) = 0.7511…, which is identical to P(1). This ambiguity prevents defining a deterministic reversed dynamic . This deterministic dynamic does not enable retrodiction.

1.2 Application to Models of Population Genetics

In this part, the reversibility of two classical models of selection in population genetics are discussed. In one case (asexual haploid population), the dynamic is reversible in the weak sense. In the second case (diploid , diallelic locus), the dynamic is retrodictable but not reversible.

1.2.1 Asexual Haploid Population: A Weakly Reversible Model

We start with a classical model of selection at a single locus in a haploid population. W i is the relative fitness of the allele i and p i is the proportion of allele i in the population. W(t) is the average fitness of the population at time t.

$$ {\mathrm{p}}_{\mathrm{i}}\left(\mathrm{t}+1\right)={\mathrm{p}}_{\mathrm{i}}\left(\mathrm{t}\right)\frac{{\mathrm{W}}_{\mathrm{i}}}{\mathrm{W}\left(\mathrm{t}\right)} $$
(13.16)

To assess the properties of this dynamic with respect to time reversal , let us write p(t) as a function of p(t + 1), and let us compare the result with Eq. (13.16).

$$ {\mathrm{p}}_{\mathrm{i}}\left(\mathrm{t}\right)={\mathrm{p}}_{\mathrm{i}}\left(\mathrm{t}+1\right)\frac{\mathrm{W}\left(\mathrm{t}\right)}{{\mathrm{W}}_{\mathrm{i}}} $$
(13.17)

Equation (13.17) can also be written:

$$ {\mathrm{p}}_{\mathrm{i}}\left(\mathrm{t}\right)={\mathrm{p}}_{\mathrm{i}}\left(\mathrm{t}+1\right)\frac{1/{\mathrm{W}}_{\mathrm{i}}}{1/\mathrm{W}\left(\mathrm{t}\right)} $$
(13.18)

Here 1/W i seems to play the same role as W i in Eq. (13.16), therefore we can write \( {W}_i^{\hbox{'}}=1/{W}_i \). However, we have to verify whether 1/W(t) can be interpreted as the mean fitness in the reversed dynamic W(t + 1), where the new fitness coefficients are the \( {W}_i^{\hbox{'}} \).

By definition, we have:

$$ \frac{1}{\mathrm{W}\left(\mathrm{t}\right)}=\frac{\mathrm{N}\left(\mathrm{t}\right)}{\mathrm{N}\left(\mathrm{t}+1\right)}={\mathrm{W}}^{\prime}\left(\mathrm{t}+1\right) $$
(13.19)

It is also possible to do this computation on the basis of the analytical expression of \( \overline{W}(t) \) which leads to the same result. Then we can conclude that:

$$ {\mathrm{p}}_{\mathrm{i}}\left(\mathrm{t}\right)={\mathrm{p}}_{\mathrm{i}}\left(\mathrm{t}+1\right)\frac{{\mathrm{W}}_{\mathrm{i}}^{\prime }}{{\mathrm{W}}^{\prime}\left(\mathrm{t}+1\right)} $$
(13.20)

This equation has exactly the same form as Eq. (13.16). Therefore the dynamic is weakly reversible.

1.2.2 Sexual Diploid Population : A Retrodictable But Irreversible Model

A population with two alleles at a single locus is now considered. The relative fitnesses are W 11 ≠ 0 and W 22 ≠ 0 for homozygotes and W 12 for heterozygotes, and W 11 > W 12 > W 22. W(t) is the average fitness of the population. p and q are the proportions of the first and second allele in the population. A classical model for this situation is then:

$$ \mathrm{p}\left(\mathrm{t}+1\right)=\frac{{\mathrm{W}}_{11}{\mathrm{p}}^2\left(\mathrm{t}\right)+{\mathrm{W}}_{12}\mathrm{p}\left(\mathrm{t}\right)\mathrm{q}\left(\mathrm{t}\right)}{\mathrm{W}\left(\mathrm{t}\right)} $$
(13.21)

We use q(t) = 1 − p(t) and W(t) = W 11 p 2(t) + 2W 12 p(t)q(t) + W 22 q 2(t).

This leads to a quadratic equation, where p(t) is the variable :

$$ \begin{array}{l}0=\left({\mathrm{W}}_{11}-{\mathrm{W}}_{12}-\mathrm{p}\left(\mathrm{t}+1\right)\left({\mathrm{W}}_{11}-{2\mathrm{W}}_{12}+{\mathrm{W}}_{22}\right)\right){\mathrm{p}}^2\left(\mathrm{t}\right)\\ {}\kern1.76em +\left({\mathrm{W}}_{12}-\mathrm{p}\left(\mathrm{t}+1\right)2\left({\mathrm{W}}_{12}-{\mathrm{W}}_{22}\right)\right)\mathrm{p}\left(\mathrm{t}\right)-\mathrm{p}\left(\mathrm{t}+1\right){\mathrm{W}}_{22}\end{array} $$
(13.22)

The reduced discriminant determines the solutions of such an equation. If the discriminant is positive, there are two mathematical solutions and no solutions if it is negative.

$$ {\Delta}^{\prime }=\left({\mathrm{W}}_{22}{\mathrm{W}}_{11}-{\mathrm{W}}_{12}^2\right)\left(\mathrm{p}\left(\mathrm{t}+1\right)-{\mathrm{p}}^2\left(\mathrm{t}+1\right)\right)+{\mathrm{W}}_{12}^2/4 $$
(13.23)

0 ≤ p(t + 1) ≤ 1, thus (t + 1) − p 2(t + 1) > 0.

If \( \gamma ={W}_{22}{W}_{11}-{W}_{12}^2>0 \), then clearly Δ is positive. In the opposite case, it is simple to verify that the smallest possible value for Δ is given by p(t + 1) = 1/2, which leads to Δ = W 22 W 11/4 > 0. Therefore, Δ > 0 always holds and the quadratic equation has two mathematical solutions . After computation we get:

$$ \begin{array}{ll}\hfill & \kern-1.3em \mathrm{p}\left(\mathrm{t}\right)\\ {}& \kern-1.8em =\frac{\left({\mathrm{W}}_{12}-{\mathrm{W}}_{22}\right)\mathrm{p}\left(\mathrm{t}+1\right)-{\mathrm{W}}_{12}/2\pm \sqrt{\left({\mathrm{W}}_{22}{\mathrm{W}}_{11}-{\mathrm{W}}_{12}^2\right)\left(\mathrm{p}\left(\mathrm{t}+1\right)-{\mathrm{p}}^2\left(\mathrm{t}+1\right)\right)+{\mathrm{W}}_{12}^2/4}}{\mathrm{p}\left(\mathrm{t}+1\right)\left({\mathrm{W}}_{12}-{\mathrm{W}}_{22}\right)+\left({\mathrm{W}}_{11}-{\mathrm{W}}_{12}\right)\left(1-\mathrm{p}\left(\mathrm{t}+1\right)\right)}\hfill \end{array} $$
(13.24)

Because W 11 > W 12 > W 22, the denominator is always positive, and the relations between the roots and the coefficients show that the two solutions have different signs. The only solution which has biological meaning is therefore the positive solution:

$$ \frac{\mathrm{p}\left(\mathrm{t}\right)=\left({\mathrm{W}}_{12}-{\mathrm{W}}_{22}\right)\mathrm{p}\left(\mathrm{t}+1\right)-{\mathrm{W}}_{12}/2+\sqrt{\upgamma \left(\mathrm{p}\left(\mathrm{t}+1\right)-{\mathrm{p}}^2\left(\mathrm{t}+1\right)\right)+{\mathrm{W}}_{12}^2/4}}{\mathrm{p}\left(\mathrm{t}+1\right)\left({\mathrm{W}}_{12}-{\mathrm{W}}_{22}\right)+\left({\mathrm{W}}_{11}-{\mathrm{W}}_{12}\right)\left(1-\mathrm{p}\left(\mathrm{t}+1\right)\right)} $$
(13.25)
$$ \mathrm{p}\left(\mathrm{t}\right)=\mathrm{h}\left(\mathrm{p}\left(\mathrm{t}+1\right)\right) $$
(13.26)

Consider now time reversal . Equation (13.21) gives p(t + 1) as a function of p(t). This corresponds to function g in the definition of reversibility above (Appendix A.1.2). p(t + 1) = g(p(t)), is a rational function, that is to say a fraction of polynomials. When γ ≠ 0, the square root in the definition of p(t) as a function h of p(t + 1) implies that h is not a rational function. The difference between g and h is then more than just a change of coefficient. In this case, retrodiction is possible but time is not reversible in either the weak or the strong sense.

Interestingly, the case where the square root disappears, γ = 0, corresponds to \( {W}_{12}=\sqrt{W_{22}{W}_{11}} \). Thus, in this case, the fitness of heterozygotes is the geometric average of the fitnesses of homozygotes, which can be interpreted as a form of linearity in the effects of the alleles . Reciprocally, when γ ≠ 0, the change of the form of the dynamics by time reversal stems from the non-linearity in the effects of the alleles in heterozygotes .

Fig. 13.5
figure 5

Effect of selection when W 11 < W 12 = W 22 (After Jacquard 1971). This is the typical case of selection against a recessive gene. Allele 1 is disadvantaged only as homozygote, and is eliminated very slowly when rare. W always increases. Selection against a recessive gene is the most frequent case among the standard situations represented in Figs. 13.3 through 13.7. Figure 13.8 represents the shape of the trajectory of gene frequencies for this case

Fig. 13.6
figure 6

Effect of selection when W 12 < W 11 < W 22 (After Jacquard 1971). The heterozygote is disadvantaged (underdominance). There are two equilibria. Δp is either negative or positive. W always increases, but moves towards two possible stable equilibria, corresponding to p = 0 and p = 1; \( \widehat{p} \) is an unstable equilibrium , corresponding to a minimal value for W. The question is debated whether this situation is realized in nature or not, and what its biological meaning is. But it is probably a very rare case

Fig. 13.7
figure 7

Effect of selection when W 11 < W 22 = W 12 (After Jacquard 1971). Known as overdominance or ‘advantage of the heterozygote’. There are two unstable equilibria, p = 0 and p = 1, and one stable equilibrium, \( \widehat{p} \), corresponding to a maximal value for W, which always increases. Δp is either negative or positive. This is the best-known polymorphic equilibrium, with ample proof of its existence in nature

Fig. 13.8
figure 8

Selection against a recessive allele for various selective coefficients (From Roughgarden 1979). Compare with Fig. 13.5, which gives the underlying dynamics. As almost all trajectories in models of selection with discrete generations, this trajectory is obtained by computer iteration. s is the ‘selection coefficient’. The greater s, the stronger the selection against the genotype. The ‘coefficient of selection’ is a convenient way of treating the relative selective values. If the selective value of the favoured genotype(s) is 1, the selective value of the unfavoured genotype (here the recessive homozygote) is 1 – s

Fig. 13.9
figure 9

Selection with heterozygote superiority (From Roughgarden 1979). Compare with Fig. 13.7, which gives the underlying dynamics. In this example, the selection against the homozygote aa is twice as intense as the selection against AA. All trajectories converge to the same value of \( \widehat{p} \). If the two homozygotes were equally selected against, the equilibrium would be obtained for \( \widehat{p} \) = 0.5

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Gayon, J., Montévil, M. (2017). Repetition and Reversibility in Evolution: Theoretical Population Genetics. In: Bouton, C., Huneman, P. (eds) Time of Nature and the Nature of Time. Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science, vol 326. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-53725-2_13

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics