Skip to main content

Model-Based Knowledge and Credible Policy Analysis

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Book cover Philosophy of Science in Practice

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 379))

Abstract

This chapter elaborates the concept of credibility as a yardstick for the assessment of model-based policies. We further distinguish between epistemic and strategic credibility and show how this distinction helps us to understand the relation between models and the assessment of public policies. For policy assessment purposes, credibility depends mostly on extrapolation. Such extrapolations have a better chance of success if we draw on a causal mechanism, as structural models do. The sort of empiricism about causal interventions promoted, among others, by field trialists in economics has a lower chance of being epistemically credible. Furthermore, the reductive relationship between strategic credibility to epistemic credibility would lack of stability.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 119.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    House of Commons: Treasury Committee (2006), p. EV53.

  2. 2.

    See Sugden (2000, 2009) and the special issue of Erkenntnis (vol. 70, issue 1, 2009).

  3. 3.

    See also, inter alia, Stokey (1991) and Drazen and Masson (1994).

  4. 4.

    See Chao and Huang (2011) for the history of Liu’s and Sims’ econometric approaches.

  5. 5.

    In this sense, Hendry subscribes to the position of pessimistic induction in the philosophy of science. See Chao (2009) for Hendry’s empirical methodology of econometrics.

  6. 6.

    Note that Sims (2010) forcibly denies both Angrist and Pischke’s (2010) conception about macroeconomics and the similarity between their research design methodology and his vector-autoregressive modeling approach.

  7. 7.

    Manski and Garfinkel’s notion of extrapolation originates from its usage in the econometric literature, which understands extrapolation to be an ex-post test on how the model fits the observed data.

  8. 8.

    For this view, see Imbens (2010, p. 417).

  9. 9.

    Steel does discuss extrapolation in the context of applied economics. See his research (2013) on Donohue and Levitt’s (2001, 2004) study on the causal relation between legalized abortion and crime rate.

  10. 10.

    A more serious problem for Steel’s account is whether comparative process tracing can really solve the extrapolator’s circle. Comparative process tracing requires sufficient knowledge of the mechanism of the target, but how much information is sufficient for the researchers to decide what works for the model works for the target is perhaps non-consensusal. Furthermore, the model’s external validity depends on its resemblance to the target. As the example of the carcinogenic effect of aflatoxin B1 shows, to decide rats are better models than mice, researchers need to study humans, but once there are such studies on humans, the rodent study seems unnecessary, except for the ethical reason that we cannot conduct experiments on humans (Howick et al. 2013). The task is indeed to find satisfactory models rather than to find out the nature of the target. In that case, given that extrapolation is hindered by various threats and structure-altering changes, social scientists may just go ahead to uncover the mechanism of the target to ensure that the policy works.

  11. 11.

    See Hesse (1966) for analogy and Giere (1988) for similarity accounts of models.

  12. 12.

    However, the question for social science is whether capacities are easy to come by. See Reiss (2008).

  13. 13.

    See also Hoover (2015) for the genesis of the version of the price-inflation Phillips curve.

  14. 14.

    Friedman (1968) and Phelps (1967) argue that, in the long run, the inflation-unemployment tradeoff does not apply, because the agents are fully aware of aggregate prices and inflation such that price and wage decisions are consistent.

References

  • Angrist, J. D., & Pischke, J.-S. (2010). The credibility revolution in empirical economics: How better research design is taking the con out of econometrics. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 24, 3–30.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1989). Nature’s capacities and their measurement. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1995). Reply to Eells, Humphreys and Morrison. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 55, 177–187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (1998). Capacities. In J. B. Davis, D. Wade Hands, & U. Mäki (Eds.), The handbook of economic methodology (pp. 45–48). Aldershot: Edward Elgar.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (2007a). Hunting causes and using them. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (2007b). Are RCTs the gold standard? Biosocieties, 2, 11–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N., & Hardie, J. (2012). Evidence-based policy: A practical guide to doing it better. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N., & Stegenga, J. (2011). A theory of evidence for evidence-based policy. In P. Dawid, W. Twining, & M. Vasilaki (Eds.), Evidence, inference and enquiry. London: Oxford University Press: British Academy.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chao, H.-K. (2009). Representation and structure in economics: The methodology of econometric models of the consumption function. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chao, H.-K., & Huang, C.-H. (2011). Ta-Chung Liu’s exploratory econometrics. History of Political Economy, 43, 140–165.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chassang, S., Miquel, G. P. I., & Snowberg, E. (2012). Selective trials: A principal-agent approach to randomized controlled experiments. American Economic Review, 102, 1279–1309.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Darden, L., & Craver, C. (2002). Strategies in the interfield discovery of the mechanism of protein synthesis. Studies in History and Philosophy of Biological and Biomedical Sciences, 33, 1–28.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Deaton, A. (2010). Instruments, randomization, and learning about development. Journal of Economic Literature, 48, 424–455.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Donohue, J., & Levitt, S. (2001). The impact of legalized abortion on crime. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 116, 379–420.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Donohue, J., & Levitt, S. (2004). Further evidence that legalized abortion lowered crime: A reply to joyce. Journal of Human Resources, 39, 29–49.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Drazen, A., & Masson, P. R. (1994). Credibility of policies versus credibility of policymakers. Quarterly Journal of Economics, 109, 735–754.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fellner, W. J. (1976). Towards a reconstruction of macroeconomics: Problems of theory and policy. Washington, DC: American Enterprise Institute.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fellner, W. J. (1979). The credibility effect and rational expectations: Implications of the Gramlich study. Brookings Papers on Economic Activity, 1, 167–78.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Forder, J. (2014). Macroeconomics and the Phillips curve myth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. (1968). The role of monetary policy. American Economic Review, 58, 1–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. N. (1988). Explaining science: A cognitive approach. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Glymour, C. (1980). Theory and evidence. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guala, F. (Forthcoming). Performativity rationalized. In I. Boldyrev & E. Svetlova (Eds.), Enacting the dismal science: New perspectives on the performativity of economics. London: Palgrave-Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heckman, J. J. (2005). The scientific model of causality. Sociological Methodology, 35, 1–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hendry, D. F. (2005). Bridging the gap: Linking economics and econometrics. In C. Diebolt & C. Kyrtsou (Eds.), New trends in macroeconomics (pp. 53–77). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Hesse, M. B. (1966). Models and analogies in science. Notre Dame: Notre Dame University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoover, K. D. (2015). The genesis of Samuelson and Solow’s price-inflation Phillips curve. History of Economics Review, 61, 1–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • House of Commons: Treasury Committee. (2006). The 2006 budget, fourth report of session 2005–06 (Vol. II). London: The Stationery Office Limited.

    Google Scholar 

  • Howick, J., Glasziou, P., & Aronson, J. K. (2013). Problems with using mechanisms to solve the problem of extrapolation. Theoretical Medicine and Bioethics, 34, 275–291.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Imbens, G. W. (2010). Better late than nothing. Journal of Economic Literature, 48, 399–423.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kydland, F. E., & Prescott, E. C. (1977). Rules rather than discretion: The inconsistency of optimal plans. Journal of Political Economy, 85(3), 473–492.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liu, T.-C. (1963). Structural estimation and forecasting: A critique of the Cowles commission method. Tsing Hua Journal of Chinese Studies, 4, 152–171.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, P., Darden, L., & Craver, C. F. (2000). Thinking about mechanisms. Philosophy of Science, 67, 1–25.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • MacKenzie, D. A. (2006). An engine, not a camera: How financial models shape markets. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Manski, C. F. (2007). Identification for prediction and decision. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Manski, C. F., & Garfinkel, I. (1992). Evaluating welfare and training programs. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • McCallum, B. T. (1984). Credibility and monetary policy. In Prices stability and public policy: A symposium sponsored by the Federal Reserve Bank of Kansas (pp. 105–135).

    Google Scholar 

  • Miguel, E., & Kremer, M. (2004). Worms: Identifying impacts on education and health in the presence of treatment externalities. Econometrica, 72, 159–217.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Phelps, E. S. (1967). Phillips curves, expectations of inflation and optimal unemployment over time. Economica, 34, 254–281.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Popper, K. R. (1963). Conjectures and refutations: The growth of scientific knowledge. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reiss, J. (2008). Social capacities. In S. Hartmann & L. Bovens (Eds.), Nancy Cartwright’s philosophy of science (pp. 265–288). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Reiss, J. (2010). Review of Across Boundaries. Economics and Philosophy, 26, 382–390.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rosenberg, A. (2012). Why do spatiotemporally restricted regularities explain in the social sciences? The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 63, 1–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rudebusch, G. D. (1996). Is opportunistic monetary policy credible? FRBSF Economic Letter. http://www.frbsf.org/economic-research/publications/economic-letter/1996/october/is-opportunistic-monetary-policy-credible/

  • Sims, C. A. (1980). Macroeconomics and reality. Econometrica, 48, 1–48.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sims, C. A. (2010). But economics is not an experimental science. Journal of Economic Perspectives, 24, 59–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steel, D. (2008). Across the boundaries: Extrapolation in biology and social science. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Steel, D. (2013). Mechanisms and extrapolation in the abortion-crime controversy. In H.-K. Chao, S.-T. Chen, & R. L. Millstein (Eds.), Mechanism and causality in biology and economics (pp. 185–206). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Stokey, N. L. (1991). Credible public policy. Journal of Economic Dynamics and Control, 15, 627–656.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sugden, R. (2000). Credible worlds: The status of theoretical models in economics. Journal of Economic Methodology, 7, 1–31.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sugden, R. (2009). Credible worlds, capacities and mechanisms. Erkenntnis, 70, 3–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

Chao’s research is sponsored by the Ministry of Science and Technology of Taiwan under grant NSC 102-2628-H-007 -003 -MY3. Teira’s research was funded by the research grants FFI2011-28835 and FFI2014-57258-P.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Hsiang-Ke Chao .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Chao, HK., Teira, D. (2017). Model-Based Knowledge and Credible Policy Analysis. In: Chao, HK., Reiss, J. (eds) Philosophy of Science in Practice. Synthese Library, vol 379. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-45532-7_10

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics