Skip to main content

Discourse Particles as CCP-modifiers: German doch and ja as Context Filters

  • Conference paper
  • First Online:
New Frontiers in Artificial Intelligence (JSAI-isAI 2015)

Part of the book series: Lecture Notes in Computer Science ((LNAI,volume 10091))

Included in the following conference series:

  • 1250 Accesses

Abstract

This paper proposes an analysis of declaratives with the German discourse particles doch and ja as context change potentials (CCPs), imposing restrictions on input and output contexts consisting of public beliefs of the discourse participants. The analysis accounts for a wider range of data than previous approaches and makes novel predictions on the distribution of doch and ja by defining public beliefs as independent of fist-order beliefs, and modeling the difference between ja and doch in terms of whether a public belief of the addressee is presupposed (ja), or not (doch).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Possible expansion to other illocutionary forces is briefly discussed in Sect. 5.

  2. 2.

    I write \(\varphi \) for the “prejacent” (the proposition of the particle utterance), \(\psi \) for the “antecedent” (the proposition of the antecedent utterance).

  3. 3.

    For space, I do not mention uses where there is propositional contrast between \(\varphi \) and \(\psi \), but both hold, which can be understood as cases of blocked defeasible inference. As they allow ja-declaratives, I consider them a sub-category of acceptances.

  4. 4.

    As a sentential adverb/discourse connective, the additive particle auch indicates that the prejacent is (additional) justification for believing some proposition asserted, similar to English “after all”.

  5. 5.

    Typical continuations include questions, in (3) for example “Tell me, how many languages are there?”, to which the addressee is likely to know the answer if the prejacent holds, and elaborations on the prejacent on part of the speaker.

  6. 6.

    This label is borrowed from Karagjosova (2004), who however includes reminders in case the speaker has no reason to assume that the prejacent is an inactive belief.

  7. 7.

    Zimmermann includes the truth of the prejacent in the paraphrases which I leave out as it is not relevant for the expressive meaning component I am concerned with.

  8. 8.

    Other than perceived similarities, the fact that their contributions become indistinguishable when they co-occur in the same utterance supports such a connection.

  9. 9.

    This wording is possibly biased, but reflects the widely accepted observation that doch and ja do not alter the truth conditions of utterances, but add felicity conditions which depend on the utterance’s propositional content.

  10. 10.

    She does not, however, take this relation to be part of doch’s meaning, but makes use of it to explain the interpretation of rejections with doch.

  11. 11.

    This is logically equivalent to \(\varphi \rightarrow \lnot \psi \) and thus a variant of contextual contrast.

  12. 12.

    Egg takes both the defeasible entailment relation and the salient element to be defeasibly deducible from the context set.

  13. 13.

    Grice and Baumann give two examples for its use which they paraphrase “self-evident statement”, and “involved or sarcastic statement”[5, 295, translation my own], which I assume represents typical uses of the contour rather than its meaning.

  14. 14.

    Explicit beliefs are the core of an agents set of beliefs in Wassermann’s model in the sense that they form the basis for reasoning.

  15. 15.

    In Wassermann’s articulated model of belief states, explicit beliefs can be either active or inactive, so that the set the speaker believes \(\varphi \) to be part of in (12) is a subset of the corresponding set in (11).

  16. 16.

    I will remain neutral in regard to the necessity of valuation of public beliefs against worlds and thus in regard to both the question of whether a Stalnakerian analysis of the common ground is preferable for what doch and ja operate on.

  17. 17.

    The symbols have been modified from the original; Gunlogson refers to speaker and addressee as the two discourse participants. Furthermore, she uses the propositions representing these beliefs to construct discourse commitments, which will not be necessary for the present purposes as no validation of propositions takes place.

  18. 18.

    This assumption may not be uncontroversial, parallel to positive introspection for knowledge, but I do not see any obstacle to make this simplification for the present analysis.

  19. 19.

    I use the propositional symbol \(\varphi \) here for simplicity, but the same goes for belief states.

  20. 20.

    This is possibly too weak an assumption for modeling the effect of assertions on contexts, see Sect. 4.4 for discussion.

  21. 21.

    “If [Peter] has been sick for a while (= \(\varphi \)), then (normally) he looks bad. (= \(\psi \))”.

  22. 22.

    How use-conditional content or presuppositions can be compared parallel to logical strength of truth conditional content is beyond the scope of this paper, but see the comparison of presuppositions in Sect. 4.1 above.

  23. 23.

    While this assumption glosses over a number of possible complications in an analysis of tag questions, the details are orthogonal to the question tag’s making the notion of “confirming nuance” more concrete and testable against intuitions.

References

  1. Asher, N., Lascarides, A.: Logics of Conversation. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (2003)

    Google Scholar 

  2. Bárány, A.: Form and interpretation of the German discourse particles ja, doch and wohl. Master’s thesis, Universität Wien (2009)

    Google Scholar 

  3. Davis, C.: Constraining interpretation: Sentence final particles in Japanese. Ph.D. thesis, University of Massachusets, Amherst (2011)

    Google Scholar 

  4. Egg, M.: A unified account of the semantics of discourse particles. In: Proceedings of SIGDIAL 2010, pp. 132–138 (2010)

    Google Scholar 

  5. Grice, M., Baumann, S.: Deutsche intonation und GToBI. Linguistische Ber. 191, 267–298 (2002)

    Google Scholar 

  6. Grosz, P.: German doch: an element that triggers a contrast presupposition. Proc. CLS 46, 163–177 (2010)

    Google Scholar 

  7. Gunlogson, C.: True to form: Rising and falling declaratives as questions in English. Ph.D. thesis, UCSC (2003)

    Google Scholar 

  8. Gutzmann, D.: Use-conditional meaning: Studies in multidimensional semantics. Oxford Unviersity Press, Oxford (2015)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  9. Karagjosova, E.: Meaning and function of German modal particles. Ph.D. thesis, Universität des Saarlandes (2004)

    Google Scholar 

  10. Kaufmann, M., Kaufmann, S.: Epistemic particles and performativity. Proc. SALT 22, 208–225 (2012)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  11. Lindner, K.: ‘Wir sind ja doch alte Bekannte’. The use of German ja and doch as modal particles. In: Abraham, W. (ed.) Discourse Particles: Descriptive and theoretical investigations on the logical, syntactic and pragmatic properties of discourse particles in German, pp. 163–201. John Benjamins, Amsterdam (1991)

    Google Scholar 

  12. Ormelius-Sandblom, E.: Die Modalpartikeln ja, doch und schon. Zu ihrer Syntax, Semantik und Pragmatik. Almqvist & Wiksell International, Stockholm (1997)

    Google Scholar 

  13. Wassermann, R.: Resource-Bounded Belief Revision. Ph.D. thesis, University of Amsterdam (2000)

    Google Scholar 

  14. Zimmermann, M.: Discourse particles. In: von Maienborn, C., von Heusinger, K., Portner, P. (eds.) Semantics: An International Handbook of Natural Language Meaning, vol. 2, pp. 2012–2038. Mouton de Gruyter, Berlin (2011)

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I thank Magda and Stefan Kaufmann for thorough discussion of and helpful comments on an earlier version, the audience at LENLS for comments, and Daisuke Bekki and Eric McCready for encouraging me to participate.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Lukas Rieser .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this paper

Cite this paper

Rieser, L. (2017). Discourse Particles as CCP-modifiers: German doch and ja as Context Filters. In: Otake, M., Kurahashi, S., Ota, Y., Satoh, K., Bekki, D. (eds) New Frontiers in Artificial Intelligence. JSAI-isAI 2015. Lecture Notes in Computer Science(), vol 10091. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-50953-2_8

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-50953-2_8

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-50952-5

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-50953-2

  • eBook Packages: Computer ScienceComputer Science (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics