Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Philosophy and Politics - Critical Explorations ((PPCE,volume 3))

  • 572 Accesses

Abstract

The concept of human rights remains a challenging concept and some of its aspects have yet to be further explored. As James Griffin notes in the introduction to his book, On Human Rights, there is a common “belief that we do not yet have a clear enough idea of what human rights are.” In a similar vein, Michael Rosen observes that “Human rights are obviously deeply puzzling— almost everyone nowadays professes commitment to them, yet few people would claim that they had a good, principled account of what they are and why we have them.” Following this same line of thought, Charles Beitz writes, “the problem is that, although the idea and the language of human rights have become increasingly prominent in public discourse, it has not become any more clear what kinds of objects human rights are supposed to be, why we should believe that people have them, or what follows from this belief for political practice.”

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    James Griffin, On Human Rights (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008), 1.

  2. 2.

    Michael Rosen, Dignity: Its History and Meaning (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2012), 54.

  3. 3.

    Charles Beitz, The Idea of Human Rights, (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2009), xii.

  4. 4.

    Jack Donnelly, Universal Human Rights in Theory and Practice, 3rd ed. (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2013), 55.

  5. 5.

    David Ingram, Habermas: Introduction and Analysis (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 2010), 176.

  6. 6.

    Rainer Forst, Justification and Critique: Towards a Critical Theory of Politics (Malden: Polity Press, 2014), 69.

  7. 7.

    Allen Buchanan, The Heart of Human Rights (New York: Oxford University Press, 2013), 10.

  8. 8.

    Ernst Bloch, Natural Law and Human Dignity, cited by Habermas, The Crisis of the European Union: A Response (Malden: Polity Press, 2012), 95.

  9. 9.

    Makau Mutua, Human Rights: A Political and Cultural Critique (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 2002), ix.

  10. 10.

    Ibid., xi.

  11. 11.

    Mutua uses this metaphor (savage-victim-savior) to question the Western discourse on human rights. He argues that “the main authors of the human rights discourse, including the United Nations, Western states, international nongovernmental organizations, and senior Western academics, constructed this three-dimensional prism” (p. 10) in order to impose Western culture and values on non-Western countries. The first dimension of the prism is the savage, which is the state. The real savage, argues Mutua, is not the state but a cultural deviation from human rights… The state itself is a neutral, passive instrumentality that conveys savagery by implementing the project of the savage culture (p. 11). Thus, he continues, when human rights norms target a deviant state, they are really attacking the normative cultural fabric of variant expressed by that state. The culture, and not the state, is the actual savage. From this perspective, human rights violations represent a clash between the culture of human rights and the savage culture (p. 23). The second dimension of the prism is the victim. The victim is a human being whose “dignity and worth” have been violated by the savage. In human rights literature, writes Mutua, the victim is usually presented as a helpless innocent who has been abused directly by the state, its agents, or pursuant to an offensive cultural or political practice… A basic characteristic of the victim is powerlessness, an inability for self-defense against the state or the culture in question (p. 28). For Mutua, “the metaphor of the victim is the giant engine that drives the human rights movements. Without the victim there is no savage or savior, and the entire human rights enterprise collapses” (p. 27). The third dimension of the prism is the savior, or the redeemer, the good angel who protects, vindicates, civilizes, restrains, and safeguards. The savior promises freedom from the tyrannies of the state, tradition, and culture. In the human rights story, he contends, the savior is the human rights corpus itself, with the United Nations, Western governments, INGOs, and Western charities as the actual rescuers, redeemers of a benighted world (p.11). According to Mutua, in the human rights narrative, savages and victims are generally nonwhite and non-Western, while the saviors are white (p.14). For him, the metaphor of the savior is constructed through two intertwining characteristics: Eurocentric universalism and Christianity’s missionary zeal (p. 31).

  12. 12.

    Makau Mutua, Human Rights, 7.

  13. 13.

    Mutua, Humain Rights, 15.

  14. 14.

    Ibid., 34.

  15. 15.

    Here I use “burdened societies” in its Rawlsian sense. That is, societies whose historical, social, [political], and economic circumstances make their achieving a well-ordered regime, whether liberal or decent, difficult if not impossible. See John Rawls, The Law of Peoples (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1999), 90.

  16. 16.

    Henry Shue, Basic Rights: Subsistence, Affluence, and U.S. Foreign Policy (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1996), 52.

  17. 17.

    The “other” here is to be understood in its Habermasian sense. For Habermas, inclusion does not imply locking members into a community that closes itself off from others. The “inclusion of the other” means rather that the boundaries of the community are open for all, also and most especially for those who are strangers to one another and want to remain strangers (Jurgen Habermas, The Inclusion of the Other, xxxvi).

  18. 18.

    Jürgen Habermas, On the Pragmatics of Communication, ed. M. Cooke (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1998b), 326.

  19. 19.

    David Ingram, Habermas: Introduction and Analysis, 137–8.

  20. 20.

    Ingram, Habermas: Introduction and Analysis, 50.

  21. 21.

    BFN, 107.

  22. 22.

    Ingeborg Maus, “Liberties and Popular Sovereignty: On Jurgen Habermas’s Reconstruction of the System of Rights,” in Cardozo Law Review, Vol. 17 (1995–1996): 833–34.

  23. 23.

    Translator’s Introduction, BFN, xxv.

  24. 24.

    Hugh Baxter, Habermas: The Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2011), 66.

  25. 25.

    Baxter, Habermas: The Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy, 66.

  26. 26.

    Ibid.

  27. 27.

    Jurgen Habermas, “Human Rights and Popular Sovereignty: The Liberal and Republican Versions,” in Ration Juris, vol.7, issue 1 (March 1994): 1.

  28. 28.

    I.O, 190.

  29. 29.

    Thomas Pogge, “The International Significance of Human Rights,” in The Journal of Ethics, vol. 4, no.1/2 (Jan. – Mar., 2000): 46.

  30. 30.

    Thomas Pogge, World Poverty and Human Rights (Malden: Polity Press, 2008), 66.

  31. 31.

    Rainer Forst, The Right to Justification (New York: Columbia University Press, 2007), 109.

  32. 32.

    Ibid., 101.

  33. 33.

    Jon Mahoney, “Rights without dignity? Some critical reflections on Habermas’s procedural model of law and democracy,” in Philosophy and Social Criticism, vol.27, n.3 (May 2001): 22.

  34. 34.

    Ibid., 23.

  35. 35.

    David Ingram, Habermas: Introduction and Analysis, 177.

  36. 36.

    Ibid.

  37. 37.

    I.O, 190.

  38. 38.

    Ibid., 191.

  39. 39.

    Jürgen Habermas, “The Concept of Human Dignity and the Realistic Utopia of Human Rights,” in Metaphilosophy, vol. 41, no. 4 (July 2010), 464.

  40. 40.

    David Ingram, Habermas: Introduction and Analysis, 178.

  41. 41.

    Habermas, “The Concept of Human Dignity,” footnote 10, p. 470.

  42. 42.

    Ibid.

  43. 43.

    BFN, 84.

  44. 44.

    Pogge, “The International Significance of Human Rights,” 46.

  45. 45.

    Ibid., 49.

  46. 46.

    I.O, 190.

  47. 47.

    Pogge, “The International Significance of Human Rights,” 49, footnote 8.

  48. 48.

    Ibid., 50.

  49. 49.

    BFN, 449.

  50. 50.

    I.O, 245.

  51. 51.

    Habermas, “The Concept of Human Dignity,” 464.

  52. 52.

    Ibid.

  53. 53.

    Jeremy Waldron, Dignity, Rank, and Rights (New York: Oxford University Press, 2012), 15.

  54. 54.

    Michael Rosen, “Dignity Past and Present,” in Jeremy Waldron, Dignity, Rank, and Rights, 81.

  55. 55.

    George Kateb, Human Digntiy (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 2011), 5.

  56. 56.

    Hugh Baxter, Habermas: The Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy, 181.

  57. 57.

    I.O, 182.

References

  • Baxter, Hugh. 2011. Habermas: The Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2009. The Idea of Human Rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Buchanan, Allen. 2013. The Heart of Human Rights. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Donnelly, Jack. 2013. Universal Human Rights in Theory and Practice, 3rd ed. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Forst, Rainer. 2007. The Right to Justification: Elements of a Constructivist Theory of Justice. New York: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. Justification and Critique: Towards a Critical Theory of Politics. Malden: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffin, James. 2008. On Human Rights. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, Jürgen. 1986. “Law and Morality,” In The Tanner Lectures on Human Values. Salt Lake City: Harvard University, October.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, Jürgen. 1994. Human Rights and Popular Sovereignty: The Liberal and Republican Versions. Ratio Juris 7(1): 1–13.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1996. Between Facts and Norms. Contributions to a Discourse Theory of Law and Democracy. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1998a. In The Inclusion of the Other: Studies in Political Theory, ed. Ciaran Cronin and Pablo De Greiff. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1998b. In On the Pragmatics of Communication, ed. M. Cooke. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1999. Introduction to the Seminar on Jürgen Habermas’s Discourse Theory. Ratio Juris 12(4): 329–335.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2010. The Concept of Human Dignity and the Realistic Utopia of Human Rights. Metaphilosophy 41(4): 464–480.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2012. The Crisis of the European Union: A Response. Malden: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ingram, David. 2010. Habermas: Introduction and Analysis. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kateb, George. 2011. Human Digntiy. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mahoney, Jon. 2001. Rights Without Dignity? Some Critical Reflections on Habermas’s Procedural Model of Law and Democracy. Philosophy and Social Criticism. 27(3): 21–40.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maus, Ingeborg. 1995. Liberties and Popular Sovereignty: On Jürgen Habermas’s Reconstruction of the System of Rights. Cardozo Law Review 17: 825.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mutua, Makau. 2002. Human Rights: A Political and Cultural Critique. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pogge, Thomas. 2000. The International Significance of Human Rights. The Journal of Ethics 4(1/2): 45–69.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2008. World Poverty and Human Rights. Malden: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, Michael. 2012. Dignity: Its History and Meaning. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2012b. Dignity Past and Present. In Dignity, Rank, and Rights, ed. Jeremy Waldron. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shue, Henry. 1996. Basic Rights: Subsistence, Affluence, and U.S. Foreign Policy, 2nd ed. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Waldron, Jeremy. 2012. Dignity, Rank, and Rights. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013. Is Dignity the Foundation of Human Rights?. New York University Public Law and Legal Theory Working Papers, paper 374.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Moka-Mubelo, W. (2017). Introduction. In: Reconciling Law and Morality in Human Rights Discourse. Philosophy and Politics - Critical Explorations, vol 3. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-49496-8_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics