Skip to main content

The Singular Square: Contrariety and Double Negation from Aristotle to Homer

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Abstract

While the traditional Square of Opposition was based on Aristotle’s logic, its first appearance postdates the Stagyrite by five centuries. In the Prior Analytics I, Aristotle himself lays out a somewhat different square, which I dub the Singular Square, to formalize his treatment of the interrelation of singular statements (it’s good, it isn’t good, it’s not-good, it isn’t not-good). Like the more familiar square, the Singular Square is based on the distinction between contradictory and contrary opposition. This paper focuses on the role of the Singular Square as a device for unmasking the conspiracy of MaxContrary, the natural language tendency for a formal contradictory (apparent wide-scope) negation ¬p to strengthen to a contrary of p in a variety of syntactic and lexical contexts. This conspiracy extends from the non-compositional narrow-scope readings of negation interacting with bare plurals, definite plurals, conjunctions, and neg-raising predicates to the prevalence of prohibitives and litotes, the contrary interpretations of affixal negation, and the seemingly illogical behavior of “logical” double negation.

I would by contraries/Execute all things.

—Tempest, II.i

The contrary bringeth bliss.

—Henry VI Part II, V.v

An earlier version of this paper was presented at the Logical Words workshop organized by Jacques Moeschler at CIL 19 in Geneva (July 2013). Some of the material discussed here was presented in other forms at other forums, including LNAT (Logic Now and Then) in Brussels (November 2008), ESSLLI in Ljubljana (August 2011), SCLP in Santa Cruz (November 2011), CRISSP in Brussels (December 2011), the LOT Summer School in Driebergen (July 2012), AMPRA 1 in Charlotte (October 2012), the Systematic Semantic Change Workshop in Austin (April 2013), and Go Figure in London (June 2013). I am grateful to commenters at those occasions and to Barbara Abbott, Chris Collins, Ashwini Deo, Elena Herburger, Dany Jaspers, Pierre Larrivée, Jacques Moeschler, and Paul Postal for helpful discussions and complaints. I am grateful to Philosophical Studies, its editor Wayne Davis, and Springer for granting permission to reprint material that appears in a slightly different form in “Lie-toe-tease: Double negatives and unexcluded middles” (Horn, to appear).

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    What of existential import? Which of the four statement forms entail or presuppose that the set over which the quantifier ranges is non-null and how does this affect the subaltern and other relations? In particular, if all is import-free while some is not, doesn’t this vitiate the Square? The fact that other operators (binary connectives, adverbs, modals, deontics) for which existential import is irrelevant can be mapped onto the Square makes such a step as unappealing as it is unnecessary. This leaves a number of options for dealing with questions of import and quantification and their relation to the Square; see Horn (1997) for discussion.

  2. 2.

    Note that despite the standard dictionary entry for cannot in which it is equated to ‘can not’, the former—as a lexicalization—can only get the E reading, never the O, regardless of the modal flavor involved. The same is true for couldn’t and couldnae, both standardly but misleadingly glossed as contractions of ‘could not.’

  3. 3.

    The relative opacity of E (as opposed to O) negative values is further attested by negative indefinites and “n-words” like Eng. no and nary (a), Ger. nie, and Fr. personne, rien, jamais, and by the O > E drift illustrated by intensifying NPI adverbials like not very Adj, not too Adj, not (all) that Adj, and not at all.

  4. 4.

    Bypassed here is the extension of MaxContrary to the phenomena motivating the principle of Conditional Excluded Middle (cf. Stalnaker 1981; von Fintel 1997; Williams 2010 for discussion and references), based on the plausibility of the assumed disjunction ([if A then C] v [if A then ¬C]).

  5. 5.

    The negative prefix non- typically functions as a contradictory and often forms minimal pairs with other contrary-forming negative prefixes (non-scientific vs. unscientific, non-artistic vs. inartistic; cf. Horn 1989: Sect. 5.1). Thus we have cases in which the contradictory non-adjective is explicitly rejected as too weak:

    In Talmudic days myrtles were used at funerals. Nowadays, the custom of flowers at a funeral…is not merely non-jewish but positively unjewish.

    (Contribution to mail.jewish net list, April 1991)

    A scale of the form <x is non-Jewish, x is un-Jewish> is clearly in play here.

  6. 6.

    While most speakers can be counted on to grasp the nuance of weakness conveyed by the negated negative, those with impairments in Theory of Mind, like the high-functioning autistic savant Daniel Tammet have difficulty in determining the motivation for, and therefore the interpretation of, litotic structures:

    Certain sentence structures can be particularly hard for me to analyze, such as: “He is not inexperienced in such things,” where the two negatives (not and in-) cancel each other out. It is much better if people just say: “He is experienced in such things.” (Tammet 2006: 162).

  7. 7.

    See http://www.myspace.com/notnotlickingtoadstunes for the eponymous Austin-based rock band.

  8. 8.

    This is effectively a scale of sanity, although negatively expressed. Similarly nuanced instantiations of positively described sanity scales are not inextant:

    We stood watching him. It was strangely riveting. Half-Dead Fred hadn’t even acknowledged the presence of others in the room, so entranced was he with discovering the tools that would allow him to rescue the princess locked in a dungeon by a nefarious wizard in cyberworld…

    Is he mad? I asked Mike.

    As in crazy? No, I don’t think so. But sane would be a little too strong.

    (J. Martin Troost (2004), The Sex Lives of Cannibals, p. 260)

References

  • Ackrill JL (ed) (1963) Aristotle: Categories and De Interpretatione. Clarendon, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Anselm ST (1936) The Lambeth fragments. In: Schmitt FS (ed) Ein neues unvollendetes Werk des hl. Anselm von Canterbury. Aschendorff, Münster i. W

    Google Scholar 

  • Aristotle. Works, under the general editorship of W.D. Ross. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Bartsch R (1973) ‘Negative transportation’ gibt es nicht. Linguistische Berichte 27:1–7

    Google Scholar 

  • Béziau JY (2003) New light on the square of oppositions and its nameless corner. LogInvest 10:218–32

    Google Scholar 

  • Béziau J-Y, Payette G (eds) (2012) The square of opposition: a general framework for cognition. Peter Lang, Bern, pp 383–416

    Google Scholar 

  • Bogen J (1991) Aristotelian contraries. Topoi 10:53–66

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bolinger D (1972) Degree words. Mouton, The Hague

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bosanquet B (1888) Logic, vol 1. Clarendon, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown K (1991) Double modals in Hawick Scots. In: Trudgill P, Chambers JK (eds) Dialects of English. Longman, London, pp 74–103

    Google Scholar 

  • Brown P, Levinson S (1987) Politeness. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge

    Google Scholar 

  • Collins C, Postal P (2014) Classical NEG-raising: an essay in the syntax of negation. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • de Cornulier B (1973) Sur une règle de déplacement de la négation. Le français moderne 41:43–57

    Google Scholar 

  • Deal AR (2011) Modals without scales. Language 87:559–585

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deutscher M (1965) A note on saying and believing. Analysis 105:53–57

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ducrot O (1973) La preuve et le dire. Maison Mame, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • Erasmus D (1519) The colloquies of Erasmus, Thompson CR (trans). University of Chicago Press, Chicago

    Google Scholar 

  • Fillmore C (1963) The position of embedding transformations in a grammar. Word 19:208–231

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fintel K von (1997) Bare plurals, bare conditionals, and only. J Semant 14:1–56

    Google Scholar 

  • Fodor J D (1970) The linguistic description of opaque contexts. Dissertation, MIT

    Google Scholar 

  • Fowler HW (1926) A dictionary of modern english usage. Oxford University Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Frege G (1919) Negation. In: Beaney M (ed) The Frege reader. Blackwell, Oxford, pp 346–361

    Google Scholar 

  • Gajewski J (2007) Neg-raising and polarity. Linguist Philos 30:289–328

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Geach PT (1972) Logic matters. University of California Press, Berkeley

    Google Scholar 

  • Goossens L (1987) Modal shifts and predication types. In: van der Auwera J, Goossens L (eds) Ins and outs of the predication. Foris, Dordrecht, pp 21–37

    Google Scholar 

  • Henry D (1967) The logic of Saint Anselm. Clarendon Press, Oxford

    Google Scholar 

  • Heyting A (1956) Intuitionism: an introduction. North-Holland, Amsterdam

    Google Scholar 

  • Hintikka J (1962) Knowledge and belief. Cornell University Press, Ithaca

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoffmann M (1987) Negatio contrarii: a study of Latin litotes. Van Gorcum, Assen

    Google Scholar 

  • Hopkins J (1972) A companion to the study of St. Anselm, University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis

    Google Scholar 

  • Horn L (1972) The semantic properties of logical operators in English. Dissertation, UCLA

    Google Scholar 

  • Horn L (1978a) Aspects of negation. In: Greenberg J et al (eds) Universals of language, vol IV, Syntax, Stanford University Press, Stanford, pp 127–210

    Google Scholar 

  • Horn L (1978b) Remarks on Neg-raising. In: Cole P (ed) Syntax and semantics 9: Pragmatics. Academic Press, New York, pp 129–220

    Google Scholar 

  • Horn L (1984) Toward a new taxonomy for pragmatic inference: Q-based and R-based implicature. In: Schiffrin D (ed) Meaning, form, and use in context (GURT ‘84). Georgetown University Press, Washington, pp 11–42

    Google Scholar 

  • Horn L (1989) A natural history of negation. University of Chicago Press, Chicago, Reissue edition, CSLI, Stanford (2001)

    Google Scholar 

  • Horn L (1990) Hamburgers and truth: why Gricean inference is Gricean. BLS 16, Parasession on the legacy of Grice, Berkeley, pp 454–471

    Google Scholar 

  • Horn L (1991) Duplex negatio affirmat…. the economy of double negation. Papers from the parasession on negation. CLS 27, Chicago, pp 78–106

    Google Scholar 

  • Horn L (1997) All John’s children are as bald as the King of France: existential import and the geometry of opposition. CLS 33, Chicago, pp 155–79

    Google Scholar 

  • Horn L (2002) Uncovering the un-word: a study in lexical pragmatics. Sophia Linguistica 49:1–64

    Google Scholar 

  • Horn L (2005) An un-paper for the unsyntactician. In: Mufwene S et al (eds) Polymorphous linguistics: Jim McCawley’s legacy. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA, pp 329–365

    Google Scholar 

  • Horn L (2010) Contradiction. In: Zalta E (ed) Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/contradiction/

  • Horn L (2012) Histoire d’*O: lexical pragmatics and the geometry of opposition. In: Béziau J-Y, Payette G (eds) The square of opposition: a general framework for cognition. Peter Lang, Bern, pp 383–416

    Google Scholar 

  • Horn L (to appear) Lie-toe-tease: double negatives and unexcluded middles. To appear in Philosophical Studies

    Google Scholar 

  • Horn L, Bayer S (1984) Short-circuited implicature: a negative contribution. Linguist Philos 7:397–414

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Humberstone L (1986) Extensionality in sentence position. J Philos Logic 15:27–54

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jackendoff R (1971) On some questionable arguments about quantifiers and negation. Language 47:282–297

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jaspers D (2005) Operators in the lexicon: on the negative logic of natural language. (Universiteit Leiden dissertation.) LOT, Utrecht

    Google Scholar 

  • Jespersen O (1917) Negation in English and other languages. Høst, Copenhagen

    Google Scholar 

  • Jespersen O (1924) The philosophy of grammar. Allen and Unwin, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Katzir R, Singh R (2013) Constraints on the lexicalization of logical operators. Linguist Philos 36:1–29

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Klooster W (2003) Negative raising revisited. In: Koster J, van Riemsdijk H (eds) Germania et Alia: a linguistic Festschrift for Hans den Besten. http://odur.let.rug.nl/~koster/DenBesten/contents.htm

  • Krifka M (1996) Pragmatic strengthening in plural predications and donkey sentences. SALT 6:136–153

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Larrivée P (2004) L’association négative. Droz, Genève

    Google Scholar 

  • Lausberg H (1960) Handbuch der literarischen Rhetorik. M. Hueber, München

    Google Scholar 

  • Liberman M (2012) Double lie toe tease. Language Log post, March 12, 2012. http://languagelog.ldc.upenn.edu/nll/?p=3839

  • Löbner S (1985) Definites. J Semant 4:279–325

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Löbner S (2000) Polarity and natural language: predication, quantification, and negation in particularizing and characterizing sentences. Linguist Philos 23:213–308

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Martinon P (1927) Comment on parle français. Larousse, Paris

    Google Scholar 

  • McCall S (1967) Contrariety. Notre Dame J Formal Logic 8:121–138

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mates B (1953) Stoic logic. University of California Press, Berkeley

    Google Scholar 

  • Oesterle J (ed) (1962) Aristotle: on Interpretation. Commentary by St. Thomas and Cajetan. Marquette University Press, Milwaukee

    Google Scholar 

  • Orwell G (1946) Politics and the English language. In: Collected essays. Secker and Warburg, London, 1961, pp 353–67

    Google Scholar 

  • Parsons T (2012) The traditional square of opposition. In: Zalta E (ed) Stanford Encycl Philos. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/square/

  • Peacham H (1593) The garden of eloquence. H. Iackson, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Poutsma H (1928) A grammar of late modern english. P. Noordhoff, Groningen

    Google Scholar 

  • Puttenham, G and/or R (1589) The arte of english poesie. Field, London

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine WVO (1960) Word and object. MIT Press, Cambridge, MA

    Google Scholar 

  • Quintilian MF Institutio Oratoria, H.E. Butler, trans, Loeb Classical Library. 3 volumes, William Heinemann, London, 1920–21

    Google Scholar 

  • Richter FK (1944) Hitler and words. Etc. 1:256–258

    Google Scholar 

  • Sapir E (1944) Grading: a study in semantics. In: Swiggers P et al. (eds) The collected works of Edward Sapir, I. De Gruyter, Berlin, 2008, pp 447–70

    Google Scholar 

  • Scriblerus M (1727) The art of sinking in poetry. In: Steeves EL (ed). King’s Crown Press, New York, 1952

    Google Scholar 

  • Shaffer B (2002) Can’t: the negation of modal notions in ASL. Sign Lang Stud 3:34–53

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sigwart C (1885) Logic, vol I, H. Dendy, trans. Macmillan, New York, 1895

    Google Scholar 

  • Stalnaker R (1981) A defense of conditional excluded middle. In: Harper WL et al (eds) Ifs. D Reidel, Dordrecht, pp 87–104

    Google Scholar 

  • Tammet D (2006) Born on a blue day. Free Press, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Tobler A (1882) Il ne faut pas que tu meures ‘du darfst nicht sterben’. Vermischte Beiträge zur französischen Grammatik 1, 3d ed. S Hirzel, Leipzig, pp 201–5

    Google Scholar 

  • van der Auwera J (1996) Modality: the three-layered scalar square. J Semant 13:181–195

    Google Scholar 

  • van der Auwera J (2006) Why languages prefer prohibitives. Wai Guo Yu, pp 1–25

    Google Scholar 

  • van der Auwera J (2010) Prohibition: constructions and markers. In: Shu D et al (eds) Contrasting meaning in languages of the East and the West. Peter Lang, Bern, pp 443–475

    Google Scholar 

  • Vizitelly F (1910) A desk-book of errors in English. Funk and Wagnalls, New York

    Google Scholar 

  • Ward G, Hirschberg J (1991) A pragmatic analysis of tautological utterances. J Pragmat 15:507–520

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams CJF (1964) Saint Anselm and his biographers. Downside Rev 82:124–140

    Google Scholar 

  • Williams JRG (2010) Defending conditional excluded middle. Noûs 44:650–668

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Laurence R. Horn .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Horn, L.R. (2017). The Singular Square: Contrariety and Double Negation from Aristotle to Homer. In: Blochowiak, J., Grisot, C., Durrleman, S., Laenzlinger, C. (eds) Formal Models in the Study of Language. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-48832-5_9

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-48832-5_9

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-48831-8

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-48832-5

  • eBook Packages: Social SciencesSocial Sciences (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics