Skip to main content

Multiple-Aggregate Games

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Theory of Externalities and Public Goods

Abstract

Consider an environment in which individuals are organised into groups, they contribute to the collective action of their group, and are influenced by the collective actions of other groups; there are externalities between groups that are transmitted through the aggregation of groups’ actions. The theory of ‘aggregative games’ has been successfully applied to study games in which players’ payoffs depend only on their own strategy and a single aggregation of all players’ strategies, but the setting just described features multiple aggregations of actions—one for each group—in which the nature of the intra-group strategic interaction may be very different to the inter-group strategic interaction. The aim of this contribution is to establish a framework within which to consider such ‘multiple aggregate games’; present a method to analyse the existence and properties of Nash equilibria; and to discuss some applications of the theory to demonstrate how useful the technique is for analysing strategic interactions involving individuals in groups.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 149.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Elsewhere this is called the ‘cumulative best reply’ (Selten 1970), the ‘inclusive reaction function’ (Wolfstetter 1999) and the ‘backward reaction correspondence’ (Novshek 1985).

  2. 2.

    A downside of the share function approach is that attention must be restricted to non-null equilibria in which X j > 0, and whether a null equilibrium also exists considered separately. Where a null equilibrium is considered it is referred to explicitly, reserving ‘Nash equilibrium’ for an equilibrium in which some individuals are active.

  3. 3.

    The justification for this definition comes from thinking about replacement functions. If X i j(X j) = 0 for all i ∈ I j then the replacement function is defined for all X j ≥ 0, and will take the value zero at X j = 0 (since by definition the replacement value must not exceed X j). Taking the sum of these replacement functions (of which a fixed point is sought), if the slope at X j ≈ 0 does not exceed 1 (which is intimately related to the condition stated in Proposition 4) then (given share functions are decreasing) it will never exceed 1, and so the only fixed point will be at X j = 0.

  4. 4.

    Note, however, that ‘group payoff functions’ are not defined, so the ideas of supermodular games need only be applied to group best responses. An interesting line of inquiry lies in considering whether, for each group, a payoff function can be defined that, when optimised over the choice of group aggregate (taking the aggregates of other groups as fixed) identifies the same group aggregate as that at the Nash equilibrium within the group. This requires the partial game to be a ‘potential game’ (Monderer and Shapley 1996), study of which would be an interesting alternative approach to that taken here.

  5. 5.

    With more than two groups and a desire for uniqueness of equilibrium when the game does not have the features of a nested aggregative game (see below), the approach of Rosen (1965) might be appealed to.

  6. 6.

    Note that an individual’s effort choice determines both their contribution to the collective effort in the inter-group contest, and their action in the intra-group contest. This is different to sequential inter- and intra-group conflict, where first individuals in groups secure a rent via their collective action in a contest between groups; and then individuals within each group (or just in the winning group in a winner-take-all contest) seek to appropriate the group’s rent with a separate strategic choice (see, for example, Katz and Tokatlidu 1996).

  7. 7.

    For simplicity, it is assumed that endowments are large enough that they will never be constraining and so are ignored in the definition of strategy sets, and in the analysis.

  8. 8.

    If either X 1 = 0 or X 2 = 0, no trader receives anything from the market.

  9. 9.

    Whilst individual share functions very smoothly in their arguments, the aggregation of these within a group, whilst continuous, does not necessarily vary in a smooth way, in particular in a neighborhood of a group member’s ‘dropout value’ \(\bar{X}_{i}^{\,j}(\mathbf{X}^{-j})\). As such, implicit differentiation should not be used at these points on the domain but, with apology, it is given its intuitive merit. In a neighborhood of any \(\bar{X}_{i}^{\,j}(\mathbf{X}^{-j})\) the derived derivatives do not hold and indeed should not be defined; the monotonicity properties can nevertheless be proved for these regions of the domain by a contradictory argument (details omitted).

References

  • Acemoglu, D., & Jensen, M. K. (2013). Aggregate comparative statics. Games and Economic Behavior, 81, 27–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Amir, R., & Bloch, F. (2009). Comparative statics in a simple class of strategic market games. Games and Economic Behavior, 65(1), 7–24.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Baik, K. H. (2008). Contests with group-specific public-good prizes. Social Choice and Welfare, 30(1), 103–117.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chung, T.-Y. (1996). Rent-seeking contest when the prize increases with aggregate efforts. Public Choice, 87(1–2), 55–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Corchon, L. C. (1994). Comparative statics for aggregative games the strong concavity case. Mathematical Social Sciences, 28(3), 151–165.

    Google Scholar 

  • Corchón, L. C. (2007). The theory of contests: A survey. Review of Economic Design, 11(2), 69–100.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cornes, R., & Hartley, R. (2000). Joint production games and share functions. Mimeo.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cornes, R., & Hartley, R. (2007). Aggregative public good games. Journal of Public Economic Theory, 9(2), 201–219.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cornes, R., & Hartley, R. (2012). Fully aggregative games. Economics Letters, 116(3), 631–633.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cornes, R., Hartley, R., & Nelson, D. (2005). Groups with intersecting interests. Mimeo.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cornes, R. C., Hartley, R., & Tamura, Y. (2010). Two-aggregate games: A method of analysis and an example. Mimeo.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dickson, A. (2013). On Cobb-Douglas preferences in bilateral oligopoly. Recherches économiques de Louvain, 79(4), 89–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dickson, A., & Hartley, R. (2008). The strategic Marshallian cross. Games and Economic Behavior, 64(2), 514–532.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Esteban, J., & Ray, D. (2001). Collective action and the group size paradox. American Political Science Review, 95, 663–672. Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gabszewicz, J., & Michel, P. (1997). Oligopoly equilibrium in exchange economies. In B. Eaton & R. Harris (Eds.), Trade, technology and economics: Essays in honor of Richard G. Lipsey (pp. 217–240). Cheltenham: Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jensen, M. K. (2010). Aggregative games and best-reply potentials. Economic Theory, 43(1), 45–66.

    Google Scholar 

  • Katz, E., Nitzan, S., & Rosenberg, J. (1990). Rent-seeking for pure public goods. Public Choice, 65(1), 49–60.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Katz, E., & Tokatlidu, J. (1996). Group competition for rents. European Journal of Political Economy, 12(4), 599–607.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kolmar, M., & Rommeswinkel, H. (2013). Contests with group-specific public goods and complementarities in efforts. Journal of Economic Behavior and Organization, 89, 9–22.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Konrad, K. A. (2009). Strategy and dynamics in contests. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Monderer, D., & Shapley, L. S. (1996). Potential games. Games and Economic Behavior, 14(1), 124–143.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nitzan, S. (1991). Collective rent dissipation. The Economic Journal, 101(409), 1522–1534.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nitzan, S., & Ueda, K. (2014). Intra-group heterogeneity in collective contests. Social Choice and Welfare, 43(1), 219–238.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Novshek, W. (1985). On the existence of Cournot equilibrium. The Review of Economic Studies, 52(1), 85–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, J. B. (1965). Existence and uniqueness of equilibrium points for concave n-person games. Econometrica, 33(3), 520–534.

    Google Scholar 

  • Selten, R. (1970). Preispolitik der Mehrproduktenunternehmung in der statischen Theorie. Berlin: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shapley, L., & Shubik, M. (1977). Trade using one commodity as a means of payment. The Journal of Political Economy, 85(5), 937–968.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vives, X. (1990). Nash equilibrium with strategic complementarities. Journal of Mathematical Economics, 19(3), 305–321.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wolfstetter, E. (1999). Topics in microeconomics: Industrial organization, auctions, and incentives. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Alex Dickson .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Appendix: Proofs

Appendix: Proofs

Proof of Proposition 1

The proof is by simple definition chasing. If x is a Nash equilibrium in \(\mathcal{G}\), then by definition \(x_{i}^{\,j{\ast}} =\tilde{ x}_{i}^{\,j}(\mathbf{X}^{-j{\ast}})\) for all i ∈ I j, j ∈ J. But then for each j ∈ J, \(X^{j{\ast}} =\sum _{i\in I^{j}}\tilde{x}_{i}^{\,j}(\mathbf{X}^{-j{\ast}}) =\tilde{ X}^{j}(\mathbf{X}^{-j{\ast}})\). Conversely, if \(X^{j{\ast}} =\tilde{ X}^{j}(\mathbf{X}^{-j{\ast}})\) for all j ∈ J, then by definition x j where \(x_{i}^{\,j{\ast}} =\tilde{ x}_{i}^{\,j}(\mathbf{X}^{-j{\ast}})\) for each i ∈ I j is a Nash equilibrium in \(\mathcal{G}^{j}(\mathbf{X}^{-j{\ast}})\) for all j ∈ J; it then follows that x is a Nash equilibrium. □ 

Proof of Proposition 2

The proof is again by definition chasing. First, if x j is a Nash equilibrium then x i j = b i j(X i j; X j) for all i ∈ I j. This implies x i j = b i j(X jx i j; X j), and so by definition x i j = r i j(X j; X j) for all i ∈ I j; and therefore \(\sum _{i\in I^{j}}r_{i}^{\,j}(X^{j{\ast}};\mathbf{X}^{-j}) = X^{j{\ast}}\). To prove necessity, suppose \(\sum _{i\in I^{j}}r_{i}^{\,j}(X^{j{\ast}};\mathbf{X}^{-j}) = X^{j{\ast}}\) and consider the strategy x i j = r i j(X j; X j). By definition of the replacement function, x i j = b i j(X jx i j; X j), and since \(X^{j{\ast}} =\sum _{i\in I^{j}}r_{i}^{\,j}(X^{j{\ast}};\mathbf{X}^{-j})\) it follows that \(X^{j{\ast}}- x_{i}^{\,j{\ast}} =\sum _{h\neq i\in I^{j}}r_{h}^{j}(X^{j{\ast}};\mathbf{X}^{-j}) = X_{-i}^{j{\ast}}\). As such, x i j = b i j(X i j; X j) for all i ∈ I j, so x j is a Nash equilibrium in \(\mathcal{G}^{j}(\mathbf{X}^{-j})\). □ 

Proof of Proposition 3

A player’s share function is the value of σ i j that makes l i j, defined in (5), equal to 0—however, if this is below zero the share function is defined as zero; and if it is above 1 the share function is undefined. First, note that under Assumption 1

$$\displaystyle\begin{array}{rcl} \frac{\partial l_{i}^{\,j}} {\partial \sigma _{i}^{\,j}} & = X^{j}\left [ \frac{\partial ^{2}u_{ i}^{\,j}} {\partial (x_{i}^{\,j})^{2}} + \frac{\partial ^{2}u_{ i}^{\,j}} {\partial x_{i}^{\,j}\partial X_{-i}^{j}}\right ] < 0\ \text{ and}& {}\\ \frac{\partial l_{i}^{\,j}} {\partial X^{j}}& =\sigma _{ i}^{\,j} \frac{\partial ^{2}u_{ i}^{\,j}} {\partial (x_{i}^{\,j})^{2}} + [1 -\sigma _{i}^{\,j}] \frac{\partial ^{2}u_{ i}^{\,j}} {\partial x_{i}^{\,j}\partial X_{-i}^{j}} < 0.& {}\\ \end{array}$$

The first inequality implies there is at most one σ i j ∈ [0, 1] where l i j = 0 so the share function is indeed a function. Continuity of this function, where it is defined, follows from l i j varying continuously in all its arguments by virtue of the assumed differentiability of utility functions.

If X i j(X j) > 0, by definition, l i j(1, X i j(X j); X j) = 0, so s i j(X i j(X j), X j) = 1 and the monotonicity properties just stated imply that for all X j < X i j(X j), l i j > 0 for all σ i j ≤ 1, and therefore the share function is undefined. In addition, again by definition, if \(\bar{X}_{i}^{\,j}(\mathbf{X}^{-j}) < \infty \) then \(l_{i}^{\,j}(0,\bar{X}_{i}^{\,j}(\mathbf{X}^{-j});\mathbf{X}^{-j}) = 0\) so \(s_{i}^{\,j}(\bar{X}_{i}^{\,j}(\mathbf{X}^{-j});\mathbf{X}^{-j}) = 0\) and the monotonicity properties of l i j imply that for all \(X^{j} >\bar{ X}_{i}^{\,j}(\mathbf{X}^{-j})\), l i j = 0 only when σ i j < 0, and therefore by definition s i j(X j; X j) = 0.

Where it is positive and defined, implicit differentiation of the first-order condition that defines the share function, (5), gives

$$\displaystyle{ \frac{\partial s_{i}^{\,j}} {\partial X^{j}} = -\frac{\frac{\partial l_{i}^{\,j}} {\partial X^{j}}} {\frac{\partial l_{i}^{\,j}} {\partial \sigma _{i}^{\,j}} } < 0, }$$

where the inequality follows from the deductions above.

If X i j(X j) = 0 the share function is defined for all X j > 0 where it takes values in the compact set [0, 1], so (taking subsequences if necessary) the limit as X j → 0 will exist, which is denoted \(\bar{s}_{i}^{\,j}(\mathbf{X}^{-j})\). □ 

Proof of Proposition 4

If \(\bar{X}_{i}^{\,j}(\mathbf{X}^{-j}) < \infty \) the share function of individual i ∈ I j is equal to zero for all \(X^{j} \geq \bar{ X}_{i}^{\,j}(\mathbf{X}^{-j})\). If not, then since it is assumed that \(\lim _{x_{i}^{\,j}\rightarrow \infty }\frac{\partial u_{i}^{\,j}(x_{ i}^{\,j},\cdot;\cdot )} {\partial x_{i}^{\,j}} < 0\) the first-order condition (5) can hold as X j →  only if \(\lim _{X^{j}\rightarrow \infty }\sigma _{i}^{\,j}X^{j} < \infty \) which requires σ i j → 0, implying the share function vanishes in the large X j limit. This implies there is an \(\bar{x}^{\,j}(\mathbf{X}^{-j})\) such that \(\sum _{i\in I^{j}}s_{i}^{\,j}(X^{j};\mathbf{X}^{-j}) < 1\) for all \(X^{j} >\bar{ x}^{\,j}(\mathbf{X}^{-j})\). The function \(\sum _{i\in I^{j}}s_{i}^{\,j}(X^{j};\mathbf{X}^{-j})\) is continuous and strictly decreasing in X j for all \(\max _{i\in I^{j}}\{\underline{X}_{i}^{\,j}(\mathbf{X}^{-j})\} < X^{j} <\bar{ x}^{\,j}(\mathbf{X}^{-j})\), and is therefore equal to 1 for at most one value of X j. If X i j(X j) > 0 for any i ∈ I j then \(\sum _{i\in I^{j}}s_{i}^{\,j}(\max _{i\in I^{j}}\{\underline{X}_{i}^{\,j}(\mathbf{X}^{-j})\},\mathbf{X}^{-j}) \geq 1\) and so there is a unique value of X j where \(\sum _{i\in I^{j}}s_{i}^{\,j}(X^{j},\mathbf{X}^{-j}) = 1\). If X i j(X j) = 0 for all i ∈ I j then the aggregate share function is defined for all X j > 0, with \(\lim _{X^{j}\rightarrow 0}\sum _{i\in I^{j}}s_{i}^{\,j}(X^{j},\mathbf{X}^{-j}) =\sum _{i\in I^{j}}\bar{s}_{i}^{\,j}(\mathbf{X}^{-j})\). As such, the existence of a (unique) Nash equilibrium requires \(\sum _{i\in I^{j}}\bar{s}_{i}^{\,j}(\mathbf{X}^{-j}) > 1\). □ 

Proof of Proposition 5

For \(\mathbf{X}^{-j} \in \mathbb{R}_{+}^{N-1}\setminus \bar{\mathcal{X}}^{j}\), the group best response is implicitly defined by (7). Continuity of the group best response follows from continuity of individual share functions in each of its arguments, which follows from the assumed differentiability of utility functions. With apologyFootnote 9 implicit differentiation of (7) gives

$$\displaystyle{ \frac{\partial \tilde{X}^{j}(\mathbf{X}^{-j})} {\partial X^{k}} = -\frac{\sum _{i\in I^{j}} \frac{\partial s_{i}^{\,j}} {\partial X^{k}}} {\sum _{i\in I^{j}}\frac{\partial s_{i}^{\,j}} {\partial X^{j}}}. }$$
(10)

Where an individual’s share function is positive, recall that it is defined by the first-order condition l i j(σ i j, X j; X j) = 0 as in (5). As deduced previously,

$$\displaystyle{ \frac{\partial s_{i}^{\,j}} {\partial X^{j}} = -\frac{\frac{\partial l_{i}^{\,j}} {\partial X^{j}}} {\frac{\partial l_{i}^{\,j}} {\partial \sigma _{i}^{\,j}} } = \frac{\sigma _{i}^{\,j} \frac{\partial ^{2}u_{ i}^{\,j}} {\partial (x_{i}^{\,j})^{2}} + [1 -\sigma _{i}^{\,j}] \frac{\partial ^{2}u_{ i}^{\,j}} {\partial x_{i}^{\,j}\partial X_{-i}^{j}}} {X^{j}\left [ \frac{\partial ^{2}u_{i}^{\,j}} {\partial (x_{i}^{\,j})^{2}} - \frac{\partial ^{2}u_{i}^{\,j}} {\partial x_{i}^{\,j}\partial X_{-i}^{j}}\right ]} < 0 }$$

under Assumption 1. In addition,

$$\displaystyle{ \frac{\partial s_{i}^{\,j}} {\partial X^{k}} = -\frac{\frac{\partial l_{i}^{\,j}} {\partial X^{k}}} {\frac{\partial l_{i}^{\,j}} {\partial \sigma _{i}^{\,j}} } = - \frac{ \frac{\partial ^{2}u_{ i}^{\,j}} {\partial x_{i}^{\,j}\partial X^{k}}} {X^{j}\left [ \frac{\partial ^{2}u_{i}^{\,j}} {\partial (x_{i}^{\,j})^{2}} - \frac{\partial ^{2}u_{i}^{\,j}} {\partial x_{i}^{\,j}\partial X_{-i}^{j}}\right ]}. }$$

Since the denominator is negative under Assumption 1, \(\mathop{\mathrm{sgn}}\nolimits \{ \frac{\partial s_{i}^{\,j}} {\partial X^{k}}\} =\mathop{ \mathrm{sgn}}\nolimits \{ \frac{\partial ^{2}u_{ i}^{\,j}} {\partial x_{i}^{\,j}\partial X^{k}}\}\). As such, since group members are qualitatively symmetric, it follows that \(\mathop{\mathrm{sgn}}\nolimits \{ \frac{\partial \tilde{X}^{j}(\mathbf{X}^{-j})} {\partial X^{k}} \} =\mathop{ \mathrm{sgn}}\nolimits \{ \frac{\partial ^{2}u_{ i}^{\,j}} {\partial x_{i}^{\,j}\partial X^{k}}\}\), as stated.

\(\left \vert \frac{\partial \tilde{X}^{j}(\mathbf{X}^{-j})} {\partial X^{k}} \right \vert < 1\) if the numerator in (10) is less than the denominator, a sufficient (but by no means necessary) condition for which is \(\left \vert \frac{\partial s_{i}^{\,j}} {\partial X^{k}}\right \vert < \left \vert \frac{\partial s_{i}^{\,j}} {\partial X^{j}}\right \vert \) for all i ∈ I j, which is implied by the inequality in the proposition. □ 

Proof of Proposition 6

If x is a Nash equilibrium, then by definition of share functions \(x_{i}^{\,j{\ast}} = X^{j{\ast}}\hat{s}_{i}^{\,j}(X^{j{\ast}};X^{{\ast}})\) for all i ∈ I j, j ∈ J. As such, \(\sum _{i\in I^{j}}\hat{s}_{i}^{\,j}(X^{j{\ast}};X^{{\ast}}) = 1\) and therefore \(X^{j{\ast}} =\hat{ X}^{j}(X^{{\ast}})\) for all j ∈ J, implying \(X^{{\ast}} =\sum _{j\in J}\hat{X}^{j}(X^{{\ast}})\). For necessity of the condition, define a player’s best response in a nested aggregative game as b i j(X i j; X j). Consider the strategy \(x_{i}^{\,j{\ast}} =\hat{ X}^{j}(X^{{\ast}})\hat{s}_{i}^{\,j}(X^{j{\ast}};X^{{\ast}})\). By definition of share functions and the consistency of \(\hat{X}^{j}(X^{{\ast}})\) within group j (which implies \(\hat{X}^{j}(X^{{\ast}}) - x_{i}^{\,j{\ast}} = X_{-i}^{j{\ast}}\)), \(x_{i}^{\,j{\ast}} = b_{i}^{\,j}(X_{-i}^{j{\ast}};X^{{\ast}}-\hat{ X}^{j}(X^{{\ast}}))\). When \(X^{{\ast}} =\sum _{j\in J}\hat{X}^{j}(X^{{\ast}})\), it follows that \(X^{{\ast}}-\hat{ X}^{j}(X^{{\ast}}) = X^{-j{\ast}}\), and therefore x i j = b i j(X i j; X j) for all i ∈ I j, j ∈ J, giving the conclusion that x is a Nash equilibrium. □ 

Proof of Proposition 7

The properties of individual share functions in \(\hat{\mathcal{G}}^{j}(X)\) are first deduced. The conditions stated on preferences are equivalent to assuming

$$\displaystyle\begin{array}{rcl} \frac{\partial \hat{l}_{i}^{\,j}} {\partial \sigma _{i}^{\,j}} & =& X^{j}\left [ \frac{\partial ^{2}\hat{u}_{ i}^{\,j}} {\partial (x_{i}^{\,j})^{2}} + \frac{\partial ^{2}\hat{u}_{i}^{\,j}} {\partial x_{i}^{\,j}\partial X^{j}} + \frac{\partial ^{2}\hat{u}_{i}^{\,j}} {\partial x_{i}^{\,j}\partial X}\right ] < 0, {}\\ \frac{\partial \hat{l}_{i}^{\,j}} {\partial X^{j}}& =& \sigma _{i}^{\,j} \frac{\partial ^{2}\hat{u}_{ i}^{\,j}} {\partial (x_{i}^{\,j})^{2}} + \frac{\partial ^{2}\hat{u}_{i}^{\,j}} {\partial x_{i}^{\,j}\partial X^{j}} +\sigma _{ i}^{\,j} \frac{\partial ^{2}\hat{u}_{ i}^{\,j}} {\partial x_{i}^{\,j}\partial X^{j}} + \frac{\partial ^{2}\hat{u}_{i}^{\,j}} {\partial (X^{j})^{2}} +\sigma _{ i}^{\,j} \frac{\partial ^{2}\hat{u}_{ i}^{\,j}} {\partial x_{i}^{\,j}\partial X} + \frac{\partial ^{2}\hat{u}_{i}^{\,j}} {\partial X^{j}\partial X} < 0,\text{ and} {}\\ \frac{\partial \hat{l}_{i}^{\,j}} {\partial X} & =& \frac{\partial ^{2}\hat{u}_{i}^{\,j}} {\partial x_{i}^{\,j}\partial X} + \frac{\partial ^{2}\hat{u}_{i}^{\,j}} {\partial X^{j}\partial X} + \frac{\partial ^{2}\hat{u}_{i}^{\,j}} {\partial (X)^{2}} < 0. {}\\ \end{array}$$

Under the first two conditions (as previously) two thresholds \(\hat{\underline{X}}_{i}^{\,j}(X)\) (which is X j > 0 such that \(\hat{l}_{i}^{\,j}(1,X^{j};X) = 1\)) and \(\hat{\bar{X}}_{i}^{\,j}(X)\) (which is X j such that \(\hat{l}_{i}^{\,j}(0,X^{j};X) = 1\) if such an X j exists, otherwise it is defined as + ) can be defined, between which the share function is defined and takes positive values, and where

$$\displaystyle{ \frac{\partial \hat{s}_{i}^{\,j}} {\partial X^{j}} = -\frac{\frac{\partial \hat{l}_{i}^{\,j}} {\partial X^{j}}} {\frac{\partial \hat{l}_{i}^{\,j}} {\partial \sigma _{i}^{\,j}} } < 0. }$$

If \(\hat{\underline{X}}_{i}^{\,j}(X)\) as defined above does not exist then the share function is defined for all X j > 0 with \(\lim _{X^{j}\rightarrow 0}\hat{s}_{i}^{\,j}(X^{j};X) =\hat{\bar{ s}}_{i}^{\,j}(X)\).

As before, the aggregation of individual share functions is taken to be defined only for values of X j where all group members’ share functions are defined. Noting that share functions are either equal to zero for large enough X j, or are vanishing in the large X j limit, if either \(\hat{\underline{X}}_{i}^{\,j}(X) > 0\) for any i ∈ I j, or \(\sum _{i\in I^{j}}\hat{\bar{s}}_{i}^{\,j}(X) > 1\) then there is a single consistent aggregate action \(\hat{X}^{j}(X)\) in \(\hat{\mathcal{G}}^{j}\) which is such that \(\sum _{i\in I^{j}}\hat{s}_{i}^{\,j}(\hat{X}^{j}(X);X) = 1\). If this is not the case then \(\hat{X}^{j}(X) = 0\).

Consider now varying X to change the partial game played by group j. Group j’s share of the total aggregate is \(\hat{S}^{j}(X) =\hat{ X}^{j}(X)/X\), defined by (9) if the resulting share is between 0 and 1. Note that

$$\displaystyle\begin{array}{rcl} \frac{\partial \hat{L}^{j}} {\partial \Lambda ^{j}}& =& X\sum _{i\in I^{j}} \frac{\partial \hat{s}_{i}^{\,j}} {\partial X^{j}}\text{ and} {}\\ \frac{\partial \hat{L}^{j}} {\partial X} & =& \sum _{i\in I^{j}}\Lambda ^{j} \frac{\partial \hat{s}_{i}^{\,j}} {\partial X^{j}} + \frac{\partial \hat{s}_{i}^{\,j}} {\partial X}. {}\\ \end{array}$$

Now,

$$\displaystyle{ \frac{\partial \hat{s}_{i}^{\,j}} {\partial X} = -\frac{\frac{\partial \hat{l}_{i}^{\,j}} {\partial X} } {\frac{\partial \hat{l}_{i}^{\,j}} {\partial \sigma _{i}^{\,j}} } < 0, }$$

which, combined with the monotonicity of share functions with respect to group aggregate, implies both of the expressions above are negative. Given this, the thresholds and the monotonicity of group share functions stated in the proposition can be derived analogously to the case within groups, so the details are omitted. Aggregate share functions are either equal to zero for \(X >\hat{\bar{ X}}^{j}\) or, if this is not finite, vanish in the large X limit—this follows by recalling that individual share functions vanish in the large X j limit, so as X →  (9) can hold only if \(\lim _{X\rightarrow \infty }\Lambda ^{j}X < \infty \) which requires \(\Lambda ^{j} \rightarrow 0\). Given this, if either \(\hat{\underline{X}}^{j} > 0\) for any j ∈ J, or \(\sum _{j\in J}\hat{\bar{S}}^{j} > 0\) if \(\hat{\underline{X}}^{j} = 0\) for all j ∈ J, the aggregate share function will exceed one for small enough X and since it is strictly decreasing in X will be equal to one at exactly one value of X, so consequently there is a unique Nash equilibrium. □ 

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Dickson, A. (2017). Multiple-Aggregate Games. In: Buchholz, W., Rübbelke, D. (eds) The Theory of Externalities and Public Goods. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-49442-5_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics