Skip to main content

The Right to Demand Love in Criminal Justice

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Judgments of Love in Criminal Justice
  • 486 Accesses

Abstract

The legend of the mill of Sanssouci, the palace of Fredrick the Great and the miller threat of the king with the judgment of the Supreme Court of Berlin is a narrative example of the right to demand fairness, respect of privacy and love for justice. The concept of human rights may sound differently. Many books and articles decorate themselves with the concept. Many philosophers and theologies quiz its nature. However, in law the concept has been given more consideration when there has been a violation of rights. It is upon this theory that the term or the word ‘humanity’ has taken shape in the body of law. Thus, from the commencement of civilisation where the law began its role human nature has been in focus, but with different degrees. Therefore, what was considered to be the concept of humanity in the Babylonian and Hammurabi Codes has enlarged into a different feature in the present structure of law and particularly in international human rights law. All these evaluations of the term humanity have helped to protect its nature than to destroy it. This protection can be seen today within the provisions of most international conventions. Thus, the character or the personality of human beings has come into law, not as a subject of obliteration, annihilation, or humiliation, but as a secure subject of law based on high value of its integrity. Kant described Humanity as:

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Kant (2014), p. 333. Available at http://www2.hn.psu.edu/faculty/jmanis/kant/critique-pure-reason6x9.pdf (Accessed December 27, 2014).

  2. 2.

    Grotius (eBook, 1603, http://oll.libertyfund.org/titles/1718) (Accessed March 28, 2015).

  3. 3.

    von Lockey (2006), p. 198. See also p. 201.

  4. 4.

    von Rovira, p. 61.

  5. 5.

    Hannikainen (1988), p. 30.

  6. 6.

    Grotius (eBook, 1603, http://oll.libertyfund.org/titles/1718) (Accessed 28 March 2015).

  7. 7.

    Grotius (eBook, 1603, http://oll.libertyfund.org/titles/1718) (Accessed March 28, 2015).

  8. 8.

    Marcin (1984), pp. 363–391. See also http://scholarship.law.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=2126&context=lawreview (Accessed June 12, 2016).

  9. 9.

    Spooner (1882), available at http://oll.libertyfund.org/titles/spooner-natural-law-or-the-science-of-justice-1882 (Accessed on May 17, 2015).

  10. 10.

    Gross (2012), p. 7.

  11. 11.

    The Basic Law of the Federal Republic of Germany.

  12. 12.

    Malekian (2015).

  13. 13.

    Concurring Opinion of Judge Power-Forde, the Grand Chamber of the European Court of Human Rights (9 July 2013) (Applications nos. 66069/09, 130/10 and 3896/10) http://hudoc.echr.coe.int/fre?i=001-122664#{%22itemid%22:[%22001-122664%22]} (Accessed October, 2015).

  14. 14.

    Concurring Opinion of Judge Yudkivska, the Grand Chamber of the European Court of Human Rights (9 July 2013), Application no (140/10), JUDGMENT. This version was rectified on 7 October 2014 under Rule 81 of the Rules of Court (Strasbourg, 4 September 2014) Final (16/02/2015). This judgment has become final under Article 44 § 2 of the Convention. http://hudoc.echr.coe.int/eng?i=001-146372#{%22itemid%22:[%22001-146372%22]} (accessed October 2, 2015).

  15. 15.

    Italics added.

  16. 16.

    Bushell’s Case, 124 Eng. Rep. 1006, 1013 (C.P. 1670). See also A complete collection of state-trials, and proceedings for high-treason, and other crimes and misdemeanours: from the reign of collection King Richard II. to the end of the reign of King George I. With two alphabetical tables to the whole (20 Volumes, Vol. xvii, London, 1816), p. 716.

  17. 17.

    See articles by Professor Michel Chossudovsky, available at http://www.globalresearch.ca/when-terrorism-becomes-counter-terrorism-the-state-sponsors-of-terrorism-are-going-after-the-terrorists/5496051. See also article by Dr. Paul Craig Roberts, ‘Washington’s Secret Agendas - Truth is Being Disguised to Suit’. Roberts puts clearly that “The public fell for the lie that the Taliban in Afghanistan are terrorists allied with al Qaeda. Americans fought a war for 13 years that enriched Dick Cheney’s firm, Halliburton, and other private interests only to end in another Washington failure. The public fell for the lie that Saddam Hussein in Iraq had “weapons of mass destruction” that were a threat to America and that if the US did not invade Iraq Americans risked a ‘mushroom cloud going up over an American city.’ With the rise of ISIS, this long war apparently is far from over. Billions of dollars more in profits will pour into the coffers of the US military security complex as Washington fights those who are redrawing the false Middle East boundaries created by the British and French after WW I when the British and French seized territories of the former Ottoman Empire. The American public fell for the lies told about Gaddafi in Libya. The formerly stable and prosperous country is now in chaos. The American public fell for the lie that Iran has, or is building, nuclear weapons. Sanctioned and reviled by the West, Iran has shifted toward an Eastern orientation, thereby removing a principal oil producer from Western influence. The public fell for the lie that Assad of Syria used “chemical weapons against his own people.” The jihadists that Washington sent to overthrow Assad have turned out to be, according to Washington’s propaganda, a threat to America. The greatest threat to the world is Washington’s insistence on its hegemony. The ideology of a handful of neoconservatives is the basis for this insistence.” Available at http://www.oneworldofnations.com/2014/09/washingtons-secret-agendas-truth-is.html. See as well https://docs.google.com/viewer?a=v&pid=sites&srcid=ZGVmYXVsdGRvbWFpbnxoYWlkZXJub3Rlc3xneDo3NDEwMDI3NjViZTNjODZm (Accessed December 25, 2015). For a useful analysis see http://www.politico.eu/article/why-the-arabs-dont-want-us-in-syria-mideast-conflict-oil-intervention/ (Accessed March 4, 2016).

  18. 18.

    Goodrich (2006), p. 1.

  19. 19.

    Id.

  20. 20.

    http://www.globalresearch.ca/when-terrorism-becomes-counter-terrorism-the-state-sponsors-of-terrorism-are-going-after-the-terrorists/5496051 and https://docs.google.com/viewer?a=v&pid=sites&srcid=ZGVmYXVsdGRvbWFpbnxoYWlkZXJub3Rlc3xneDo3NDEwMDI3NjViZTNjODZm (Accessed February 14, 2015).

  21. 21.

    Id.

  22. 22.

    Goodrich (2006), p. 2.

  23. 23.

    Id., p. 1.

  24. 24.

    Id., p. 25.

  25. 25.

    Goodrich (2006), p. 52.

  26. 26.

    Graybill, available at http://www.illinoismedieval.org/ems/VOL5/graybill.html (Accessed March 29, 2015), p. 95.

  27. 27.

    von Lockey (2006), p. 198.

  28. 28.

    von Lockey (2006), p. 198. See also p. 201.

  29. 29.

    Grotius, p. 434. Available at http://oll.libertyfund.org/titles/1718 (Accessed May 3, 2015).

  30. 30.

    See generally Roback (2001).

  31. 31.

    Rinpoche (2002).

  32. 32.

    Hora (1986), p. 19.

  33. 33.

    Trechsel (1997), pp. 94–119.

  34. 34.

    See Atwell (2008), pp. 501 and 505.

  35. 35.

    Id.

  36. 36.

    Mahatma Gandhi.

  37. 37.

    Andersen (2011), pp. 76–78.

  38. 38.

    Ward (2001), p. 946.

  39. 39.

    Consult chapters ten and eleven.

  40. 40.

    See Malekian (2014a).

  41. 41.

    Letter from John Keats to Benjamin Bailey (Nov. 22, 1817), in Rollins (Ed.) (1985), p. 185. See also http://www.john-keats.com/briefe/221117.htm (Accessed June 4, 2015).

  42. 42.

    Consult Bozbayindir (2013), pp. 20–21.

  43. 43.

    Mahatma Gandhi.

  44. 44.

    Klaus Stern, ‘From the European Convention on Human Rights to the European Charter of Fundamental Rights: The Prospects for the Protection of human Rights in Europe’ in Blanke and Mangiameli (2006), pp. 169–184.

  45. 45.

    Id. pp. 169–171.

  46. 46.

    Malekian (2005), p. 721.

  47. 47.

    Paracelsus (1493–1541).

  48. 48.

    Carty (1986), p. 21. See also Charlesworth and Chinkin (2000); Bederman (2002); Koskenniemi (2005); Marks (2000); Meron (2006). Goldsmith and Posner (2007); Chayes and Chayes (1995).

  49. 49.

    Mission for Establishment of Human Rights in Iran, available at http://www.google.de/url?sa=t&rct=j&q=&esrc=s&source=web&cd=1&ved=0CCIQFjAA&url=http%3A%2F%2Fmehr.org%2FIslamic_Penal_Code_of_Iran.pdf&ei=uSpvVYbDA4bfUayBgdgN&usg=AFQjCNHhVkRBVR1-Gx-4IMUToSeIhg_uTA&bvm=bv.94911696,d.d24 (Accessed June 3, 2015); Malekian (2014b), pp. 31–69; Malekian and Nordlöf (2012a), pp. 1–3; Malekian and Nordlöf (2012b), pp. 1–5.

  50. 50.

    For instance, see Fedorova (2012), p. 11.

  51. 51.

    Vattel (1844), para. 231, p. 108. Available at http://www.loc.gov/rr/frd/Military_Law/Lieber_Collection/pdf/DeVattel_LawOfNations.pdf (Accessed December 16, 2016).

  52. 52.

    R.v. Sussex Justices, ex parte McCarthy (1924) I.K.B.256, p. 259.

  53. 53.

    Fichtelberg (2015).

  54. 54.

    Fichtelberg (2015), pp. 182–185.

  55. 55.

    Id., pp. 177-8 & 179, 185.

  56. 56.

    von Pufendorf (1931), p. 315.

  57. 57.

    Id.

  58. 58.

    Martin Luther King. See also Vischer (2014), pp. 39–41.

  59. 59.

    Id.

  60. 60.

    Some psychologists may also have a similar policy without measuring and solving the internal position with love.

  61. 61.

    Malekian (2005), p. 691.

  62. 62.

    Id., p. 690.

  63. 63.

    For the morality of lawyer, consult Pepper (1986), p. 613.

  64. 64.

    Wendel (2012), p. 1.

  65. 65.

    Luther King (1963), p. 6.

  66. 66.

    Simon (1998), p. 138.

  67. 67.

    Kruse (2010), p. 393.

  68. 68.

    Pearce (2002), p. 1807.

References

  • Andersen, P. (2011). Klassisk og Kristen Naturret. In O. Hammerslev & H. P. Olsen (Eds.), Restsfilosofi – ecntrale tekster og temaer (pp. 71–96). København: Hans Reitzels Forlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Atwell, B. L. (2008). The jurisprudence of love. University of Detroit Mercy Law Review, 85, 495.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bederman, D. J. (2002). The spirit of international law. The University of Georgia Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blanke, H.-J., & Mangiameli, S. (2006). Governing Europe under a constitution: a hard road from the European treatise to a European constitutional treaty (pp. 169–184). Erfurt: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bozbayindir, A. E. (2013). Turkey and the international criminal court: A substantive criminal law analysis in the context of the principle of complementarity. Germany: Nomos Verlagsgeseells, Baden-Baden.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Carty, A. (1986). The decay of international law? Manchester University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Charlesworth, H., & Chinkin, C. (2000). The boundaries of international law: A feminist analysis. Manchester: Manchester University Press, Melland Schill Studies in International Law.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chayes, A., & Chayes, A. H. (1995). The new sovereignty: Compliance with international regulatory. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fedorova, M. (2012). The principles of equality of arms in international criminal proceedings. Cambridge: Intersentia.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fichtelberg, A. (2015). Hybrid tribunals, a comparative examination. Heidelberg: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goldsmith, J. L., & Posner, E. A. (2007). The limits of international law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodrich, P. (2006). Law in the courts of love: Literature and other minor jurisprudences. The Politics of Language.

    Google Scholar 

  • Graybill, R. V. Courts of love: Challenge to feudalism. In Essays in Medieval Studies (Vol. 5).

    Google Scholar 

  • Gross, H. (2012). Crime and punishment: A concise moral critique. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Grotius, H. Commentary on the Law of Prize and Booty.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hannikainen, L. (1988). Peremptory Norms (Jus Cogens) in International Law. Helsinki.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hora, T. (1986). Beyond the dream: A wakening to reality. The Crossroad Publishing Co. 1996.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (2014). The critique of pure reason (J. M. D. Meiklejohn, Trans.). An Electronic Classical Series Publication.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koskenniemi, M. (2005). From apology to Utopia. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kruse, K. R. (2010). Lawyers in character and lawyers in role. Nevada Law Review, 10, 393.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luther King, M., Jr. (1963). Strength to love. United States: Fortress Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malekian, F. (2005). Emasculating the philosophy of international criminal justice in the Iraqi special tribunal. Cornell International Law Journal, 38(3), 673–723.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malekian, F. (2014a). Jurisprudence of international criminal court. Cambridge: Cambridge Scholars Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malekian, F. (2014b). The international criminal law of children on war crimes. Prawa Dziecka i Ich Ochrona, Horyzonty Wychowania, 13(25), 31–69.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malekian, F., & Nordlöf, K. (2012a). The sovereignty of children in law (pp. 1–3).

    Google Scholar 

  • Malekian, F., & Nordlöf, K. (2012b). Confessing the international rights of children (pp. 1–5).

    Google Scholar 

  • Malekian, F. (2015). The canon of love against the use of force in Islamic and public international law: Part II: The anatomy of love against violations. International Criminal Law Review, 861–889.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marcin, R. B. (1984). Justice and love. Catholic University Law Review, 33(2), 363–391.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marks, S. (2000). The riddle of all constitutions: International law, democracy, and the critique of ideology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meron, T. (2006). The humanization of international law. Netherland: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pearce, R. (2002). Model Rule 1.0: lawyers are morally –accountable. Fordham Law Review, 70, 1805.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pepper, S. L. (1986). The lawyer’s amoral ethical role: A defence, a problem, and some possibilities. American Bar Foundation Research Journal, 613.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rinpoche, S. (2002). The Tibetan Book of Living and Dying: A spiritual classic from one of the foremost interpreters of Tibetan Buddhism to the West. CPI Cox and Wyman, Reading, RG1 8EX.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roback, M. J. (2001). Love & economics: Why the Laissez Faire family doesn’t work.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rollins, H. E. (Ed.). (1985). The Letters of John Keasts, 1814–1821 (Vol. 1).

    Google Scholar 

  • Simon, W. H. (1998). The practice of justice: A theory of lawyers’ ethics. United States: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spooner, L. (1882). Natural law; or the science of justice: A treatise on natural law, natural justice, natural rights, natural liberty, and natural society; showing that all legislation whatsoever is an absurdity, a usurpation, and a crime. Part First.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trechsel, S. (1997). Why must trials be fair. Israel Law Review, 31, 94–119.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Vattel, M. (1844). The law of nations or the principles of the law of nations applied to the conduct and affair of nations and sovereign (6th American Addition, A new edition by Joseph Chitty).

    Google Scholar 

  • Vischer, R. K. (2014). Martin Luther King Jr. and the morality of legal practice: Lessons in love and justice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Lockey, B. C. (2006). Law and Empire in English Renaissance Literature. Cambridge: Cambridge Publications.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • von Pufendorf, S. (1931). Two books of the elements of universal jurisprudence (1660) (W. Abbott, Oldfather, Trans.).

    Google Scholar 

  • von Rovira, M. G.-S. The project of positivism in international law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ward, I. (2001). Universal jurisprudence and the case for legal humanism. ALTA Law Review, 38, 941.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wendel, B. (2012). Lawyers and fidelity to law. New Jersey: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Malekian, F. (2017). The Right to Demand Love in Criminal Justice. In: Judgments of Love in Criminal Justice. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-46900-3_5

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-46900-3_5

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-46899-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-46900-3

  • eBook Packages: Law and CriminologyLaw and Criminology (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics