Skip to main content

Introduction: Time Between Metaphysics and Natural Sciences: From Physics to Biology

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Time of Nature and the Nature of Time

Part of the book series: Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science ((BSPS,volume 326))

Abstract

Although each scientific discipline has a specific approach to time and distinctive methodologies for implementing time in their models, pervasive issues about time still arise in all sciences, like the reality of time, the measurement of time, the definition of irreversibility and reversibility (time’s arrow), the status of the past, the notion of timescale, etc. In this introductive chapter, we claim that a comparative and interdisciplinary approach to time as it is used and represented in the natural sciences would be the most appropriate way to deal with these issues in order to provide a philosophical understanding of the time of nature. In the natural sciences, time is a crucial dimension of physics. However, we stress that “time in physics” is something of an abstraction, since “the physics” itself is nowadays a set of different disciplines working with heterogeneous models, assumptions, and experimental settings. Because of this disparity, several perspectives on time and time paradoxes emerge from various fields in physics. In addition to the controversies about the time in physics, we argue that geology, paleontology and biology should be included in the philosophical assessment of the nature of time: within these sciences, time indeed displays different properties, is investigated using very different methods and tools, and raise specific problems, many of them due to the fact that evolutionary theory is the current framework for much of biological investigation. Finally, this interdisciplinary approach leads to the question of the univocal or pluralist nature of the concept of time, which is raised in the conclusion of the chapter.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 119.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See e.g. Thomas Gold and Herman Bondi (eds.), The Nature of Time, 1967, Raymond Flood and Michael Lockwood (eds.), The Nature of Time, 1986, Dennis Dieks (ed.), The Ontology of Spacetime, 2 Vol. 2006, 2008, and most recently Craig Callender (ed.), The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Time , 2011, Adrian Bardon , The Future of the Philosophy of Time, 2012, Adrian Bardon and Heather Dyke (eds.), A Companion to the Philosophy of Time, 2013, Abhay Ashtekar , and Vesselin Petkov (eds.), Springer Handbook of Spacetime, 2014 and L. Nathan Oaklander (ed.) , Debates in the Metaphysics of Time, 2014. See also Dean Rickles and Maria Kon (eds.) Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences, Vol. 1326, Special Issue on “Flow of Time ”, October 2014.

References

  • Albert, D., and R. Galchen. 2009. A quantum threat to special relativity. Scientific American 300: 32–39.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Amundson, R. 2005. The changing role of the embryo in evolutionary thought: Roots of Evo-Devo. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Ashtekar, A., and V. Petkov, (eds.). 2014. Springer handbook of spacetime. Berlin : Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Baer, K.E. 1828. Über die Entwicklungsgeschichte der Thiere. Königsberg: Bornträger.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bardon, A. 2012. The future of the philosophy of time. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bardon, A., and H. Dyke, (eds.). (2013). A companion to the philosophy of time. Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barriel, V. 2015. Character. In Handbook of evolutionary thinking in the sciences, ed. T. Heams, P. Huneman, G. Lecointre, and M. Silberstein, 115–140. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bird, A. 2007. Nature’s metaphysics: Laws and properties. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Boltzmann, L. 1964 [1896]. Lectures on gas theory. Trans. Stephen G. Brush. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1966 [1877]. On the relation of a general mechanical theorem to the second law of thermodynamics. In Kinetic theory. Volume 2: Irreversible processes, ed. S.G. Brush, 188–193. Oxford: Pergamon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bowler, P. 1971. Preformation and pre-existence in the seventeenth century: A brief analysis. Journal of the History of Biology 4 (2): 221–244.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Boyer, C. 1949. The history of Calculus. New York: Dover Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Callender, C. (ed.). (2011). The Oxford handbook of philosophy of time. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Canguilhem, G., G. Lapassade, G. Piquemal, and J. Ullman. 1962. Du développement à l’évolution au 19ème siècle. Paris: PUF.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chang, H. 2004. Inventing temperature: Measurement and scientific progress. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Chibbaro, S., L. Rondoni, and A. Vulpiani. 2014. Reductionism, emergence and levels of reality. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Danchin, E., A. Charmontier, F.A. Champagne, A. Mesoudi, B. Pujol, and S. Blanchet. 2011. Beyond DNA: Integrating inclusive inheritance into an extended theory of evolution. Nature Reviews Genetics 12: 475–486.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Danchin, E., and A. Pocheville. 2014. Inheritance is where physiology meets evolution. Journal of Physiology 592: 2307–2317.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dawkins, R. 1982. The extended phenotype. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dieks, D. (ed.). (2006). The ontology of spacetime. Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. (ed.). (2008). The ontology of spacetime II. Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dobzhansky, Th. 1973. Nothing in biology makes sense except in the light of evolution. American Biology Teacher 35 (3): 125–129.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Duchesneau, F. 1987. Genèse de la théorie cellulaire. Paris: Vrin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dupont, J.-C. 2007. Pre-kantian revival of epigenesis: Caspar Friedrich Wolff’s De formatione intestinorum. In Understanding purpose: Kant and the philosophy of biology, ed. P. Huneman, 37–49. Rochester: University Rochester Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eddington, A. 1990. Space, time and gravitation. An outline of the general relativity theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flood, R., and M. Lockwood, (eds.). 1986. The nature of time. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gayon, J. 1998. Darwinism’s struggle for survival: Heredity and the hypothesis of natural selection. Trans. M. Cobb. Cambridge: Cambridge University press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gödel, K. 1949. A remark about the relationship between relativity theory and idealistic philosophy. In Albert Einstein: Philosopher-scientist, ed. P.A. Schilpp, 557–562. La Salle: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gold, T., and H. Bondi, (eds.) (1967). The nature of time. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gould, S.J. 1977. Ontogeny and phylogeny. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1989. Wonderful life: The burgess shale and the nature of history. New York: W. W. Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goy, I. 2014. Epigenetic theories. Caspar Friedrich Wolff and Immanuel Kant. In Kant’s theory of biology, ed. I. Goy and E. Watkins, 45–60. Berlin/New York: De Gruyter.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Grünbaum, A. 1963. Philosophical problems of space and time. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoffheimer, M.H. 1982. Maupertuis and the eighteenth century critique of pre-existence. Journal of the History of Biology 15 (1): 119–144.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hopwood, N. 2000. Producing development: The anatomy of human embryos and the norms of Wilhelm His. Bulletin of the History of Medicine 74(1): 29–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Huneman, P. 2007. Reflexive judgement and wolffian embryology: Kant’s shift between the first and the third Critique. In Understanding purpose ? Kant and the philosophy of biology, Publication Series of the North American Kant Society, ed. P. Huneman, 75–100. Rochester: University of Rochester Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huneman P., and D. Walsh, (eds.) (2017). Challenging the modern synthesis: Development, inheritance, adaptation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jablonka, E. (with Lamb, M.). 2005. Evolution in four dimensions. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kauffman, S. 1993. The origins of order: Self organization and selection in evolution. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kearl, M. 2009. Wilhelm Roux (1850–1924). Embryo project encyclopedia (2009–07-22). ISSN: 1940–5030. http://embryo.asu.edu/handle/10776/1753

  • Ladyman, J. (with Ross, Don). 2009. Every thing must go: Metaphysics naturalized. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz, G.W. 1998. The Leibniz-Clarke correspondence, ed. H.G. Alexander. Manchester: Manchester University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lenoir, T. 1982. The strategy of life. Teleology and mechanism in nineteenth century German biology. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lovejoy, A. 1936. The great chain of being: A study of the history of an idea. Harvard: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maudlin, T. 2007. The Metaphysics within physics. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Mayr, E. 1961. Cause and effect in biology. Science 134 (3489): 1501–1506.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mesoudi, A., S. Blanchet, A. Charmentier, et al. 2013. Is non-genetic inheritance just a proximate mechanism? A corroboration of the extended evolutionary synthesis. Biological Theory 7 (3): 189–195.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • North, J. 2011. Time in Thermodynamics. In The Oxford handbook of philosophy of time, ed. G. Callender, 312–350. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oaklander, L. N. (ed.). (2014). Debates in the metaphysics of time. London: Bloomsbury.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oppenheimer, J. 1967. Essays in history of embryology. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pigliucci, M., and G. Müller, (eds.) (2011). Evolution: The extended synthesis. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Price, H. 1996. Time’s arrow and Archimedes’ point. New York/Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prigogine, I. 1961. Introduction to the thermodynamics of irreversible processes. New York: Interscience.

    Google Scholar 

  • Prigogine, I. (with Nicolis, G.). 1977. Self-organization in non-equilibrium systems. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. 1967. Time and physical geometry. The Journal of Philosophy 64 (8): 240–247.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reichenbach, H. 1920. Relativitatstheorie und Erkenntnis a priori. Berlin: J. Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1928. Philosophie der Raum-Zeit-Lehre. Berlin and Leipzig: Walter de Gruyter.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1956. The direction of time. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richards, R.J. 1992. The meaning of evolution. The morphological construction and ideological reconstruction of Darwin’s theory. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rickles, D., and M. Kon, (eds.) (2014). Flow of Time. Special issue of the annals of the New York academy of sciences, 1326, 1–96.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ricoeur, P. 1984. Time and narrative. vol. 1. Trans. K. McLaughlin and P. Pellauer. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1985. Time and narrative. vol. 2. Trans. K. McLaughlin and P. Pellauer. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1988. Time and narrative. vol. 3: Narrated time. Trans. K. McLaughlin and P. Pellauer. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roe, S. 1980. Matter, life and generation. Eighteenth century embryology and the Haller-Wolff debate. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roger, J. 1963. Les sciences de la vie dans la pensée française au 18ème siècle. Paris: Albin Michel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rudwick, M.J.S. 2005. Bursting the limits of time: The reconstruction of geohistory in the age of revolution. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Scott-Phillips, T.C., et al. 2011. Evolutionary theory and the ultimate-proximate distinction in the human behavioral sciences. Perspectives on Psychological Science 6 (1): 38–47.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sklar, L. 1974. Time, space, and space-time. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1985. Philosophy and space-time Physics. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1993. Physics and chance. Philosophical issues in the foundations of statistical mechanics. Cambridge: University of Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Uffink, J. 2007. Compendium to the foundations of classical statistical mechanics. In Handbook for the philosophy of physics, ed. J. Butterfield and J. Earman, 924–1074. Amsterdam: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weyl, H. 1949. Philosophy of mathematics and natural science. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wright, S. 1932. The roles of mutation, inbreeding, crossbreeding and selection in evolution. Proceedings of the VI International Congress of Genetics 1: 356–366.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

The authors are grateful to Andrew McFarland (The City University of New York) for a thorough language check of the text.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Christophe Bouton .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Bouton, C., Huneman, P. (2017). Introduction: Time Between Metaphysics and Natural Sciences: From Physics to Biology. In: Bouton, C., Huneman, P. (eds) Time of Nature and the Nature of Time. Boston Studies in the Philosophy and History of Science, vol 326. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-53725-2_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics