Skip to main content

Surveillance of the Norm of Love in Criminal Law

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Judgments of Love in Criminal Justice
  • 510 Accesses

Abstract

We will come back time and again to a few key terms in this lecture. These are “crime”, “legal”, “moral”, “criminal justice”, and “love”. The alarm clocks of the terms “crime”, “legal” and “moral” are ringing, but it seems like no one is truly listening. Almost in parallel, one can refer to the term “criminal justice” as constituting the most miserable institute. The unjust nature of criminal justice in practice and its impact on natural law justice, is like Hitler and Stalin’s cruel marching music colliding with Édith Piaf’s harmonious voice—non, je ne regrette rien”. She sang for the reestablishment of vanished rights for the sake of justice. The last but the most honourable term is “love”—let me echo her name again—the norm love. This is the most rational term that has to be established and integrated, with certain measures, into the terms “criminal law” and “criminal justice”, if justice is to be trusted and not misused by those with power. One of the world’s most romantic voices, Tom Jones, sang about “sex bomb”—I will demonstrate the necessity of the completion of our criminal law with a love bomb.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Let us to say, the “ethical judgment of our inadequate responses to political injustice.” Richards (2016), p. 120; See also https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=Q3Kvu6Kgp88; https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=vwe3CzWZ4Bg; https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=iEMggo5o0FM; https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=6-CA8jp6yoY; https://www.youtube.com/watch?v=ToB0Gez3Hdw (Accessed May 31 and June 1, 2015). See also Haveman et al. (2013).

  2. 2.

    Drapkin (1989), p. 95; Starr (1965), p. 280; Olmstead (1948), p. 125.

  3. 3.

    Voegelin and Franz (2000), pp. 207–208.

  4. 4.

    Thornton (2011), p. 18.

  5. 5.

    Walton (2008), p. 50.

  6. 6.

    Cohen (1949), p. 1025.

  7. 7.

    Raoult (2011), p. 26.

  8. 8.

    Andernaes (1974), p. 1.

  9. 9.

    Maeland (2013), p. 29.

  10. 10.

    Skeie (1937), p. 1; consult also Eser (2007). www.freidok.uni-freiburg.de/volltexte/6198.

  11. 11.

    Cohen (1949), p. 990.

  12. 12.

    For instance, see the Danish criminal law Langsted et al. (2011), p. 18.

  13. 13.

    Id.

  14. 14.

    Schabas (2002), pp. 1–3.

  15. 15.

    Consult Morrow (2002); see also Novak (2014), pp. 31–32, 73–74, 125–126.

  16. 16.

    Pre-Trial Chamber II, “Decision Pursuant to Article 15 of the Rome Statute on the Authorization of an Investigation into the Situation in the Republic of Kenya, ICC-01/09-19-Corr, p. 87, para 8 and 65. Italics added.

  17. 17.

    Cryer et al. (2010), p. 109.

  18. 18.

    Eskeland (2000), pp. 162–169. See also Rinceanu (2011a), pp. 281–296. Also Rinceanu (2011b), pp. 227–238.

  19. 19.

    Hirst (2003), pp. 236–281. Eskeland (2000), pp. 162–169; see also Eser (2008), pp. 863–893. www.freidok.uni-freiburg.de/volltexte/6318.

  20. 20.

    Consult several relevant articles on Darcy and Powderly (2010).

  21. 21.

    Robert Cryer, ‘The Ad Hoc Tribunals and the Law of Command Responsibility: Aquite Earthquake’ in Darcy and Powderly (2010), pp. 159–183.

  22. 22.

    The reference has solely been on joint criminal responsibility; see Mohamed Shahabudeen, ‘Judicial Creativity and Joint Criminal Enterprise’ in Darcy and Powderly (2010), pp. 184–203.

  23. 23.

    In the conclusion of my first book on international criminal law (1985), I drafted the concept of international criminality of states in seven articles in order to facilitate the future development of the concept (pp. 195–197). For the concept of international criminal responsibility of states see Malekian (1985).

  24. 24.

    Id.

  25. 25.

    For entities criminal liability see Rinceanu (2016), pp. 407–418.

  26. 26.

    Id.

  27. 27.

    Farhad Malekian, International Criminal Responsibility in Bassiouni (1999), pp. 192–221.

  28. 28.

    Id.

  29. 29.

    Id.

  30. 30.

    Often quoted from the Appeals Chamber in the Tadi jurisdiction. Majority Opinion para. 8. ICTY, Prosecutor v. Zlatko Aleksovski, Case No.: IT-95-14/1-A (24 March 2000). Available at http://www.icty.org/x/cases/aleksovski/acjug/en/ale-asj000324e.pdf (Accessed April 4, 2015).

  31. 31.

    Id.

  32. 32.

    Malekian (2015a), pp. 591–628; Shah-Kazemi (2014), pp. 73–101; Fouladvand (2012).

  33. 33.

    Id., pp. 593–594.

  34. 34.

    Id., p. 603.

  35. 35.

    Id., p. 601.

  36. 36.

    Sundin (1992), p. 13.

  37. 37.

    Alexius (1997), p. 15.

  38. 38.

    Ashworth (2013), p. 2.

  39. 39.

    Ashworth (2006), p. 68.

  40. 40.

    Ashworth (2013), p. 1.

  41. 41.

    Ashworth (2006), p. 68.

  42. 42.

    Cohen (1949), p. 996.

  43. 43.

    Id.

  44. 44.

    Fromm (1956). Available at https://archive.org/stream/TheArtOfLoving/43799393-The-Art-of-Loving-Erich-Fromm#page/n15/mode/2up (Accessed June 4, 2016).

  45. 45.

    Dickens (1859); See also Richards (2016).

  46. 46.

    Fromm (1956), p. 56.

  47. 47.

    An email message from Miss Dr. Narumi (2013-11-15-14:18).

  48. 48.

    PhR, Para.158A. Quoted in Westphal (1984), pp.77–92, at 87.

  49. 49.

    Mother Teresa.

  50. 50.

    Richards (2016), pp. 231–232; Malekian (2015b), pp. 889–892. For instance, the use of force against the natural environment or its destruction is clearly prohibited.

  51. 51.

    See Atwell (2008), p. 495; Gray (1995).

  52. 52.

    For a useful analysis of international human rights law, see Shelton (2014).

  53. 53.

    As it is stated “The human race, says Suárez, though it is divided into different peoples, possesses unity, not only as a species, but also a kind of political and moral unity. We know that that is so because there is a precept of natural law which enjoins us to love and to be charitable to all, even to strangers of every nation. Hence, though each single state is a perfect community, yet in relation to the human race states are none the less also in a sense members of a universal whole” Brierly (1948). Francisco Suárez was a Spanish philosopher and lawyer (1548–1617).

  54. 54.

    Malekian (2015b). For the development of the European Law consult. Weiler and Wind (2003).

  55. 55.

    Trechsel (1997), pp. 101–105.

  56. 56.

    di Beccaria (1872), pp. 143–144; http://oll.libertyfund.org/titles/beccaria-an-essay-on-crimes-and-punishments (Accessed April 27, 2015).

  57. 57.

    Venturi (1972), pp. 106–109.

  58. 58.

    Cohen (1949), pp. 1014–1018.

  59. 59.

    Martin Luther King. See also Vischer (2014), p. 6.

  60. 60.

    Nussbaum (2013), p. 15.

  61. 61.

    Consult also Souryal (2015).

  62. 62.

    Pufendorf (1717), p. 457. Available at http://find.galegroup.com/mome/quickSearch.do?now=1427655629859&inPS=true&prodId=MOME&userGroupName=mpi_vb (Accessed March 29, 2015).

  63. 63.

    Luther King (1967), p. 247. See also http://mlk-kpp01.stanford.edu/index.php/encyclopedia/documentsentry/where_do_we_go_from_here_delivered_at_the_11th_annual_sclc_convention/ (Accessed May 25, 2015).

  64. 64.

    Paracelsus (1493–1541).

  65. 65.

    Wägenbaur (2013), p. 1.

  66. 66.

    McAuley and McCutcheon (2000), pp. 2–3.

  67. 67.

    Id., pp. 4–6.

  68. 68.

    Al-Hussein (2009), p. 653. Available at http://www.auilr.org/; http://digitalcommons.wcl.american.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1098&context=auilr (Accessed October 20, 2014). See also the next sub-section.

  69. 69.

    Zahle (2005), pp. 317–319.

  70. 70.

    Ross (1939), pp. 325–326. David Ross clarifies that a clear distinction between the morally good and the morally right ‘will do much to remove some of the perplexities of our moral thought.’ Ross (1930), p. 7. See also Stern (2012).

  71. 71.

    Sohm (1935), pp. 28–29.

  72. 72.

    Id., p. 29.

  73. 73.

    Bentzon and Agersnap (2005), p. 8.

  74. 74.

    Kelsen (1941), p. 44.

  75. 75.

    For the concept of reliability of evidence, see Roberts and Redmayne (2009), pp. 1–18. See also the new examination of evidence by Daniele (2015a), pp. 179–194.

  76. 76.

    Rawls (1971), pp. 191–192.

  77. 77.

    Rawls (1971), p. 172.

  78. 78.

    Id.

  79. 79.

    Id.

  80. 80.

    Derrett (1968), p. vii.

  81. 81.

    Ross (1958), p. 29. Thus, the writer strongly attacks the opinion of Bentham and the doctrine of morality, pp. 290–292.

  82. 82.

    White and Willock (2007), p. 22.

  83. 83.

    Mill (1863), available at https://www.marxists.org/reference/archive/mill-john-stuart/1863/utility/ch02.htm (Accessed June 10, 2015).

  84. 84.

    Love is principle that most governments do not give any attention to. As has rightly been formulated “It’s the human principle of contact. It was my experience in dealing with people in soup kitchens and in our AIDS shelter that they were thirsting for someone to know them by name, to care about their life story, to care if they woke up the next morning, simple things like that. And government can’t do that. President Bush says this all the time, ‘Government cannot love.’ It’s very hard for government to be a neighbour.” Crisis Interview with Jim Towey, CRISIS, June 2002, at 40, 43 (defining subsidiary). Quoted in Czarnetzky and Rychlak (2003), p. 121.

  85. 85.

    Shelton (2014), pp. 294–295.

  86. 86.

    Ashworth (2008), p. 11.

  87. 87.

    Greve (2005), p. 532.

  88. 88.

    Fashing and Gottschalk (2008), p. 11.

  89. 89.

    Greve (2005), p. 515.

  90. 90.

    Id.

  91. 91.

    von Pufendorf (1931), p. 319. Available at http://oll.libertyfund.org/titles/2220 (Accessed March 29, 2015).

  92. 92.

    For false evidence, see Roberts and Redmayne (2009), p. 17.

  93. 93.

    Daniele (2015b), pp. 179–194, 181; Malekian (1992). Cited in Gray, note 58, at p. 12.

  94. 94.

    Roberts and Redmayne (2009), p. 17.

  95. 95.

    Prosecutor v. Nahimana, Barayagawiza and Negeza Case ICTR-99-52, Judgment and Sentence p. 945 (December 3, 2003).

  96. 96.

    Id., at para. 46.

  97. 97.

    Id.

  98. 98.

    Kant (1793), p. 87. Launched by Jonathan Bennett, available at http://www.earlymoderntexts.com/pdfs/kant1793part4.pdf (Accessed April 12, 2015).

  99. 99.

    Id.

  100. 100.

    Bernstein (2002), pp. 11–14.

  101. 101.

    Bondeson (2006), pp. 3–5.

  102. 102.

    Wägenbaur (2013), p. 1.

  103. 103.

    Id., pp. 2–3.

  104. 104.

    Cohen (1949), pp. 989–990.

  105. 105.

    Ashworth (2008), pp. 13–15.

  106. 106.

    Nussbaum (2013), pp. 2–4. See also Weiler (1999).

  107. 107.

    Andenaes (1965), p. 4.

  108. 108.

    Comprés (2009), p. 1027.

References

  • Alexius, K. (1997). Politisk Yttrandefrihet: En Studie i Lagstiftning och Praxis under Demkratins Genombrottstid. Lund.

    Google Scholar 

  • Al-Hussein, Z. (2009). For love of country and international criminal law. American University International Law Review, 24(4), 647–664.

    Google Scholar 

  • Andenaes, J. (1965). The general part of criminal law of Norway. London: Sweet & Maxwell Limited.

    Google Scholar 

  • Andernaes, J. (1974). Alminnelig Strafferett. Oslo: Universitertsforlaget.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ashworth, A. (2013). Positive obligations in criminal law. Oxford: Hart Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ashworth, A. (2006). Four threats to presumption of innocence. South African Journal, 63–97.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ashworth, A. (2008). Criminal procedure, human rights and ‘balance’: Towards the dark night sea? In Ikke Kun Straf: Festskrift til Vagen Greve (pp. 11–20). Jurist- og Økonomforbunds forlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Atwell, B. L. (2008). The jurisprudence of love. University of Detroit Mercy Law Review, 85, 495.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bassiouni, M. C. (1999). International criminal law: Crimes (2nd ed.). New York: Transnational Publishers, Inc. Ardsley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bentzon, A. W., & Agersnap, T. (2005). Retssikkerhed, Legitimitet og Tillid i et Aendringssmfund med Kulturelfoldighet. In C. Damgaard, C. Henrichsen, & H. Peterson (Eds.), Ret & Usikkerhed (pp. 5–20). Jurist- og Økonomforbunds forlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bernstein, R. J. (2002). Radical evil: A philosophical interrogation. Cambridge: Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bondeson, U. V. (2006). Theory of law and morality. In U. V. Bondeson (Ed.), Law and morality (pp. 3–16). Forlaget Thomson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brierly, J. L. (1948). Suárez’s vision of a world community. An address delivered before the University of Granada.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, M. (1949). Moral aspects of the criminal law. Yale Law Journal, 49, 987–1026.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Comprés, T. (2009). Labour of love: Using international labour law to achieve human rights for women sex workers in the Dominican Republic. Georgetown Journal of International Law, 40, 1027.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cryer, R., Friman, H., Robinson, D., & Wilmshurst, E. (2010). An introduction to international criminal law and procedure (2nd ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Czarnetzky, J. M., & Rychlak, R. J. (2003). An empire of law: Legalism and the international criminal court. Notre Dame Law review, 79, 55–126.

    Google Scholar 

  • Daniele, M. (2015a). Evidence gathering in the realm of the European investigation order from nations rules to global principles. New Journal of European Criminal Law, 6(2), 179–194.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Daniele, M. (2015). Evidence gathering in the realm of the European investigation order from nations rules to global principles. New Journal of European Criminal Law, 6(2), 179–194, 181.

    Google Scholar 

  • Darcy, S., & Powderly, J. (2010). Judicial creativity at the international criminal tribunals. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Derrett, J. D. M. (1968). An introduction to legal system.

    Google Scholar 

  • di Beccaria, C. B. (1872). An essay on crimes and punishments [1764]. De Voltaire.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dickens, C. (1859). A tale of two cities a story of the French revolution.

    Google Scholar 

  • Drapkin, I. (1989). Crime and punishment in the ancient world. Toronto: Lexington Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eser, A. (2007). The nature and rationale of punishment. Cardozo Law Review, 28, 2427–2436.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eser, A. (2008). Article 31: ‘Grounds for Excluding Criminal Responsibility’. In O. Triffterer (Ed.), Commentary on the Rome Statute of the International Criminal Court. Observers’ Notes Article by Article (2nd ed.). C.H. Beck, München et al.

    Google Scholar 

  • Eskeland, S. (2000). Strafferett. Oslo: Cappelen Akademisk Forlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fashing, I. A., & Gottschalk, P. (2008). Kriminelle Organisasjoner: Hvordan forstp organisert kiminalitet. Fagbokforlaget.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fouladvand, S. (2012). Complementarity and cultural sensitivity: Decision-making by the International Criminal Court (ICC) Prosecutor in Relation to the Situations in the Darfur Region of the Sudan and the Democratic Republic of Congo (DRC). Sussex.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fromm, E. (1956). The art of loving. Harper & Row.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gray, M.A. (1995). The International Crime of Ecocide. California Western International Journal, 26(2), 215–271. http://scholarlycommons.law.cwsl.edu/cgi/viewcontent.cgi?article=1335&context=cwilj. Accessed 25 Aug 2016.

  • Greve, V. (2005). Sheep or wolves. European Journal of Crime, Criminal Law and Criminal Justice, 4, 515–532.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haveman, R., Kavran, O., & Nicholls, J. (2013). Supranational criminal law: A system sui generis. Intersentia.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hirst, M. (2003). Jurisdiction and the ambit of the criminal law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, I. (1793). Religion within the Limits of Bare Reason.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelsen, H. (1941). The pure theory of law and analytical jurisprudence. Harvard Law Review, 55(1), 44–70.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Langsted, L. B., Greve, V., & Garde, P. (2011). Criminal law in Denmark. London: Kluwer Law International.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luther King, M., Jr. (1967). Where do we go from here: Chaos or community?

    Google Scholar 

  • Maeland, H. J. (2013). Norsk Alminnelig Strafferett. Bergen: Grafisk Formidling AS.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malekian, F. (1985). International criminal responsibility of states. Stockholm: Almqvist & Wiksell International.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malekian, F. (1992). The principal function of an international criminal tribunal, delivered at U.N. Int'l Inst. of Higher Studies in Criminal Sciences. In World Conference on the Establishment of an International Criminal Court to Enforce International Criminal Law and Human Rights, Siracusa, Italy, 2–5 December 1992.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malekian, F. (2015a). The Canon of love against the use of force in Islamic and public international law: Part I: The chamber of love within legal discipline. International Criminal Law Review, 15(4), 591–628.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Malekian, F. (2015b). The Canon of love against the use of force in Islamic and Public International Law: Part II: The anatomy of love against violations. International Criminal Law Review, 15, 861–895.

    Google Scholar 

  • McAuley, F., & McCutcheon, J. P. (2000). Criminal liability. Round Hall, Seet & Maxwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mill, J. S. (1863). Utilitarianism: What unitarianism is?

    Google Scholar 

  • Morrow, A. (2002). Killing in the name of love: Genocide of a nation. Rising Sun Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Novak, A. (2014). The global decline of the mandatory death penalty: Constitutional jurisprudence and legislative reform in Africa, Asia and the Caribbean. Surrey: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. C. (2013). Political emotions: Why love matters for justice. Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Olmstead, A. T. (1948). History of Persian Empire. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pufendorf, B. (1717). Of the law of nature and nations. Eight books (translated by Basil Kennet).

    Google Scholar 

  • Raoult, S. (2011). La theorisation de l’évolution pénale. Presses Universitaires D’Aix-Marseille.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of justice.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richards, D. A. J. (2016). Why love leads to justice: Love across the boundaries. New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rinceanu, J. (2011a). Extraterritorial jurisdiction – The applicability of domestic criminal law to activities committed abroad in Romania. In U. Sieber, S. Forster, & K. Jarvers (Eds.), National criminal law in a comparative legal context. Volume 2(1): Max-Planck-Institute für auslðndisches und internationals Strafrecht (pp. 281–296). Berlin: Duncker & Humblot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rinceanu, J. (2011b). Objective aspects of the offense in Romania. In U. Sieber, S. Forster, & K. Jarvers (Eds.), National criminal law in a comparative legal context. Volume 3(1): Max-Planck-Institute für auslðndisches und internationals Strafrecht (pp. 227–238). Berlin: Duncker & Humblot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rinceanu, J. (2016). Criminal liability of legal persons in Romania in Riccardo Borsari, Responsabilità da reato deli enti (pp. 407–418). Padova: Padova University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roberts, P., & Redmayne, M. (2009). Introduction: Teaching evidence scholarship. In P. Roberts & M. Redmayne (Eds.), Innovations in evidence and proof. Oxford: Hart Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross, W. D. (1939). Foundations of ethics. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross, W. D. (1930). The right and the good. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross, A. (1958). On law and justice. London: Stevens & Sons Limited.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schabas, W. A. (2002). The abolition of the death penalty in international law (3rd ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Shah-Kazemi, R. (2014). The metaphysics of oneness and sanctifying love in Islamic mysticism. In S.T. Hidden (Ed.), Jewish, Christian, and Islamic mystical perspectives on the Love of God (pp. 73–101). Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shelton, D. L. (2014). Advanced introduction to international human rights law. USA: Edward Elgar Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skeie, J. (1937). Den Norske Strafferett. Oslo: Olaf Norlis Forlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sohm, R. (1935). A textbook of the history and system of Roman private law (J. C. Ledlie, Trans.). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Souryal, S. S. (2015). Ethics in criminal justice: In search of the truth (6th ed.). New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Starr, C. G. (1965). A history of the ancient world. Oxford: University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stern, R. (2012). Understanding moral obligation: Kant, Hegel, Kierkegaard. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sundin, J. (1992). För Gud, Staten, Folket: Brott och Rättskipning I Sverige. Lund.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thornton, B. (2011). The Book of Ancient Bastards: 101 of the Worst Miscreants and Misdeeds from the Ancient Sumer to the English Tenement. USA: Adams Media.

    Google Scholar 

  • Trechsel, S. (1997). Why must trials be fair. Israel Law Review, 31, 94–119.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Venturi, F. (1972). Italy and enlightenment: Studies in a cosmopolitan century. New York: New York University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vischer, R. K. (2014). Martin Luther King Jr. and the morality of legal practice: lessons in love and justice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Voegelin, E., & Franz, M. (2000). Order and history (Vol. 4). University of Missouri Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Pufendorf, S. (1931). Two books of the elements of universal jurisprudence (1660) (W. Abbott, Oldfather, Trans.).

    Google Scholar 

  • Wägenbaur, B. (2013). Court of the European Union. C.H.Beck. Hart. Nomos.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walton, W. S. (2008). The Demos at Dawn. US: Author House.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weiler, J. H. H., & Wind, M. (2003). European Union law consult European constitutionalism beyond the state. Cambridge, UK; New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weiler, J. H. H. (1999). The Constitution of Europe: “Do the New Clothes have an Emperor?” and other Essays on European Integration. Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Westphal, M. (1984). Hegel’s radical idealism: Family and state as ethical communities. In Z. A. Pelczynski (Ed.), The state and civil society: Studies in Hegel’s political philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • White, R. M., & Willock, I. D. (2007). The Scottish legal system (4th ed.). Glasgow: Tottel Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zahle, H. (2005). Praktisk restfilosofi. Christian Ejlers’ Forlag.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing AG

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Malekian, F. (2017). Surveillance of the Norm of Love in Criminal Law. In: Judgments of Love in Criminal Justice. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-46900-3_1

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-46900-3_1

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-46899-0

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-46900-3

  • eBook Packages: Law and CriminologyLaw and Criminology (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics