Skip to main content

Poznański and Wundheiler’s ‘The Concept of Truth in Physics’: The Lvov-Warsaw School Contribution to Encyclopedism

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Significance of the Lvov-Warsaw School in the European Culture

Part of the book series: Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook ((VCIY,volume 21))

  • 234 Accesses

Abstract

This paper provides an introduction to the joint work of Edward Poznański and Aleksander Wundheiler translated in this volume as ‘The Concept of Truth in Physics’. The view they formulated in the early 1930s occupies a unique place in the heritage of the Lvov-Warsaw School—and not only on account of its non-Tarskian, operationalist conception of truth. Their image of science, focused on its fallibility, anti-foundationalism, the limitedness of empirical control, conventionalism, holism, and physicalism, exhibits a far-reaching conformity with Neurath’s encyclopedism. This paper describes the background of the Poznański-Wundheiler collaboration and the history of the reception of their ideas and then discusses the viability of their concept of truth in comparison to Neurath’s much-criticised rejection of the notion of truth altogether.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Poznański met Kotarbiński already in 1913 when he was still a pupil in Mikołaj Rej Gimnasium in Warsaw and the latter was appointed there as a classic Greek and Latin teacher.

  2. 2.

    Poznański was born into a rabbinic family but remained an atheist throughout his adult life. He was also quite negative about the term ‘national minorities’ which he thought of, it seems, as a socially disparaging description. In the multi-ethnic society of the inter-war Poland he felt neither like a Jew in a foreign country nor like a Pole with some Jewish ancestry, but rather simply as a Polish citizen. He seems to have upheld a similar attitude in Israel.

  3. 3.

    Cf. Notes (1974), p. 441; see also Jadacki (2010), p. 139.

  4. 4.

    In a letter to Kotarbiński he wrote: ‘I am the Academic Secretary of the University here, something like a Registrar in English university—I am responsible for academic administration sensu stricto, i.e., I am the secretary of the Rector, of the Senate, I am responsible for administering of teaching in the faculties […], for stipends and prizes, for the relationships between the University and the totality of students (v. uneasy task)—and I have also a good dozen of various other troubles.’ (‘Jestem Sekretarzem Akademickim Uniwersytetu, coś na kształt Registrar w uniwersytecie angielskim—jestem odpowiedzialny za administrację akademicką stricte sensu, tj. jestem sekretarzem Rektora, Senatu, jestem odpowiedzialny za administrację nauczania w wydziałach […], za stypendia i nagrody, za stosunki między Uniwersytetem i ogółem studenckim (b. niełatwe zadanie)—i mam jeszcze dobry tuzin rozmaitych innych kłopotów’), Poznański to Kotarbiński, 11-04-1952 [zbiory archiwalne Połączonych Bibliotek Wydziału Filozofii i Socjologii UW, Instytutu Filozofii i Socjologii PAN i Polskiego Towarzystwa Filozoficznego, Warszawa, Polska].

  5. 5.

    From then on this journal was published without interruption which would not have been possible without Poznański’s hard work and his connections that enabled financial support of several institutions in the 1950s (for this information we thank Eva Shorr, the Associate Editor of Iyyun).

  6. 6.

    For instance, the library of the Friends of the Hebrew University Society, which was shipped to Jerusalem in 1939, contained more than ten thousand of volumes (cf. Tentative (1946), p. 54).

  7. 7.

    Poznański stayed in touch with philosophers in Poland, especially with Tadeusz Kotarbiński and his wife, Janina (alias Dina Sztejnbarg, 1901–1997), who was a philosopher of science. Some younger scholars, like Leszek Kołakowski, Jerzy Pelc, or Henryk Skolimowski, visited Israel on his invitation.

  8. 8.

    Woleński (2007), p. 50. In 1971 in Jerusalem a two-day symposium was organized (April, 11–12) to celebrate Poznański’s seventieth birthday (cf. The Teaching, 1972). After his death a commemorative volume was issued (as a supplement to Iyyun, Vol. 25 (1974)), as well as a collection of his papers (Poznański 1980).

  9. 9.

    A short information on Wundheiler and his relatives was published in Bańkowska (2010), p. 3.

  10. 10.

    His dissertation, entitled in original: Geometria reonomiczna jako podstawa mechaniki absolutnej (1932), presented a generalized version of non-Euclidean (Riemannian) geometry; the results he obtained were published as Wundheiler (1933).

  11. 11.

    See Fifth International Congress (1939/1940), p. 371. It seems Wundheiler did not attend the next congress in Chicago 1941 (cf. Stadler 2001, pp. 391–393).

  12. 12.

    See Mancosu (2010), pp. 372–373; Awodey (2007), p. 239, fn. 23; Frost-Arnold (2013), passim; cf. also Woleński (1985), p. 29.

  13. 13.

    Excerpts of this memoir are published as L. Wundheiler (1991). They, however, do not include the passages where Alex’s journey to Europe is mentioned. In its entirety the manuscript of ‘Growing up in Nazi Germany’ is available in the United State Holocaust Memorial Museum in Washington, DC (USHMM 2009.406.1). (We thank Sofia Grachova, USHMM, for providing us with a copy of the document). Luitgard N. Wundheiler, née Albrecht-Natorp (b. 1922) was originally a German philologist (with PhD in 1948 at Marburg); she moved to US in the late 1940s, sought out Alex and married him in 1951.

  14. 14.

    L. Wundheiler, USHMM 2009.406.1, p. 48. The further details of this journey remain unknown.

  15. 15.

    Having heard about Wundheiler’s death in 1957 Karl Menger dedicated to him a paper he wrote that year (Menger 1958). Underneath the title of Wundheiler’s paper on ‘Irreversible Systems, Entropy and Riemann Spaces’ (1954) there is the following inscription: ‘Communicated by P. W. Bridgman’; the implicit recommendation by the Nobel Prize winner that this represents also indicates the high esteem in which Wundheiler’s academic work was held. Wundheiler also was a close friend of Zenon Waraszkiewicz (cf. Mioduszewski 2013, p. 135). Waraszkiewicz (1907–1946) was a topologist, known for the ‘Waraszkiewicz spirals’ which he made use of to give a negative answer to Hans Hahn’s question if there existed a universal metric continuum for which any other continuum would be a continuous image. Cf. van Dantzig et al. (1930), p. 357; Waraszkiewicz (1934).

  16. 16.

    In the 1950s Poznański, together with Bar-Hillel, translated Tarski’s Introduction to Logic and to the Methodology of the Deductive Sciences (Tarski 1941) into Hebrew.

  17. 17.

    Poznański also knew Carnap and personally communicated to him his current views while being in Prague for the 18th Zionistenkongress (21.08–04.09.1933). In the entry of 22.08.1933 Carnap wrote down in his diary: ‘Poznański from Warsaw here. (Because of a conference about the library of Jerusalem University). Recounts the seminar with Kotarbiński. He there defended his conception of the concept of truth and of testing in physics: cyclical process, an isolated sentence is not tested, but only in the system. He wants to write a paper about it, perhaps for Erkenntnis’ (‘Poznanski aus Warschau hier. (Wegen Konferenz über Jerusalemer Universitätsbibliothek). Erzählt vom Konversatorium bei Kotarbinski. Er hat dort seine Auffassung über Wahrheitsbegriff und Nachprüfung in der Physik vertreten: Kreisprozeß, nicht der einzelne Satz wird nachgeprüft, sondern nur im System. Er möchte darüber Aufsatz schreiben, vielleicht für Erkenntnis’ [ASP (RC) 025-75-11]).

  18. 18.

    The Neurath’s collection in Haarlem (NL) contains only five letters from Poznański to Neurath, four from Neurath to Poznański, two from Wundheiler to Neurath and one from Neurath to Wundheiler. Most probably some items are missing.

  19. 19.

    In one of his letters to Neurath in April, 1934, Poznański announced another paper which was, however, never published. Its subject-matter was outlined as follows: ‘Now we want to get down to the problem of pseudo-questions in physics. First it is about classification and, so to say, the categorization of various forms of physicalistic pseudo-questions and pseudo-sentences, e.g., relations without a relatum (‘Is the earth moving?’) or the creation of forbidden linkages from the legitimate terms of a theory (‘a state of an electron between two adjacent quantum orbits’) and so on. The second question which occupies us currently is the problem of technical and in principle impossibility. This question is always evaded or treated quite superficially, and for this [reason] it has fundamental meaning for various problems in methodology of physics.’ (‘Jetzt moechten wir das Problem der Scheinfragen in der Physik in Angriff nehmen. Zuerst geht es um Klassifizierung und sozusagen Kanonisierung verschiedener Formen von physikalischen Scheinfragen und Scheinsaetzen, z.B. Relation ohne Relatum („Bewegt sich die Erde?’) oder Bildung verbotener Verknuepfungen aus zulaessigen Termini der Theorie („Zustand eines Elektrons zwischen zwei benachbarten Quantenorbiten’) usw. Die zweite Frage, welche uns letztens bescheftigt [sic], das ist das Problem der technischen und der prinzipiellen Unmoeglichkeit. Diese Frage wird immer umgegangen oder ganz oberflaechlich behandelt, und dabei ist sie von grundlegender Bedeutung fuer verschiedenen Probleme der Methodologie der Physik,’ Poznański to Neurath, 08-04-1934; quoted by permission of the Wiener Kreis Stichting [WKS], Rijksarchief, Haarlem, Netherlands, all rights reserved).

  20. 20.

    Cf. Bridgman (1927); Campbell (1920). Besides Bridgman’s book in their first paper they mentioned the following sources of inspirations: Russell (1927); Eddington (1925); Eddington (1928).

  21. 21.

    Poznański developed this idea further in his (1932).

  22. 22.

    The use of the ‘method of coincidence’ phrase, widely associated with Schlick’s epistemological writings, esp. on the theory of relativity, suggests familiarity with his work as well. Cf. Schlick (1917), pp. 34–35 (English translation: Schlick (2005), pp. 49–50); Schlick (1918), pp. 234–237 (English translation: Schlick (1974), pp. 272–276). See also Glassner (2009), pp. 162 ff.

  23. 23.

    ‘This fascinating methodological problem, with which Poznański and Wundheiler were occupied here in the 30s, did not meet with any response in the works of other our logicians and methodologists, alas’ (Ajdukiewicz 1978, p. 313, translation changed). On the Vienna Circle’s protocol sentence debate see Uebel (2007). A late and off-beat response can be discerned in Ludwik Fleck’s (1935).

  24. 24.

    This volume was followed up by two other collections of papers written in honor of Kotarbiński (in 1959 and 1967).

  25. 25.

    Hempel mentioned Poznański and Wundheiler in a letter to Neurath (22-09-1938 [ASP (RC) 102-46-17]) à propos Tarski’s views on the philosophy of science. Hempel did not refer to them in his paper on truth published one year earlier (1937).

  26. 26.

    ‘Der Begriff der Wahrheit auf dem Gebiete der Physik’; undated copies exist in both the Carnap and the Neurath Nachlass [ASP (RC) 081-37-01; WKS 393/R.48]. In the mid-1930s Rand was working on her dissertation on Kotarbiński (for which she received her PhD in 1938) and this is how she could have learnt about Poznański and Wundheiler’s paper. Another possibility is that Rand summarized the paper at Neurath’s suggestion (in 1937 he wanted to hire her for preparing summaries of current Polish philosophical literature: see Neurath to Rand, 03-09-1937 [WKS]). The conjecture is that she prepared the German summary at the end of 1937 or in the first half of 1938 (see previous note). Still another possibility is that Neurath asked her earlier having learnt about the publication of the Festschrift and knowing from his meetings with Poznański and Wundheiler that they published their paper there.

  27. 27.

    And some of the Circle’s early critics, too. In his report on Studia Philosophica (a journal edited by Ajdukiewicz and Ingarden, established in 1935 to promote Polish philosophy in Western languages) Julius Weinberg (author of An Examination of Logical Positivism, 1936) mentioned the Poznański-Wundheiler paper in the context of Neurath’s proposal to replace ‘truth’ with some other term and related concerns by Popper and Reichenbach (see Weinberg 1938, p. 74, fn. 4).

  28. 28.

    Some methodological views from ‘The Concept of Truth in Physics’ were summarized in Giedymin (1986), pp. 206–209.

  29. 29.

    Already in 1936 Maria Kokoszyńska, a prominent Lvov-Warsaw School member, published a paper in defense of semantics and the ‘absolute concept of truth’ arguing against, among others, the view held by Poznański and Wundheiler (see Kokoszyńska 1936, p. 143, fn. 1).

  30. 30.

    In his early writings Neurath also talked about ‘the system of hypotheses of physics’ (cf. Neurath 1983a [1916], p. 24).

  31. 31.

    See §11 of their paper below.

  32. 32.

    Cf. ibid., §§18 and 34. Their claim that ‘sometimes we acknowledge two different and even mutually inconsistent truths (e.g., the wave and the quantum theory of light) at the same time’ (ibid., §34) should not be confused with another according to which the existence of ‘two equally formed cycles’ in physics (i.e. cycles of justification) is a mere possibility (something they found to be a consequence of their position). Such two cycles would be mutually inconsistent but ‘equally coherent and equally verified’ (ibid., §18), and the (rational) choice between them would be permanently precluded. However, they add, such situation, i.e., ‘[…] the creation of two equally probable cycles,’ is practically possible in the humanities.

  33. 33.

    Ajdukiewicz (1935), p. 151. See also Woleński (1989), pp. 444–445. Thus, the big group of those who sympathized in the inter-war Poland with the Vienna Circle accepted its general aims and postulates but remained rather skeptical about the methods of their realization.

  34. 34.

    ‘Es wirkt sehr staerkend, wenn man erfaehrt, dass Menschen aus verschieden Kreisen ganz unabhaengig voneinander zu denselben oder verwandten Ergebnissen gelangen. Da kann man doch vermuten, dass der eingeschlagene Weg richtige ist’ (Poznański to Neurath, 08-04-1934 [WKS]).

  35. 35.

    ‘Es ist sehr stärkend, so ähnliche Gedankengänge zu finden’ (Neurath to Poznański, 11-04-1934 [WKS]). Neurath also consulted Poznański on his philological interpretations of the parable of the burning bush from Exodus.

  36. 36.

    Cf. Hofmann-Grüneberg (1988), pp. 146–152; Mormann (1999); Uebel (2001), pp. 215–217; Uebel (2007), pp. 338–340; Mancosu (2008); Koterski (2010).

  37. 37.

    On the exchanges with Tarski and Kokoszyńska, see Mancosu (2008); on the exchange with Carnap, besides Koterski (2010), see Hegselmann (1985) and Mormann (1999).

  38. 38.

    In the 1950s, Poznański—in another Kotarbiński’s Festschrift and still as a follower of operationalism—wrote that his works with Wundheiler were more enthusiastic than critical and that they would require far-reaching corrections (Poznański 1959, p. 181).

  39. 39.

    Tarski introduced his book to the Polish publisher on March 21, 1931. He presented its summary already in December 1930 (cf. Tarski 1930/1931), pp. 210–211). In 1930 Tarski lectured on semantic theory of truth at least twice (in Lvov and Warsaw). He soon took care to communicate his results outside of Poland (cf. Tarski 1932, pp. 23–25). See also McFarland et al. (2014), pp. 356 and 361–363.

  40. 40.

    Poznański (2010), p. 147. This was also Neurath’s complaint about semantics. See e.g. Neurath (1983c [1937/1938]), p. 206; the vast majority of his doubts Neurath expressed in his correspondence, mainly with Carnap, Frank, Hempel, and Tarski). Neurath not only thought that semantics was useless beyond the formal domain but he was also convinced that it was dangerous for development of science and even for democracy (see Koterski 2010, §3.3).

  41. 41.

    Neurath wanted to respond to Carnap and Kokoszyńska but the plan, which he entitled ‘Wahrheit eines Satzes,’ [WKS 212/K.127] was never materialized.

  42. 42.

    Kokoszyńska (1934). This is the only written response to their work that was published in the inter-war years in Poland. The typically critical comments from Polish colleagues came after the war and often were politically motivated. Thus, the Poznański-Wundheiler paper was criticized by Marxist-Leninists who, unsurprisingly, declared it to be arch-reactionary expression of idealism and relativism (cf. Schaff 1959, pp. 434–442).

References

  • Ajdukiewicz, K. 1935. Der logistische Antiirrationalismus in Polen. Erkenntnis 5: 151–161.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1978. The Problem of Empiricism and the Concept of Meaning. In The Scientific World-Perspective and Other Essays, 1931–1963, ed. J. Giedymin (1978), 306–319. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company. (Translation of Zagadnienie empiryzmu a koncepcja znaczenia. Studia Filozoficzne, 1, 1964, pp. 3–14.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Awodey, S. 2007. Carnap’s Quest for Analyticity: The Studies in Semantics. In The Cambridge Companion to Carnap, ed. M. Friedman and R. Creath, 226–247. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Bańkowska, A. (ed.). 2010. Inwentarz zbioru ‘Spuścizna rodziny Halpersonów ([1920] 1939–1942 [2000])’. Warszawa: Archiwum Żydowskiego Instytutu Historycznego, im. Emanuela Ringelbluma. (Inventory of the Collection: The Legacy of the Halperson Family. Archive of the Emanuel Ringelblum Jewish Historical Institute.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Bridgman, P.W. 1927. The Logic of Modern Physics. New York: The Macmillan Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Campbell, N.R. 1920. Physics. The Elements. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. 1936. Testability and Meaning, p. I. Philosophy of Science 3(4): 419–471.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1937a. Testability and Meaning, p. II. Philosophy of Science 4(1): 1–40.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1937b. Logical Syntax of Language. (Translation of Logische Syntax der Sprache. Wien: Verlag von Julius Springer, 1934.).

    Google Scholar 

  • Eddington, A.S. 1925. Relativitätstheorie in mathematischer Behandlung. Berlin: Verlag von Julius Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1928. The Nature of Physical World. New York: The Macmillan Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fifth International Congress for the Unity of Science. 1939/1940. Erkenntnis 8: 369–371.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fleck, L. 1935. Entstehung und Entwicklung einer wissenschaftlichen Tatsache. Einführung in die Lehre vom Denkstil und Denkkollektiv. Basel: Benno Schwabe und Co. Verlagbuchhandlung. (Translated as Genesis and Development of a Scientific Fact, ed. T.J. Trenn and R.K. Merton. (1979). Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Frost-Arnold, G. 2013. Carnap, Tarski, and Quine at Harvard. Conversations on Logic, Mathematics, and Science. Chicago: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giedymin, J. 1986. Polish Philosophy in the Inter-War Period and Ludwik Fleck’s Theory of Thought-Styles and Thought-Collectives. In Cognition and Fact. Materials of Ludwik Fleck, ed. R.S. Cohen and T. Schnelle, 179–215. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Glassner, E. 2009. Was heißt Koinzidenz bei Schlick? In Stationen. Dem Philosophen und Physiker Moritz Schlick zum 125. Geburtstag, ed. F. Stadler and H.J. Wendel, 146–166. Wien: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hegselmann, R. 1985. Die Korrespondenz zwischen Otto Neurath und Rudolf Carnap aus den Jahren 1934 bis 1945—ein vorläufiger Bericht. In Philosophie, Wissenschaft und Aufklärung, ed. H.-J. Dahms, 276–290. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hempel, C.G. 1935. On the Logical Positivists’ Theory of Truth. Analysis 2(4): 49–59.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1937. Le problème de la vérité. Theoria 2: 206–246. (Translated as The Problem of Truth. In C. G. Hempel, Selected Philosophical Essays (pp. 35–74). R. Jeffrey (Ed.). 2000. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Hofmann-Grüneberg, F. 1988. Radikal-empiristische Wahrheitstheorie. Eine Studie über Otto Neurath, den Wiener Kreis und das Wahrheitsproblem. Wien: Hölder-Pichler-Tempsky.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jadacki, J. 2010. Edward Poznański: Warszawska Szkoła Logiczno-Filozoficzna (1918–1939). Filozofia Nauki 2(70): 139. (Edward Poznański: Warsaw Logical-Philosophical School (1918–1939), in Polish.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Kijania-Placek, K. 1998. Truth as Consensus. A Logical Analysis. In The Lvov-Warsaw School and Contemporary Philosophy, ed. K. Kijania-Placek and J. Woleński, 343–353. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2009. Nonclassical Conceptions of Truth in Polish Philosophy. In The Golden Age of Polish Philosophy: Kazimierz Twardowski’s Philosophical Legacy, ed. S. Lapointe, J. Woleński, M. Marion, and W. Miśkiewicz, 191–202. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kokoszyńska, M. 1934. Fragmenty filozoficzne. Przegląd Filozoficzny 37(2): 199–210. (Philosophical Fragments, in Polish.).

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1936. Über den absoluten Wahrheitsbegriff und einige andere semantische Begriffe. Erkenntnis 6: 143–165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Koterski, A. 2010. Neurath i semantyka. Przegląd Filozoficzny, NS 2: 211–234. (Neurath and Semantics, in Polish.).

    Google Scholar 

  • Mancosu, P. 2008. Tarski, Neurath, and Kokoszyńska on Semantic Conception of Truth. In New Essays on Tarski, ed. D. Paterson, 192–224. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2010. The Adventure of Reason. Interplay Between Philosophy of Mathematics and Mathematical Logic, 1900–1940. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Menger, K. 1958. Rates of Change and Derivatives. Fundamenta Mathematicae, 46(1): 89–102. (Reprinted in K. Menger, Selecta Mathematica, Vol. 2 (pp. 393–406), B. Schweizer, A. Sklar, K. Sigmund, P. Gruber, E. Hlawka, L. Reich & L. Schmetterer (Eds.). (2003). Wien: Springer-Verlag.)

    Google Scholar 

  • McFarland, A., J. McFarland, and J.T. Smith, ed. 2014. Alfred Tarski. Early Work in Poland—Geometry and Teaching. New York: Birkhäuser/Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mioduszewski, J. 2013. Dwie Warszawy. In Cztery szkice z przeszłości matematyki, ed. J. Mioduszewski, 123–185. Kraków: Impuls. (Two Warsaws, in Polish.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Mormann, T. 1999. Neurath’s Opposition to Tarskian Semantics. In Alfred Tarski and the Vienna Circle, ed. J. Woleński and E. Köhler, 165–178. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Neurath, O. 1983a. On the Classification of Systems of Hypotheses (With Special Reference to Optics). In Philosophical Papers 1913–1946, ed. M. Neurath and R.S. Cohen, 13–31. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company. (Translation of Zur Klassifikation von Hypothesensystemen. In Jahrbuch der Philosophischen Gesellschaft an der Universität Wien, Leipzig, 1916.)

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1983b. Individual Sciences, Unified Science, Pseudorationalism. In Philosophical Papers, ed. M. Neurath and R.S. Cohen, 132–138. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company. (Translation of Einzelwissenschaften, Einheitswissenschaft, Pseudorationalismus. In Actes du Congrès Internationale de Philosophie Scientifique, Sorbonne, Paris 1935, Fasc. I: Philosophie scientifique et empirisme logique (pp. 57–64), Paris: Herman & Cie Éditeurs, 1936.)

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1983c. Comments on the Papers by Black, Kokoszyńska, Williams. In Philosophical Papers, ed. M. Neurath and R.S. Cohen, 206–208. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company. (Translation of Zu den Vorträgen von Black, Kokoszyńska, Williams. Erkenntnis 7 (1937/1938), pp. 371–374.)

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. (sine anno). Wahrheit eines Satzes. Unpublished. (WKS 212/K.127).

    Google Scholar 

  • Notes. 1944. Bulletin of the American Mathematical Society 50(9): 658–663.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Notes and News. 1974. Philosophia 4(2/3): 441–442.

    Google Scholar 

  • Poznański, E. 1931. Bertrand Russell, Philosophie der Materie. Mathesis Polska 6(1/2): 207–209.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1932. Analiza operacyjna pojęć fizyki. Przegląd Filozoficzny 35(3/4): 209–232. (The Operational Analysis of Concepts of Physics, in Polish.)

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1959. Operacjonizm po trzydziestu latach. In Fragmenty Filozoficzne, II. Księga pamiątkowa ku uczczeniu czterdziestolecia pracy nauczycielskiej w Uniwersytecie Warszawskim profesora Tadeusza Kotarbińskiego, ed. J. Kotarbińska, M. Ossowska, J. Pelc, M. Przełęcki, and K. Szaniawski, 178–218. Warszawa: PWN. (Operationalism After Thirty Years, in Polish.)

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1980. Essays, Reviews, Reminiscences. Jerusalem: The Hebrew University Magnes Press. (In Hebrew.)

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2010. Warszawska Szkoła Logiczno-Filozoficzna (1918–1939). Filozofia Nauki 2(70): 140–150. (Warsaw Logical-Philosophical School (1918–1939), in Polish.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Poznański, E., and A. Wundheiler. 1931. Rola pojęcia koincydencji w rewizji podstaw fizyki. Mathesis Polska 6(1/2): 1–24. (The Role of the Concept of Coincidence in the Revision of the Foundations of Physics, in Polish.)

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1934. Pojęcie prawdy na terenie fizyki. In Fragmenty filozoficzne, I, Księga pamiątkowa ku uczczeniu piętnastolecia pracy nauczycielskiej w Uniwersytecie Warszawskim profesora Tadeusza Kotarbińskiego, ed. E. Geblewicz, J. Hosiassion, J. Kreczmar, M. Ossowska, St. Ossowski, A. Pański, I. Raczyńska, D. Sztejnbarg and M. Wallis-Walfisz, 97–143. Warszawa: Nakładem uczniów.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rand, R. (sine anno). Edward Poznański & Aleksander Wundheiler: Der Begriff der Wahrheit auf dem Gebiete der Physik. (Unpublished summary of Poznański & Wundheiler (1934). ASP (RC) 081-37-01; WKS 393/R.48).

    Google Scholar 

  • Rotenstreich, N. 2007. Poznański, Edward. In Encyclopaedia Judaica, Vol. 16, ed. M. Berenbaum, F. Skolnik. Detroit: Gale (2nd ed.).

    Google Scholar 

  • Rougier, L. 1935. Introduction. In Le développement du Cercle du Vienne et l’avenir de L’Empirisme logique, ed. O. Neurath. Paris: Hermann & Cie Éditeurs.

    Google Scholar 

  • Russell, B. 1927. The Analysis of Matter. London: Kegan Paul, Trench, Trubner & Co..

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaff, A. 1959. Z zagadnień marksistowskiej teorii prawdy. Warszawa: Książka i Wiedza. (Problems in the Marxist Theory of Truth, in Polish.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Schlick, M. 1917. Raum und Zeit in der gegenwärtigen Physik. Zur Einführung in das Verständnis der allgemeinen Relativitätstheorie. Berlin: Springer 1917. (Translated as Schlick, 2005.)

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1918. Allgemeine Erkenntnislehre. Berlin: Verlag von Julius Springer. (Translated as Schlick, 1974.)

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1974. General Theory of Knowledge. New York: Springer. (Translation from the 2nd revised ed., 1925, of Schlick 1918.)

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2005. Space and Time in Contemporary Physics. An Introduction to the Theory of Relativity and Gravitation. Mineola, Dover Publications, Inc. (Translation from the 2nd enlarged ed., 1920, of Schlick, 1917.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Stadler, F. 2001. The Vienna Circle. Studies in Origins, Development, and Influence of Logical Empiricism. Wien: Springer. (Translation of Studien zum Wiener Kreis. Ursprung, Entwicklung und Wirkung des Logischen Empirismus im Kontext. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1997.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Tarski, A. 1930/1931. O pojęciu prawdy w odniesieniu do sformalizowanych nauk dedukcyjnych. Ruch Filozoficzny, 12(1/10): 210–211. (Translated as On the Concept of Truth in Reference to Formalized Deductive Sciences. In A. McFarland, J. McFarland & J. T. Smith (Eds.), Alfred Tarski. Early Work in Poland—Geometry and Teaching (pp. 357–361). New York: Birkhäuser/Springer, 2014.)

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1932. Der Wahrheitsbegriff in den Sprachen der deduktiven Disziplinen. Akademie der Wissenschaften in Wien, Mathematisch-naturwissenschaftlichen Klasse, Akademischer Anzeiger 69: 23–2e5.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1933. Pojęcie prawdy w językach nauk dedukcyjnych. Warszawa: Prace Towarzystwa Naukowego Warszawskiego, Wydział III Nauk Matematyczno-Fizycznych, nr 34. (Translated from enlarged German edition of 1935 as The Concept of Truth in Formalized Languages. In Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics, ed. J. Corcoran (1983), 2nd edn., 152–278. Indianapolis: Hackett.)

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1941. Introduction to Logic and to the Methodology of the Deductive Sciences. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tentative List of Jewish Cultural Treasures in Axis-Occupied Countries. 1946. Supplement to Jewish Social Studies 8(1).

    Google Scholar 

  • The Teaching of Philosophy in Secondary Schools and Universities. Proceedings of a Symposium in Honour of Mr. E. I. J. Poznański in the Occasion of his 70th Birthday. 1972. Iyyun 23: 1–55. (In Hebrew.)

    Google Scholar 

  • Uebel, T. 2001. Carnap and Neurath in Exile: Can Their Disputes Be Resolved? International Studies in the Philosophy of Science 15(2): 211–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007. Empiricism at the Crossroads. The Vienna Circle’s Protocol-sentence Debate. Chicago: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ulam St. 1976. Adventures of a Mathematician. New York: Charles Scribner’s Sons.

    Google Scholar 

  • van Dantzig, D., K. Kuratowski, K. Menger, and H. Hahn. 1930. Problèmes. Fundamenta Mathematicae 15(1): 356–357.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waraszkiewicz, Z. 1934. Sur un problème de M. H. Hahn. Fundamenta Mathematicae 22(1): 180–205.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weinberg, J. 1936. An Examination of Logical Positivism. London: Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1938. Studia Philosophica. The Philosophical Review 47(1): 70–77.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woleński, J. 1985. Filozoficzna szkoła lwowsko-warszawska. Warszawa: PWN (The Philosophical Lvov-Warsaw School, in Polish.)

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1989. The Lvov-Warsaw School and the Vienna Circle. In The Vienna Circle and the Lvov-Warsaw School, ed. K. Szaniawski, 443–453. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1994. Some Polish Contribution to Fallibilism. In Living Doubt. Essays Concerning the Epistemology of Charles Sanders Peirce, ed. G. Debrock and M. Huskwit, 187–195. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007. Because He Admitted to Being a Jew. Cracow: The Judaica Foundation—Center for Jewish Culture.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wundheiler, A. 1933. Rheonome Geometrie. Absolute Mechanik. Prace Matematyczno-Fizyczne 40(1): 97–142.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1954. Irreversible Systems, Entropy and Riemann Spaces. Proceedings of the National Academic of Science 40(9): 844–848.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wundheiler, L. 1991. Growing Up in Nazi Germany. In Politics and Psychology: Contemporary Psychodynamic Perspectives, ed. J. Offerman-Zuckerberg, 185–206, sine loco, Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wundheiler, L., and A. Wundheiler. 1955. Some Logical Concepts for Syntax. In Machine Translation of Languages, ed. W.N. Locke and A.D. Booth, 194–207. New York: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

Archives:

  • ASP. Archives of Scientific Philosophy. Pittsburgh: Pittsburgh University.

    Google Scholar 

  • USHMM: United States Holocaust Memorial Museum, Washington, DC, USA.

    Google Scholar 

  • WKS: Wiener Kreis Stichting, Rijksarchief in Noord-Holland, Haarlem, The Netherlands.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zbiory archiwalne Połączonych Bibliotek Wydziału Filozofii i Socjologii Uniwersytetu Warszawskiego, Instytutu Filozofii i Socjologii PAN i Polskiego Towarzystwa Filozoficznego, Warszawa, Polska.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Artur Koterski .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Koterski, A., Uebel, T. (2017). Poznański and Wundheiler’s ‘The Concept of Truth in Physics’: The Lvov-Warsaw School Contribution to Encyclopedism. In: Brożek, A., Stadler, F., Woleński, J. (eds) The Significance of the Lvov-Warsaw School in the European Culture. Vienna Circle Institute Yearbook, vol 21. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-52869-4_14

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics