Skip to main content

TEM’s Details

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Modal Justification via Theories

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 380))

  • 236 Accesses

Abstract

According to TEM, a person is justified in believing an interesting modal claim, p, if and only if (a) she is justified in believing a theory according to which p is true, (b) she believes p on the basis of that theory, and (c) she has no defeaters for her belief that p. Accordingly, we need a story about how we come to justifiably believe theories, a story about theories on which they have modal content, and a story about what it is to believe a claim on the basis of a theory. This chapter provides the second and third story, and explains why I can leave the problem of theory confirmation for others.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

eBook
USD 16.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 89.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 89.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    On this point, see “What Theories Are Not” in Putnam (1979).

  2. 2.

    For arguments in favor of the semantic view, see Lloyd (1994), Suppe (1977, 1989), Suppes (1993), Thompson (1989), van Fraassen (1989).

  3. 3.

    The theoretical definition stands to the models roughly as sentences stand to propositions. Many sentences can express a single proposition, and it’s the proposition—i.e., what’s said—that’s of interest. Likewise, the proposed theoretical definition is the standard way to define the set of models, but there are other theoretical definitions that would do the same work, and none has any privileged status: it’s the models that matter. For this reason, it’s inaccurate to say that the theoretical definition expresses the theory’s laws. Of course, you could take some subset of those claims that hold true in every model of the theory to be the theory’s laws, given some account of what laws are. But an adherent of the semantic view need not appeal to laws at any juncture; they need not figure into her understanding of theories, nor of their modal content.

  4. 4.

    There are interesting wrinkles associated with the members of S that vacuously satisfy the theoretical definition. There are a few ways to think about such cases. First, you might take it to be implicit in the theoretical hypothesis that we aren’t supposed to take a stand on those models that vacuously satisfy the theoretical definition—i.e., we should neither affirm nor deny that they represent possible states of the target system. Second, you might delimit the relevant models by appealing to our explanatory aims: those models are relevant such that, without them, the theory wouldn’t explain what it purports to explain. Relatedly, you might delimit the relevant models by appealing to our epistemic circumstances: those models are relevant such that, without them, we wouldn’t be justified in believing the theory—the rest aren’t.

  5. 5.

    We can also define “theoretical counterfactuals” (CT): if p were the case, then q would be the case according to a theory if and only if (a) S includes a model that is supposed to represent actuality (the “@-model”), (b) S includes representing p-models and representing q-models, and (c) the representing p-model most like the @-model is a representing q-model. This definition is based on Stalnaker’s semantics for counterfactuals, but it’s obvious that you could use Lewis’s; the only difference is that Stalnaker makes the simplifying assumption that there will be a unique closest world.

  6. 6.

    If you doubt that the demon lacks understanding, we can get a conclusion that’s just as good for present purposes via a slightly different argument. Suppose, again, that the demon can perfectly predict the evolution of a system, and that the demon is kind enough to report his predictions on demand. (He’s always truthful: if the demon says that an object will be at a location at t, the object is at the location at t.) With the demon available to you, you too can predict and retrodict every state of the world at every other time. But clearly you aren’t a model of epistemic success in this scenario: you don’t need to understand anything at all to have this power. Explanation is a good that goes beyond mere predictive (and retrodictive) accuracy. For further problems with the view that explanation is prediction and retrodiction, see Salmon (1989).

  7. 7.

    If we wanted to bracket the trivial cases, we could restrict H origins to things that have origins, but nothing turns on this here.

  8. 8.

    For a related view, see DePaul and Ramsey (1998).

  9. 9.

    See Gentner and Stevens (1983) and Johnson-Laird (2004) for helpful overviews.

  10. 10.

    For a related view, see Nichols (2006).

  11. 11.

    Of course, if you aren’t sufficiently familiar with the theory in question, you won’t be able to draw on it in the way I’m suggesting. But if you aren’t sufficiently familiar with the theory in question, TEM says that you can’t use to secure justified beliefs about the modal claims it sanctions, so this is hardly a problem.

  12. 12.

    For similar perspectives, see Lewis (1970), Churchland (1986), Churchland (1989), and Baker (2007).

  13. 13.

    Or, if you prefer, let’s say that folk theory is that part of our global theory that stands in the relevant relation to all those beliefs that we do not obviously hold on the basis of a scientific or metaphysical theory. Alternately, let’s say that our folk theories are those theories that stand in the relevant relation to various sets of beliefs not obviously held on the basis of a scientific or metaphysical theory. I’ll ignore these variants in what follows, since I don’t think that much turns on how we individuate theories.

References

  • Baker, L. R. (2007). The metaphysics of everyday life: An essay in practical realism. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. S. (1986). Neurophilosophy: Toward a unified science of the mind-brain. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, P. M. (1989). A neurocomputational perspective: The nature of mind and the structure of science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • DePaul, M. R., & Ramsey, W. (1998). Rethinking intuition: The psychology of intuition and its role in philosophical inquiry. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gentner, D., & Stevens, A. L. (1983). Mental models, cognitive science. Hillsdale: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. N. (1979). Understanding scientific theories. New York: Holt, Rinehart, and Winston.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gopnik, A., & Meltzoff, A. N. (1997). Words, thoughts, and theories: Learning, development, and conceptual change. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson-Laird, P. N. (2004). The history of mental models. In K. Manktelow & M. C. Chung (Eds.), Psychology of reasoning: Theoretical and historical perspectives (pp. 179–212). New York: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (1994). Explanatory knowledge and metaphysical dependence. Philosophical Issues, 5, 51–69.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1980). Naming and necessity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, C. I. (1970). The pragmatic element in knowledge. In J. D. Goheen & J. L. Mothershead (Eds.), Collected papers of Clarence Irving Lewis (pp. 240–257). Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lewis, D. (1986). On the plurality of worlds. Malden: Blackwell Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lloyd, E. A. (1994). The structure and confirmation of evolutionary theory. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S. (2006). Imaginative blocks and impossibility: An essay in modal psychology. In S. Nichols (Ed.), The architecture of the imagination (pp. 237–256). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1979). Mathematics, matter, and method: Philosophical papers. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Salmon, W. C. (1989). Four decades of scientific explanation. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Strawson, P. F. (1959). Individuals: An essay in descriptive metaphysics. London: Methuen.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Suppe, F. (1977). The structure of scientific theories. Urbana: University of Illinois Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppe, F. (1989). The semantic conception of theories and scientific realism. Chicago: University of Illinois Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suppes, P. (1993). Models and methods in the philosophy of science: Selected essays. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Thompson, P. (1989). The structure of biological theories. New York: State University of New York Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vaidya, A. (2015). The epistemology of modality. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2015/entries/modality-epistemology

  • Van Fraassen, B. (1980). The scientific image. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Van Fraassen, B. (1989). Laws and symmetry. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Vogel, J. (1990). Cartesian skepticism and inference to the best explanation. The Journal of Philosophy, 87(11), 658–666.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Fischer, B. (2017). TEM’s Details. In: Modal Justification via Theories. Synthese Library, vol 380. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-49127-1_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics