Skip to main content

Final Destination Relativistic Historicism?

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 313 Accesses

Abstract

Strictly universal laws are necessary in the theoretical social sciences including economics, but all attempts of Mises’ contemporaries to justify them are unsustainable, according to Mises and proponents of historicism. Despite this agreement, Mises relation to historicist positions is judicial. Mises critically describes the limitations of the method of historical understanding (Verstehen). In spite of the obstacles presented in Chapter 2, he maintains that relativistic historism, which he ascribes to Weber, Rickert, Windelband, Collingwood, Dilthey, and Schmoller, and which in Mises’ eyes represents a major threat to the discipline of economics and to human civilization, can be avoided by praxeology.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   49.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   64.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   64.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    One such rule of thumb is that people probably act approximately like in the past (Mises [1957] 2005, 142).

  2. 2.

    Until the present, discussions that superficially address methodology of economics actually reveal different conceptions of the boundaries of the scientific discipline. These boundaries may either define a certain class of phenomena, for instance “economic” behavior, as the object of inquiry, or emphasize a specific perspective on a – usually wider – field of phenomena. Stressing that economics is concerned with a specific aspect of phenomena instead of certain kinds of phenomena gives rise to what is often criticized as economic imperialism – the pervasion of various disciplines by economic methodology. At any rate, once criteria for interesting and justified knowledge in economics are agreed upon, specific research programs result from them. Political economy, econometrics, praxeology, rational choice theory, institutional economics, and behavioral game theory all differ; not least with regards to their empiricism and their normativity. Confer Kirzner ([1960] 1976); Hoover (1995); Milford (2015).

  3. 3.

    Interestingly enough, Mises changed both his epistemological position and his political and economic position in that time. He entered the University of Vienna as an etatist and started doubting whether interventionism functions (Mises [1940, 1978] 2009, 11).

  4. 4.

    Confer Iggers (1983).

  5. 5.

    The only exceptions would be usually rather uninteresting “descriptions” where an object o is said to have a property P, which is defined solely by listing all the finitely many members of its extension, say P:={o,q,r,s}. Such artificial exceptions could be constructed for relations as well.

  6. 6.

    Confer Mises ([1957] 2005, 140–41). Given praxeological theorems remain true or false irrespective of the economic system, what might certainly change is how interesting or practically relevant they are. Mises supposedly would not deny, for example, that if we lived in an economic system without business cycles, elaborating the details of praxeological business cycle theory would lose its practical urgency.

References

  • Hoover, Kevin D. 1995. “Why Does Methodology Matter for Economics?” The Economic Journal 105(430): 715–734. doi: 10.2307/2235030.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Iggers, Georg G. 1983. The German Conception of History: The National Tradition of Historical Thought from Herder to the Present. Rev. ed., 1st Wesleyan pbk. ed. Middletown, CT, Scranton, PA: Wesleyan University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kirzner, Israel M. (1960) 1976. The Economic Point of View: An Essay in the History of Economic Thought. 2 edn. Studies in Economic Theory. Kansas City: Sheed and Ward.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2010. “On Menger, Hayek and on the Concept of ‘Verstehen’.” In Hagemann, Nishizawa, and Ikeda 2010, 257–275.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2015. “Zur Entwicklung der Volkswirtschaftslehre an der Universität Wien von 1763 bis 1976”. In Reflexive Innensichten aus der Universität: Disziplinengeschichten zwischen Wissenschaft, Gesellschaft und Politik, edited by Karl Fröschl, Gerd B. Müller, Thomas Olechowski, and Brigitta Schmidt-Lauber, 341–354 650 Jahre Universität Wien – Aufbruch ins neue Jahrhundert; Bd. 4. Göttingen: V&R unipress.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1940. Nationalökonomie: Theorie des Handelns und Wirtschaftens. Genf: Editions Union.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. (1962) 1990. “Epistemological Relativism in the Sciences of Human Action”. In Money, Method, and the Market Process: Essays by Ludwig Von Mises, edited by Richard M. Ebeling, 37–51. Auburn, AL: Praxeology Press of the Ludwig von Mises Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. (1942) 1990. “Social Science and Natural Science”. In Money, Method, and the Market Process: Essays by Ludwig Von Mises, edited by Richard M. Ebeling, 3–15. Auburn, AL: Praxeology Press of the Ludwig von Mises Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. (1944) 1990b. “The Treatment of ‘Irrationality’ in the Social Sciences”. In Money, Method, and the Market Process: Essays by Ludwig Von Mises, edited by Richard M. Ebeling, 16–36. Auburn, AL: Praxeology Press of the Ludwig von Mises Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. (1933) 2003. Epistemological Problems of Economics. 3rd edn. Auburn, AL: Ludwig Von Mises Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. (1969) 2003. The Historical Setting of the Austrian School of Economics. Online Edition. New Rochelle: Arlington House, Ludwig von Mises Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. (1957) 2005. Theory and History: An Interpretation of Social and Economic Evolution. Liberty Fund Library of the Works of Ludwig Von Mises. Indianapolis, IN: Liberty Fund.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. (1940, 1978) 2009. Memoirs. Auburn, AL: Ludwig Von Mises Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. (1929) 2011. A Critique of Interventionism. Auburn, AL: Ludwig von Mises Instuitue.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mises, Ludwig von, and Bettina B. Greaves. 2004. The Free Market and Its Enemies: Pseudo-Science, Socialism, and Inflation. Irvington-on-Hudson: Foundation for Economic Education.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zilian, Hans G. 1990. Klarheit und Methode: Felix Kaufmanns Wissenschaftstheorie. Studien zur österreichischen Philosophie 16. Amsterdam: Rodopi

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Linsbichler, A. (2017). Final Destination Relativistic Historicism?. In: Was Ludwig von Mises a Conventionalist?. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-46170-0_3

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-46170-0_3

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Palgrave Macmillan, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-46169-4

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-46170-0

  • eBook Packages: Economics and FinanceEconomics and Finance (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics