Skip to main content

Constitutionalism and Value-Free Method: Kelsen’s Legacy in Contemporary Challenges

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Kelsenian Legal Science and the Nature of Law

Part of the book series: Law and Philosophy Library ((LAPS,volume 118))

  • 662 Accesses

Abstract

The challenge of constitutionalization arises, first of all, from the positivization of moral principles in law, elaborated by an Enlightened rational jusnaturalism. From its inception, according to some ethical perspectives, a crisis of the artificial character of the law occurs with a concomitant dissolution of the Kelsenian legal science of positive law, whose formal paradigm is rigidly centered on procedures of authorization and competence. To this outmoded Kelsenian model are opposed theories of moral justification that invoke forms of foundational rationality and, thereby, shift the focus and emphasis from dynamic-voluntarist to static elements. It is believed that the Constitution has filled up the ‘legal space’, redrawing within the boundaries of the law the classic dialectical tension of natural law/positive law, and circumscribing, through the requirement of justification, the previously irreducible Kelsenian space of interpretative discretion. However, is constitutionalization the irreversible crisis of legal positivism and the abandonment of the methodological disenchantment of Kelsen legal science? In this chapter, the predominant conception of constitutionalization is placed into question by analyzing different strategies for the composition of legal agreements, and reemphasizing the indispensability of some central aspects of the Kelsenian tradition. The attempts to refound forms of moral objectivity, situated between procedural strategies and comprehensive ethics, contain the underlying risk of a moralization of law: a risk which can only reinforce the disorientation of contemporary jurisprudence through its preceding rejection of a disenchanted and sober reaffirmation of the rationale of legal positivism. Only the latter is able to understand the tension between law and the multiplicity of ethical viewpoints existing in our fragmented, contemporary societies, without claiming to lead them back to a universal moral point of view with a transcendental foundation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 149.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See Kelsen 1928a, for the initial formulation of this position.

  2. 2.

    As Kelsen states in the Reine Rechtslehre of 1934, “[t]he Pure Theory of Law is a theory of positive law, of positive law as such, and not of any special system of law. It is general legal theory, not an interpretation of particular national or international legal norms. As theory, the Pure Theory of Law aims solely at cognition of its subject-matter, its object. It attempts to answer the questions of what law is and how the law is made, not the questions of what the law ought to be or how the law ought to be made. The Pure Theory of Law is legal science, not legal policy. It characterizes itself as a ‘pure’ theory because it aims at cognition focused on the law alone, and because it aims to eliminate from this cognition everything not belonging to the object of cognition, precisely specified as law. That is, the Pure Theory aims to free legal science of all foreign elements” (Kelsen 2002, 6) [“La dottrina pura del diritto è una teoria del diritto positivo. Del diritto positivo semplicemente, non di un particolare ordinamento giuridico. E’ teoria generale del diritto, non interpretazione di norme giuridiche particolari, statali o internazionali. Essa, come teoria, vuol conoscere esclusivamente il suo oggetto. Essa cerca di rispondere alla domanda: che cosa e come è il diritto, non però alla domanda: come esso deve essere o deve essere costituito. Essa è scienza del diritto, non già politica del diritto. Se viene indicata come dottrina pura del diritto, ciò accade perché vorrebbe assicurare una conoscenza rivolta soltanto al diritto, e perché vorrebbe eliminare da tale conoscenza tutto ciò che non appartiene al suo oggetto esattamente determinato come diritto. Essa vuole liberare cioè la scienza del diritto da tutti gli elementi che le sono estranei” (Kelsen 1952/67, 47).

  3. 3.

    According to Kelsen, ‘validity’ coincides with Weberian ‘ideal validity’. Of course, the distinctions between the two authors are many. For a critical reading, see Bryan et al. 2015.

  4. 4.

    “The whole contrast between natural and positive law may, in a certain sense, be presented as a contrast between a static and a dynamic system of norms. To the extent that natural law theory ceases to develop its natural order according to a static principle and substitutes a dynamic one, that is, as it is impelled to introduce the principle of delegation because it has to realize itself in application to actual human conditions, it imperceptibly changes into positive law” (Kelsen 1928a, 407) [L’intera contrapposizione fra diritto naturale e diritto positivo può essere prospettata, in un certo senso, come la contrapposizione fra un sistema statico e un sistema dinamico di norme. Nella misura in cui la teoria giusnaturalistica cessa di sviluppare il suo ordinamento naturale in conformità ad un principio statico, e ve ne sostituisce uno dinamico, cioè nella misura in cui è costretta ad introdurre il principio di delegazione, perché deve realizzarsi applicandosi alle effettive condizioni umane, essa muta impercettibilmente in un diritto positivo”.],

  5. 5.

    “In this respect law is like King Midas: just as everything he touched turned to gold, so everything to which the law refers assumes a legal character. Within the legal order, nullity is only the highest degree of annullability” (Kelsen 1960, 309–310) [“A questo riguardo il diritto è come re Mida: come tutto ciò che questi toccava si tramutava in oro, così tutto ciò cui il diritto si riferisce assume carattere giuridico. Nell’ordinamento, la nullità è soltanto il massimo grado di annullabilità”]. According to Kelsen, it would be not correct to require the annulment of an act created by an individual who in no way is invested with public authority; and, at the same time, it would not be possible to consider as non-existent each act produced in breach of the competence principle (Kelsen 1928b, 163–164).

  6. 6.

    The original theoretical manifesto of the theories of legal reasoning is assumed to be that of Aarnio et al. 1981.

  7. 7.

    In Alexy’s re-elaboration, the principle of universalization of moral judgments, as elaborated by Hare, together with the Habermasian universal pragmatics, in which the pragmatic transcendental foundation becomes that of a procedural requirement for the discursive formation of the political will through the democratic process assumes the status of a hypothetical negative criterion for normative statements (Alexy 1978, Italian Edition, 154.). This strategy of effectively undermining the Habermasian rationalist foundation, by the consideration of the mere counterfactual character of the ideal linguistic, also overcomes the utopian feature of such a project and allows us to circumnavigate the risk of a sacralisation of the democratic process implicit in the abstraction of the particularism produced by moral argumentation. However, that strategy seems to call into play, by recovering the logical foundation of a universal ethics, typically a combination of utilitarian prescriptivism, particularistic and subjective elements (Hare 1981, 1997), risking to undermine the generalizing Kantian element in the various forms of the legal justification. On these aspects and, more generally, on the risks related to variations of the principle of universalization in the procedural strategies, see Giordano 2012.

  8. 8.

    In the sense accorded to it by the analyses of Schmitt 1960.

  9. 9.

    “A book of jurisprudence can have but one or the other of two objects:

    1. To ascertain what the law is: 2. To ascertain what it ought to be. In the former case, it may be styled a book of expository jurisprudence; in the latter, a book of censorial jurisprudence: or, in the other words, a book on the art of legislation” (Bentham 1988, 324).

  10. 10.

    In this view, defeasibility of practical reasoning seems to resort to evaluative concepts, inevitably based on a thesis of ultimate irreducible relevance. For a particularistic reading, see Dancy 1999, Celano 2006. Concerning the limits of a stabilized decision of moral reasoning, derived from the implication of ethical concepts, see Naughton and Rawling 2000; McDowell 1998; Crisp 2000. Concerning the incommensurability of moral reasons, see Shafer-Landau 1997. Concerning the derivation of particularism from an analytical, epistemological and methodological viewpoint, see Sinnott-Armstrong 1999. For a deeper understanding of defeasibility, in the direction of epistemic contextualism, see Lance and Little 2004; on defeasible conditionals, see the foundational analyses of Alchourrón 1996, Moreso 2002. Concerning the conceptual opposition between universalism and particularism, as ideal models of practical reasoning, see Redondo 2005, 448. On the exclusionary nature of legal reasons, see Raz 1990.

  11. 11.

    See, Catania 2008, 22.

References

  • Aarnio, Aulis. 1987. The Rational as Reasonable. A Treatise on Legal Justification. Dordrecht/Boston/Lancaster/Tokyo: Reidel.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aarnio, Aulis, Alexy Robert, and Aleksander Peczenik. 1981. The Foundation of Legal Reasoning. Rechstheorie 12.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aarnio Aulius, Alexy Robert, Peczenik, Aleksander, Rabinowicz Wlodek and Wolenski, Jan. 1998. On Coherence Theory of Law. Juristförlaget I. Lund: Lund, January.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alchourrón, Carlos E. 1996. Para una lógica de las razones prima facie. Análisis filosófico 16: 113–124.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy, Robert. 1978. Theorie der juristichen Argumentation. Die Theorie des razionalen Diskurses als Theorie der juristischen Begründung. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag. Italian edition: Alexy, Robert. 1998. Teoria dell’argomentazione giuridica. La teoria del discorso razionale come teoria della motivazione giuridica. Trans. M. Latorre. Milan: Giuffrè.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1986. Theorie der Grundrechte. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp. English edition: Alexy, Robert 2002. A Theory of Constitutional Rights. Trans. J. Rivers. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1992. Begriff und Geltung des Rechts. Freiburg im Breisgau-München: Verlag Karl Alber GMBh. Italian edition: Alexy, Robert. 1997. Concetto e validità del diritto. Trans. F. Fiore. Turin: Einaudi.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1999. My Philosophy of Law: The Institutionalisation of Reason. In The Law in Philosophical Perspectives, edited by L.J. Wintgens, 23–45. Dordrecht/Boston/London: Kluwer Academic.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2003. On Balancing and Subsumption. A Structural Comparision. Ratio Juris 16: 433–449.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2009. Hauptelemente einer Theorie der Doppelnatur des Rechts. Archiv für Rechts- und Sozialphilosophie 95: 151–166.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barberis, Mauro. 2012. Il neocostituzionalismo, terza filosofia del diritto. Rivista di filosofia del diritto 1: 153–164.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bentham, Jeremy. 1988. The Principles of Morals and Legislation. Buffalo: Prometheus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bratman, Michael. 1992. Shared Cooperative Activity. Philosophical Review 101: 327–341.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bryan, Ian, Peter Langford, and John McGarry, eds. 2015. The Foundation of the Juridico-Political: Concept Formation in Kelsen and Weber. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bobbio, Noberto. 1966. Principi generali del diritto. Novissimo Digesto italiano XIII: 886–896.

    Google Scholar 

  • Catania, Alfonso. 1997. Acceptance in the Thought of H.L.A. Hart. In Law and Language: The Italian Analytical School, edited by A. Pintore and M. Jori, 147–163. Liverpool: Deborah Charles Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2008. Metamorfosi del diritto. Decisione e norma nell’età globale. Rome-Bari: Laterza.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013. Diritto naturale e diritto positivo nella tradizione occidentale. Costituzione e diritti umani. In Effettività e modelli di diritto, edited by V. Giordano, 33–148. Turin: Giappichelli.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bruno, Celano. 2006. Pluralismo etico, particolarismo e caratterizzazioni di desiderabilità: il mod-ello triadico. Ragion Pratica 1: 133–150.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coleman, Julius. 1982. Negative and Positive Positivism. The Journal of Legal Studies 11: 139–164.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2001a. The Practice of Principle. In Defence of a Pragmatist Approach to Legal Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2001b. Incorporationism Conventionality and the Practical Difference Thesis. In Hart’s Postscript. Essay on the Postscript to the Concept of Law, edited by J. Coleman, 123–147. Cambridge: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Crisp, Roger. 2000. Particularizing Particularism. In Moral Particularism, edited by B. Hooker and M. Little, 23–47. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dancy, Jonathan. 1999. Defending Particularism. Metaphilosophy 30: 25–32.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, Ronald. 1977. Taking Rights Seriously. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1978. Is There No Right Answer in Hard Cases? New York University Law Review 53/ I. Re-edited in Dworkin Ronald. 1985. A Matter of Principle. Cambridge Mass.: Harvard University Press. Italian translation: Dworkin, Ronald 1990. Questioni di principio. 147–178. Milan: Il Saggiatore.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1986. Law’s Empire. Cambridge (MA): Harvard University Press. Italian edi- tion: Dworkin Ronald. 1989. L’impero del diritto. (trans: Caracciolo di San Vito L.). Milan: Il Saggiatore.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1996. Freedom’s Law, The Moral Reading of The American Constitution. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2006. Justice in Robes. Cambridge (Mass): The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press. Italian edition: Dworkin, Ronald 2010. Giustizia in toga. Rome-Bari: Laterza.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2011. Justice for Hedgehogs. Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ferrajoli, Luigi. 2007. Principia Iuris, Teoria del diritto e della democrazia. Vol. 1 and 2. Laterza: Rome- Bari.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1998. Diritto e Ragione, Teoria del garantismo penale. Rome-Bari: Laterza.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fioravanti, M. 2009. Constitutionalism. In A Treatise of Legal Philosophy and General Jurisprudence, Vol.9 A History of Law in the Civil Law World 1600–1900, edited by D. Canale, P. Grossi, and H. Hofmann, 263–300. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Giordano, Valeria. 2004. Il positivismo e la sfida dei principi. Naples: ESI.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2012. Le teorie del ragionamento giuridico. Divaricazioni, ambivalenze, dilemmi. Ars Interpretandi 1: 103–121.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, Jürgen. 1983. Moralbewuβtsein und kommunikatives Handeln. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp Verlag. Italian edition: Habermas, Jürgen. 1993. Etica del discorso. Roma-Bari: Laterza.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hare, Richard M. 1952. The Language of Morals. London: Oxford University Press. Italian edition: Hare, Richard M. 1968. Il linguaggio della morale. Rome: Ubaldini.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1981. Moral Thinking. New York: Oxford University Press. Italian edition: Hare Richard M. 1989. Il pensiero Morale. Livelli, metodi, scopi. Bologna: Il Mulino.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1997. Sorting Out Ethics. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press. Italian Edition: Hare, Richard M. 2006. Scegliere un’etica. Bologna: Il Mulino.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart, Herbert L.A. 1961. The Concept of Law. London: Oxford University Press. Italian Edition (trans: Cattaneo, M.): Hart, Herbert L.A. 1965. Il concetto di diritto. Turin: Einaudi.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1994. The Concept of Law 2nd ed. with a Postscript edited by Penelope A. Bulloch and Josef Raz. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelsen, Hans. 1928a. Die philosophischen Grundlagen der Naturrechtslehre und des Rechtspositivismus. Italian translation: Kelsen, Hans. 1952. La dottrina del diritto naturale ed il positivismo giuridico, 395–454. Appendix to Teoria Generale del diritto e dello Stato.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelsen, H. 1928b. La garantie Jurisdictionnelle de la Constitution (La justice constitutionnelle). Rev. Dr.publ.et sc. Pol. XXXV: 197–257. Italian edition: Kelsen, H. 1981. La garanzia giuris- dizionale della Costituzione (la giustizia costituzionale). In La giustizia costituzionale, Hans Kelsen Milan: Giuffrè.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelsen, Hans. 1930–1931. Wer Soll de Hüter der Verfassung sein. Die Justice, Italian Edition: Kelsen, H. 1981. “Chi deve essere il custode della Costituzione”. In La giustizia costituzionale, edited by Hans Kelsen, 229–291. Milan: Giuffrè.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1934. Reine Rechtslehre. Einleitung in die rechtswissenschaftliche Problematik. Leipzig/Vienna: Verlang Franz Deuticke. Italian Edition: Kelsen, H. 1952. La dottrina pura del diritto (trans: Treves, R.) Turin: Einaudi. (Re-edited 1967 with the title Lineamenti di dot- trina pura del diritto.)

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1945. General Theory of Law and State. Cambridge Mass: Harvard University Press. Italian Edition: Kelsen, Hans. 1952. Teoria generale del diritto e dello Stato. Milan: Etas.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1960. Reine Rechtslehre. Vienna: Verlag Franz Deuticke. Italian Edition: Kelsen, H. 1966. La dottrina pura del diritto (trans: Losano, M.G.). Turin: Einaudi.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2002. Introduction to the Problems of Legal Theory (trans: Paulson, Bonnie Litschewski and Paulson, Stanley L). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lance, Mark, and Little Margaret. 2004. Defeasibility and the Normative Grasp of Context. Erkenntnis 61: 435–455.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, John Henry. 1998. Mind Value and Reality. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacCormick, N. 1978. Legal Reasoning and Legal Theory. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Italian translation: MacCormick, N. 2001. Ragionamento giuridico e teoria del diritto (trans: Schiavello, A.). Turin: Giappichelli.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marmor, Andrei. 2001. Legal Conventionalism. In Hart’s Postcript. 193–217.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moreso, Josè Juan. 2001. In defence of Inclusive Legal Positivism. In The Legal Ought, edited by P. Chiassoni, 37–63. Turin: Giappichelli.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2002. Conflitti fra principi costituzionali. Ragion Pratica 18: 201–221.

    Google Scholar 

  • Naughton, David, and J. Piers Rawling. 2000. Unprincipled Ethics. In Moral Particularism, edited by B. Hooker and M. Little, 265–275. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Peczenik, Aleksander. 1989. On Law and Reason. Dordrecht/Boston/London: Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Raz, Joseph. 1979. The Authority of Law. Essays on Law and Morality. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1999. Practical Reason and Norms. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Redondo, M. Cristina. 2005. Ragioni e norme. Ragion pratica 25: 439–468.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shafer-Landau, Russ. 1997. Moral Rules. Ethics 107: 584–611.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, Scott. 2002. Law, Plans, and Practical Reasons. Legal Theory 8: 387–441.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2011. Legality. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schmitt, Carl. 1960. Die Tyrannei der Werte. Stuttgart: W. Kohlhammer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sinnott-Armstrong, Walter. 1999. Some Varieties of Particularism. Metaphilosophy 30: 1–12.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Waluchow, Wilfrid J. 1994. Inclusive Legal Positivism. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weber, Max. 1917/1949. The Meaning of ‘Ethical Neutrality’ in Sociology and Economics. In The Methodology of the Social Sciences, edited by E.A. Shils and H.A. Finch, 1–47. New York: Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zagrebelsky, Gustavo. 1992. Il diritto mite. Legge, diritti, Giustizia. Turin: Einaudi.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Valeria Giordano .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Giordano, V. (2017). Constitutionalism and Value-Free Method: Kelsen’s Legacy in Contemporary Challenges. In: Langford, P., Bryan, I., McGarry, J. (eds) Kelsenian Legal Science and the Nature of Law. Law and Philosophy Library, vol 118. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-51817-6_6

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-51817-6_6

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-51816-9

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-51817-6

  • eBook Packages: Law and CriminologyLaw and Criminology (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics