Skip to main content

A Theory-Based Epistemology of Modality

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Modal Justification via Theories

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 380))

Abstract

This book articulates and defends a theory-based epistemology of modality (TEM). At TEM’s core is the idea that if we’re justified in believing the extraordinary modal claims to which philosophers often appeal—such as the claim that I could be disembodied, or that there could be a maximally perfect being—it’s because we’re justified in believing theories according to which those claims are true. This chapter articulates some of the assumptions that shape TEM, sketches the view, and then develops the basic argument for it, which is based on an analogy between a plausible modal epistemology for games and modal epistemology generally.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 69.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 89.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 89.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Of course, others have become non-realists on epistemic grounds—e.g., Sidelle (1989).

  2. 2.

    I say a bit more elsewhere: see my (2016) and (Forthcoming).

  3. 3.

    More precisely, he distinguishes between ordinary claims that those that are “remote from the concerns of everyday life” (1998, 76), but it’s become customary to refer to the latter as extraordinary.

  4. 4.

    Van Inwagen acknowledges that the name is a poor one, since it suggests that the view is more radical than it is. As a result, some have taken to calling his view “moderate modal skepticism,” distinguishing it from the view that we have no modal justification whatever. That’s certainly more accurate, but for ease of exposition, I’ll use the shorter name.

  5. 5.

    I do, however, explore how much TEM could explain—see below.

  6. 6.

    Of course, if we start with an extraordinary modal claim as a premise, then we may be able to infer other extraordinary modal claims from it. (I call this “conditional” modal justification, and discuss it in Sect. 3.3.) But cases like this aren’t the interesting ones. What matters is how we get extraordinary modal justification in the first place, not what we can do with it once we’ve got it.

  7. 7.

    Expressions like “ordinary modal justification” are shorthand for the less-wieldy “justification for believing ordinary modal claims.”

  8. 8.

    People can cheat in games. But let’s assume, just for the sake of simplicity, that we were watching a bunch of rule-followers play Clue.

  9. 9.

    On the assumption that no cause can travel faster than the speed of light, we can say, very roughly, that our light cone is the region of spacetime containing both (a) the events that could causally affect us and (b) the events on which we might have some causal impact. See Huggett (2010) for a philosophically-astute introduction.

  10. 10.

    Another analogy. Imagine that you’re a spy who’s captured in the middle of a daring mission. Your captors drug you and take you to an undisclosed location. You wake up slumped in the corner of windowless room; two of your captors are standing in the opposing corner, guns drawn. They say:

    You are in a building. This may or may not be the building’s only room. Give us your estimate of the contents of this building, being careful to indicate, for any two objects, whether or not you judge them to be in the same room. And by the way: you may not leave this room, we will not answer any questions about the building or its contents, and you should not assume that the other rooms—if others there are—bear any resemblance to this room.

    And of course, because this is a spy story, they go on to say: “If your estimation is largely correct, then we will release you immediately; if it is not, then we will torture you until you give up national security secrets.” There should be little doubt that you are about to be tortured. There is virtually no way that your estimation will be correct; you have no information from which you can plausibly extrapolate the facts about the building. But now let’s suppose that realism about modality is true, and that we are causally isolated from the truthmakers for modal claims, and that the worlds are not organized in any discernable way (i.e., if they have no invariant features that we can discover by theorizing about actuality). If all this is true about modal reality, then what’s the difference between your epistemic situation in our spy story and your epistemic situation vis-à-vis modal reality? To my mind, none whatever.

  11. 11.

    Granted, this runs counter to the methodology that metaphysicians often employ. Hart (1988) and Chalmers (1996), for example, offer arguments for dualism that stand or fall on contentious modal premises that are not supposed to presuppose any particular theory of mind. Indeed, many of us were drawn to the epistemology of modality precisely because metaphysicians argued for theories based on extraordinary modal claims, and we wanted to know whether those claims could be justified. That, at least, is my own story. However, the analogy with Clue suggests that it’s a mistake to argue for theories based on extraordinary modal claims. (It may be permissible to argue from uncontroversial modal claims, as we might want to explain their truth in terms of more fundamental modal realities.) That analogy puts the epistemic weight on attempts to explain actuality—not extraordinary possibilities. TEM agrees. I say more about all this in Sect. 3.4.

  12. 12.

    For more objections to this kind of evolutionary argument, see Stich (1990) and Plantinga’s contributions to Plantinga and Tooley (2008).

References

  • Armstrong, D. M. (1989). A combinatorial theory of possibility. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Benacerraf, P. (1973). Mathematical truth. The Journal of Philosophy, 70, 661–679.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (1996). The conscious mind: In search of a fundamental theory. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, R. W. (2015). Theory selection in modal epistemology. American Philosophical Quarterly, 52, 289–304.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, B. (2016). Modal empiricism: Objection, reply, proposal. In B. Fischer & F. Leon (Eds.), Modal epistemology after rationalism. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hale, B. (2003). Knowledge of possibility and necessity. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society, 103, 1–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hale, B. (2013). Necessary beings: An essay on ontology, modality, and the relations between them. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hart, W. D. (1988). The engines of the soul. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huggett, N. (2010). Everywhere and everywhen: Adventures in physics and philosophy. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Koons, R. C. (2000). Realism regained: An exact theory of causation, teleology, and the mind. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kripke, S. (1980). Naming and necessity. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kung, P. (2010). Imagining as a guide to possibility. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 81, 620–663.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lowe, E. J. (2012). What is the source of our knowledge of modal truths. Mind, 121, 919–950.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Molnar, G., & Mumford, S. (2003). Powers: A study in metaphysics. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nichols, S. (2006). Imaginative blocks and impossibility: An essay in modal psychology. In S. Nichols (Ed.), The architecture of the imagination (pp. 237–256). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Nozick, R. (2003). Invariances. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Connor, T. (2008). Theism and ultimate explanation: The necessary shape of contingency. Malden: Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Peacocke, C. (1999). Being known. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Plantinga, A., & Tooley, M. (2008). Knowledge of God. New York: Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Rea, M. C. (2002). World without design: The ontological consequences of naturalism. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Roca-Royes, S. (2011). Modal knowledge and counterfactual knowledge. Logique et analyse, 54(216), 537–552.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sidelle, A. (1989). Necessity, essence, and individuation: A defense of conventionalism. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stich, S. P. (1990). The fragmentation of reason: Preface to a pragmatic theory of cognitive evaluation. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vaidya, A. (2015). The epistemology of modality. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2015/entries/modality-epistemology

  • Van Inwagen, P. (1998). Modal epistemology. Philosophical Studies, 92, 67–84.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, T. (2007). The philosophy of philosophy. Malden: Blackwell.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fischer, B. (Forthcoming). C. I. Lewis and the Benacerraf problem. Episteme.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Fischer, B. (2017). A Theory-Based Epistemology of Modality. In: Modal Justification via Theories. Synthese Library, vol 380. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-49127-1_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics