Skip to main content

Why Care beyond the Square? Classical and Extended Shapes of Oppositions in Their Application to “Introspective Disputes”

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Part of the book series: Studies in Universal Logic ((SUL))

Abstract

So called “shapes of opposition”—like the classical square of opposition and its extensions—can be seen as graphical representations of the ways in which types of statements constrain each other in their possible truth values. As such, they can be used as a novel way of analysing the subject matter of disputes. While there have been great refinements and extensions of this logico-topological tool in the last years, the broad range of shapes of opposition are not widely known outside of a circle of specialists. This ignorance may lead to the presumption that the classical square of opposition fits all disputes. A broader view, which takes expanded shapes of opposition into account, may come to a more nuanced appraisal of possible disputes. Once we take other shapes of opposition into account, some alleged disputes may turn out to be Scheindisputes. In order to do the wide range of linguistic expressions justice and to differentiate Scheindisputes from real ones, a broader view is advised. To illustrate this point, I discuss the notion of “introspective disputes”. These are commonly reconstructed as obeying the square, but are more aptly reconstructed with a more complex octagon. If we reconstruct these disputes based on Buridan’s octagon, it becomes obvious that “introspective disputes” are likely Scheindisputes.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   69.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   89.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    For example, “Laura is rich” and “Laura is poor” are not syntactically or on the surface levels negations of another (because there is no “not” involved at all). Still, both sentences are contrary to another, because both can be simultaneously false: Laura could simply be doing alright.

  2. 2.

    See e.g. [4, 5, 11, 19, 23, 24, 38], as well as the examples in this volume for specialists’ papers on the shapes of opposition.

  3. 3.

    Sometimes, the method is broadened: Reports that are deemed to express an introspectively formed opinion or questionnaires about experiences are sometimes seen as introspection as well.

  4. 4.

    Some argue that more than the phenomenal aspects of experiences can be introspected. There might then be introspective disputes concerning attitudes, content, experience onset, and so on. I will focus only on introspective disputes concerning phenomenal aspects of experiences, as this subject matter provides the best examples for introspective disputes.

  5. 5.

    See [34, Chap. 2] for a discussion with more historical references.

  6. 6.

    Armstrong [2, 300], for example, argues for this, and seems to justify that claim by introspection.

  7. 7.

    See also Zahavi [43, 132]: “Whereas we live through a number of different experiences, the dimension of first-personal experiencing remains the same […] it may be described as an invariant dimension of first-personal givenness throughout the multitude of changing experiences.”

  8. 8.

    See also Hume [14, Sect. VI].

  9. 9.

    One may wonder how one justifies the general opinion by introspective acquaintance. But the method of eidetic or Phenomenological variation builds on one’s direct grasp of phenomenal experiences to justify such general statements. General statements about phenomenality can then be justified by one’s grasp of one’s experiences from the first-person perspective. So there are similar disputes in Phenomenology. For the purpose at hand, we may see such Phenomenological disputes as part of the larger class of introspective disputes.

  10. 10.

    See also Dennett [8, 66]: “It is just astonishing to see how often ‘academic’ discussions of phenomenological controversies degenerate into desk-thumping cacophony, with everybody talking past everybody else. This is all the more surprising, in a way, because according to long-standing philosophical tradition, we all agree on what we find when we “look inside” at our own phenomenology. […] just about every author who has written about consciousness has made what we might call the first-person plural presumption: Whatever mysteries consciousness may hold, we (you, gentle reader, and I) may speak comfortably together about our mutual acquaintances, the things we both find in our streams of consciousness. […] This would be fine if it weren’t for the embarrassing fact that controversy and contradiction bedevil the claims under these conditions of polite mutual agreement. We are fooling ourselves about something.”

  11. 11.

    The epistemological problem regarding phenomenological, first-person approaches of “data generation” [meant as scare quotes] is that if inconsistencies in two individual “data sets” [scare quotes again] should appear, there is no way to settle the conflict. […] This is a third defining characteristic of the scientific way of approaching reality: there are procedures to settle conflicts resulting from conflicting hypotheses. Epistemic progress continues.” [21, 591].

  12. 12.

    “I aim to persuade you that people in general know very little about what might seem to be obvious features of their stream of conscious experience […] People often differ greatly in their judgments about their stream of experience (across cultures, between individuals within the same culture, or within the same individual over time). Sometimes, in such cases, it seems unlikely that their actual underlying experiences vary correspondingly. Consequently, some of their judgments—we don’t necessarily know which ones—are probably wrong.” [34, ix–x].

  13. 13.

    Kriegel [16, 122f] augurs this: “The above phenomenological disputes, and others like them, are disconcerting inasmuch as the Consciousness Studies community does not have accepted guidelines for adjudicating them. Phenomenological disputes have a way of leading to apparent deadlocks with remarkable immediacy. Disputants reach the foot-stomping stage of the dialectic more or less right after declaring their discordant positions. […] The most violent reaction is to claim that there is no fact of the matter concerning these disputes.”

  14. 14.

    This is in accord with the presumption that a square of opposition is committed to existential import [1, II, 176, 20–21]. That is, if I were to claim that all goblins eat cheese and you claim that no goblin eats cheese, either statement commits us to the existence of goblins if we presume that we two are in a dispute [see also 30]. If we reject the presumption that we are in a dispute, we thereby reject the ontological commitment: If there are no goblins, we do not need to fight over their affinity to cheese. Rejecting the existence claim means that general statements can (under some views) be considered true, but vacuously so. This affects disputes based on contrary opinions.

  15. 15.

    However, see [12] for a conflicting view.

  16. 16.

    Buridan’s example is of a man’s ass running, i.e. omnis asinus hominis currit.Hominis” is here in the genitive.

  17. 17.

    See especially [28] for a discussion of this form and its variations.

  18. 18.

    In contrast to the reconstruction as an octagon, one might think that there should in principle be sixteen different types of statements and, therefore, a sixteen-sided figure: While I have introduced A- and I-statements (universally and particularly affirmative statements), I have ignored the possible forms of E- or O-statements (universally and particularly negative statements). Only a sixteen-sided figure would accommodate these additional eight statement-types.

    Why are these omitted? Because each is equivalent to some of the forms mentioned. Consider the case of an AA-statement like “For all experiencers, all their thoughts have phenomenal aspects.” This is equivalent to the EO-statement “For all experiencers, none of their thoughts fails to have phenomenal aspects.” And consider an II-statement like “For some experiencer, some thought have phenomenal aspects.” This is equivalent with the OE-statement that “For some experiencers, not all thoughts fail to have phenomenal aspects.” The general rule for such quantifier-involving statements is: To find the equivalent statement to some \(\Gamma \Delta \)-statement, take the contrary or subcontrary type to \(\Gamma \) in the classical square (A transforms to E, I to O, and vice versa) and the contradictory form to \(\Delta \) in the square (A transforms to O, I to E, and vice versa). This leads to a reduction of a hypothetical 16-sided figure to the octagon in the following way: AA ≡ EO; AE ≡ EI; AI ≡ EE; AO ≡ EO; IA ≡ OO; IE ≡ OI; II ≡ OE; IO ≡ OA. Thus, we may continue with the octagon as presented in Fig. 2.

  19. 19.

    Especially the person whose opinion this is.

  20. 20.

    Levin [17] argued that induction plays a major part of Phenomenological or eidetic variation, which is often used to justify such statements.

  21. 21.

    This article is built on work published in my PhD-thesis (2015) at the University of Osnabrück. This work has been supported by a Lichtenberg scholarship. I am grateful to Karsten Engel and one anonymous reviewer for helpful comments, and also to the organisers of Square 2014 at the Vatican for a very enjoyable conference.

References

  1. P. Abaelardus, Dialectica (After the Parisian Manuscript MS. Lat. 14.614) (Koninklijke Van Gorcum & Comp. N. V., Assen, 1970/before 1125)

    Google Scholar 

  2. D.M. Armstrong, The Nature of Mind (Cornell University Press, Ithaca, 1981)

    Google Scholar 

  3. T. Bayne, M. Spener, Introspective humility. Philos. Issues 20 (1), 1–22 (2010)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  4. J.-Y. Béziau, New light on the square of oppositions and its nameless corner. Log. Investig. 10, 218–233 (2003)

    Google Scholar 

  5. J.-Y. Béziau, D. Jacquette (eds), Around and Beyond the Square of Opposition (Birkhäuser, Basel, 2012)

    Google Scholar 

  6. J. Buridan, Summulae de Dialectica (Yale University Press, New Haven, 2001)

    Google Scholar 

  7. F. Crick, The Astonishing Hypothesis: The Scientific Search For The Soul (Scribner, New York, 1995)

    Google Scholar 

  8. D.C. Dennett, Consciousness Explained (Little, Brown, Boston, 1991)

    Google Scholar 

  9. F.I. Dretske, Naturalizing the Mind (MIT Press, Cambridge, 1995)

    Google Scholar 

  10. P. Goff, A priori physicalism, lonely ghosts and cartesian doubt. Conscious. Cogn. 21 (2), 742–746 (2012). Standing on the Verge: Lessons and Limits from the Empirical Study of Consciousness, http://www.sciencedirect.com/science/article/pii/S105381001100033X

  11. E.A. Hacker, The octagon of opposition. Notre Dame J. Form. Log. 16 (3), 352–353 (1975)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  12. W. Hirstein, Mindmelding: Consciousness, Neuroscience, and the Mind’s Privacy (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2012)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  13. T. Horgan, J. Tienson, The intentionality of phenomenology and the phenomenology of intentionality, in Philosophy of Mind: Classical and Contemporary Readings, ed. by D.J. Chalmers (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 2002)

    Google Scholar 

  14. D. Hume, A Treatise of Human Nature: A Critical Edition (Clarendon Press, Oxford, 1739–40/2007)

    Google Scholar 

  15. W. James, The Principles of Psychology (Holt, New York, 1890/1957)

    Google Scholar 

  16. U. Kriegel, The phenomenologically manifest. Phenomenol. Cogn. Sci. 6 (1), 115–136 (2007)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  17. D.M. Levin, Induction and Husserl’s theory of eidetic variation. Philos. Phenomenol. Res. 29 (1), 1–15 (1968), http://www.jstor.org/stable/2105814

    Article  Google Scholar 

  18. J. Levine, Qualia: Intrinsic, relational or what?, in Conscious Experience, ed. by T. Metzinger (Schöningh, Paderborn, 1995), pp. 277–292

    Google Scholar 

  19. D. Luzeaux, J. Sallantin, C. Dartnell, Logical extensions of Aristotle’s square. Log. Univers. 2 (1), 167–187 (2008)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  20. T. Metzinger, The problem of consciousness, in Conscious Experience, ed. by T. Metzinger (Schöningh, Paderborn, 1995), pp. 3–40

    Google Scholar 

  21. T. Metzinger, Being No One (MIT Press, Cambridge, 2004)

    Google Scholar 

  22. G.E. Moore, Sense Data (George Allen & Unwin, London, 1953), Chap. II, pp. 28–40

    Google Scholar 

  23. A. Moretti, Geometry for modalities? Yes: Through n-opposition theory. Aspects Univers. Log. 17, 102–145 (2004)

    Google Scholar 

  24. A. Moretti, The Geometry of Logical Opposition, PhD thesis, University of Neuchâtel, Switzerland (2009)

    Google Scholar 

  25. J.K. O’Regan, A. Noë, A sensorimotor account of vision and visual consciousness. Behav. Brain Sci. 24, 939–1031 (2001)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  26. C. Peacocke, Sense and Content (Oxford University Press, Oxford, 1983)

    Google Scholar 

  27. J.J. Prinz, The ins and outs of consciousness. Brain Mind 1 (2), 245–256 (2000)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  28. S. Read, John Buridan’s theory of consequence and his octagons of opposition, in Around and Beyond the Square of Opposition, ed. by J.-Y. Béziau, D. Jacquette. Studies in Universal Logic (Springer, Basel, 2012), pp. 93–110

    Google Scholar 

  29. B. Roberts, The Experience of No-Self: A Contemplative Journey (State University of New York Press, New York, 1993)

    Google Scholar 

  30. B. Russell, H. MacColl, The existential import of propositions. Mind 14 (55), 398–402 (1905). http://www.jstor.org/stable/2248428

    Article  Google Scholar 

  31. E. Schwitzgebel, Why did we think we dreamed in black and white? Stud. Hist. Philos. Sci. 33, 649–660 (2002)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  32. E. Schwitzgebel, Do people still report dreaming in black and white? An attempt to replicate a questionnaire from 1942. Percept. Mot. Skills 96, 25–29 (2003)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  33. E. Schwitzgebel, The unreliability of naive introspection. Philos. Rev. 117 (2), 245–273 (2008)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  34. E. Schwitzgebel, Perplexities of Consciousness (MIT Press, Cambridge, 2011)

    Google Scholar 

  35. E. Schwitzgebel, C. Huang, Y. Zhou, Do we dream in color? cultural variations and skepticism. Dreaming 16, 36–42 (2006)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  36. J. Searle, The Rediscovery of Mind (MIT Press, Cambridge, 1992)

    Google Scholar 

  37. C. Siewert, The Significance of Consciousness (Princeton University Press, Princeton, 1998)

    Book  Google Scholar 

  38. H. Smessaert, L. Demey, Logical geometries and information in the square of oppositions. J. Log. 23, 527–565 (2014)

    Google Scholar 

  39. A.D. Smith, The Problem of Perception (Harvard University Press, Cambridge, 2000)

    Google Scholar 

  40. M. Tye, Visual qualia and visual content, in The Contents of Experience, ed. by T. Crane (Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1992), pp. 158–176

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  41. R.A. Wilson, Intentionality and phenomenology. Pac. Philos. Q. 84, 413–431 (2003)

    Article  Google Scholar 

  42. D. Zahavi, Self-Awareness and Alterity (Northwestern University Press, Evanston, 1999)

    Google Scholar 

  43. D. Zahavi, Subjectivity and Selfhood: Investigating the First-Person Perspective (MIT Press, Cambridge, 2005)

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Sascha Benjamin Fink .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Fink, S.B. (2017). Why Care beyond the Square? Classical and Extended Shapes of Oppositions in Their Application to “Introspective Disputes”. In: Béziau, JY., Basti, G. (eds) The Square of Opposition: A Cornerstone of Thought. Studies in Universal Logic. Birkhäuser, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-45062-9_20

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics