Skip to main content

Kelsen and the Necessity of God in the Natural-Law Doctrine

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 649 Accesses

Part of the book series: Law and Philosophy Library ((LAPS,volume 118))

Abstract

In this chapter, I examine Kelsen’s contention that the natural law doctrine necessarily depends on the existence of God or other supreme creator. I argue that this contention is based on a number of interrelated claims: that the natural law doctrine attempts to provide a definitive standard of justice; that such a definitive account may only be posited by a superhuman creator; that natural law seeks to derive principles of justice from the nature of reality; and that natural law norms may only be derived from a general norm posited by God, moreover, if natural lawyers deny the claim that the principles of natural law may only be derived from God, they must necessarily be attempting to derive an ought from an is. Throughout the chapter, I challenge Kelsen’s claims by considering natural law theories which do not conform to them. I consequently argue that Kelsen’s conception of natural law is a caricature which does not correspond to, or accurately reflect, the rich and varied tradition of natural law thought.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   149.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See, also, ‘Only under this presupposition [i.e.: that a divine will is inherent in nature] is it possible to maintain the doctrine that the law can be deduced from nature and that this law is absolute justice’ (1949: 485); and ‘Above the imperfect positive law created by man a perfect, because absolutely just, natural law exists, established by divine authority’ (1949:485).

  2. 2.

    He also writes that the natural-law doctrine ‘may deny the jurisdiction of [the tribunal of science] by referring to its religious character’ (1949: 485), thereby implying that religious based assertions are not suitable for scientific (i.e.: objective) evaluation.

  3. 3.

    It is noteworthy that Kelsen quotes Grotius’ view that acts may be prohibited or encouraged ‘by the authority of nature, God’ and that the ‘essential traits implanted in man’, from which we may derive laws of nature ‘can rightly be attributed to God’ (1949: 482) but that he does not mention Grotius’ assertion that his account of natural law would be valid if God did not exist.

  4. 4.

    We reach the same conclusion if we use Dworkin’s own definition of the ‘less extreme “natural law” theories [which] claim only that morality is sometimes relevant to the truth of propositions of law. They suggest, for instance, that when a statute is open to different interpretations … whichever interpretation is morally superior is the more accurate statement of the law’ (1986: 36.). And, again, if we adopt d’Entrèves’ formulation that ‘Perhaps the best description of natural law is that it provides a name for the point of intersection between law and morals’ (1965: 116.)

  5. 5.

    Bodenheimer also appears to see this as being firmly within the natural law tradition: ‘The natural-law approach … considers prevailing convictions, widely accepted ideals and the “reason of the age” as legitimate supplementary sources of law-finding …’ (1950: 342).

  6. 6.

    See Sect. 13.5.

  7. 7.

    He also writes that this ‘line of argument … amounts to the negation of natural law by natural law’ (1949: 486).

  8. 8.

    Elsewhere, Dworkin similarly writes: ‘Coherence is the best protection against discrimination’ (2006: 250). Rawls appears to concur (1999: 209).

  9. 9.

    Bodenheimer agrees that it is inherent within the natural law doctrine that certain kinds of human behaviour should be regulated to ensure the survival of society: ‘According to natural-law doctrine, the rational side of our nature teaches us that without restrictions on homicide organized society cannot exist’ (1950: 346).

  10. 10.

    As a point of interest, Dworkin suggests that those in the original position who would choose the two principles of justice that Rawls claims they would – the so-called liberty and difference principles – rather than, say, utilitarianism, would also naturally choose interpretivism (i.e.: integrity) as a ‘better bet to achieve justice … in the long run’ (2006: 249).

  11. 11.

    For example, using Gadamer (1989), I would argue that any attempt to abstract ourselves from our life circumstances is itself conditioned by those circumstances, by our effective history, so that the veil of ignorance is an artifice governed by our cultural and life contingencies. Indeed, a number of writers have detected evidence of bias in Rawls’ original position (Freeman 2014: 486–487).

  12. 12.

    Hart similarly writes that ‘Natural Law is part of an older conception of nature’ which assumes that the natural world has a teleological purpose (1994: 188–189).

  13. 13.

    It is worth observing that this supposition is reminiscent of his pure theory of law whereby each norm of a legal system derives from a higher norm. To be sure, it is, in part, Kelsen’s assertion that we cannot rely on a meta-norm – whether derived from God or nature – that leads him to posit a basic norm, the Grundnorm, which must be presupposed (2002: 201–205).

  14. 14.

    As a point of interest, Dworkin states that the existence of God would not, in itself, evade what he calls Hume’s principle’ (that moral values cannot be derived from facts). The ‘scientific fact’ of God’s existence, like any other fact, does not ‘justify a particular conviction of value’ without some additional ‘background principle’ to explain why (Dworkin 2013: 21–29).

  15. 15.

    Moreover, Fuller argues that the positivists’ attempt to divorce law from morality, to become ‘pure science’, means that they fail to have anything significant to say about the content of the law and, thereby, their usefulness as legal theorists is limited (Fuller 1966: 85–95).

References

  • Bix, Brian H. 2002. Natural Law: The Modern Tradition. In Oxford Handbook of Jurisprudence and Philosophy of Law, edited by Jules L. Coleman and Scott Shapiro, 61–103. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bodenheimer, Edgar. 1950. The Natural-Law Doctrine Before the Tribunal of Science: A Reply to Hans Kelsen. The Western Political Quarterly 3: 335–363.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Brooks, Thom. 2007. Between Natural Law and Legal Positivism: Dworkin and Hegel on Legal Theory. Georgia State University Law Review 23 (3): 513–560.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cicero, Marcus T. 1998. The Republic and the Laws. Translated by N. Rudd. Oxford World Classics, Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crowe, Michael B. 1977. The Changing Profile of Natural Law. The Hague: BRILL.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • d’Entrèves Alexander, P. 1994. Natural Law: An Introduction to Legal Philosophy. 2nd ed. New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, Ronald. 1982. “Natural” Law Revisited. University of Florida Law Review 34: 165–188.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1986. Law’s Empire. London: Fontana Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2006. Justice in Robes. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013. Religion Without God. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Finnis, John. 1980. Natural Law and Natural Rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fuller, Lon L. 1958. A Rejoinder to Professor Nagel. Natural Law Forum 3: 83–104.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1966. The Law in Quest of Itself. Boston: Beacon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Freeman, Michael D.A. 2014. Lloyd’s Introduction to Jurisprudence. 9th ed. London: Sweet & Maxwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gadamer, Hans-Georg. 1989. Truth and Method. 2nd edn. Translated by Joel Weinsheimer and Donald G. Marshall. London: Sheed & Ward.

    Google Scholar 

  • George, Robert P. 2004. Kelsen and Aquinas on the Natural Law Doctrine. In St. Thomas Aquinas and the Natural Law Tradition: Contemporary Perspectives, edited by John Goyette, Mark S. Latkovic, and Richard S. Myer, 237–259. Washington, DC: The Catholic University of America Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldsworthy, Jeffrey. 1996. Fact and Value in the New Natural Law Theory. American Journal of Jurisprudence 41 (1): 21–46.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guest, Stephen. 2009. How to Criticize Ronald Dworkin’s Theory of Law. Analysis 62: 352–364.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hart, Herbert L.A. 1994. The Concept of Law. 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, David. 2006. In Moral Philosophy, edited by Geoffrey Sayre-MaCord. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelsen, Hans. 1949. The Natural-Law Doctrine Before the Tribunal of Science. The Western Political Quarterly 2: 481–513.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1971. What is Justice: Justice, Law and Politics in the Mirror of Science: Collected Essays. Berkley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2002. Pure Theory of Law. 2nd edn. Translated by Max Knight. Clark: The Lawbook Exchange.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nederman Cary J. 1994. Introduction. In Alexander. P. d’Entrèves Natural Law: An Introduction to Legal Philosophy. 2nd edn. New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, John. 1999. A Theory of Justice. Revised ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2001. In Justice as Fairness: A Restatement, edited by Erin Kelly. London: Belknap Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Summers, Robert S. 1984. Lon L. Fuller. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgement

I am grateful to my co-editors, Dr. Peter Langford and Dr. Ian Bryan, for their comments and suggestions on an earlier version of this chapter; any errors remain my own.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to John McGarry .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

McGarry, J. (2017). Kelsen and the Necessity of God in the Natural-Law Doctrine. In: Langford, P., Bryan, I., McGarry, J. (eds) Kelsenian Legal Science and the Nature of Law. Law and Philosophy Library, vol 118. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-51817-6_13

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-51817-6_13

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-51816-9

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-51817-6

  • eBook Packages: Law and CriminologyLaw and Criminology (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics