Skip to main content

A (Contrarian’s) Reappraisal of the History and Current State of the Ontology Debate in the Philosophy of Space

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Deep Metaphysics of Space

Part of the book series: European Studies in Philosophy of Science ((ESPS))

  • 435 Accesses

Abstract

If substantivalism (absolutism) holds that space is an independently existing entity, and relationism claims that space is only a relation between such entities, then what do alternative ontologies of space, which are allegedly neither substantivalist nor relationist, contend? This chapter will begin the discussion of this central question, although, as will become apparent throughout our investigation, there is much uncertainty regarding the content and scope of both substantivalism and relationism as well. In §1.1, a brief overview of the ideas and influences that have shaped the contemporary evolution and understanding of the standard dichotomy, i.e., substantivalism and relationism, will be provided, whereas §1.2 will offer a preliminary categorization of alternative spatial ontologies. In contrast, §1.3 will examine the background to the modern dichotomy at the beginning of the seventeenth century, that is, in the period just prior to the contributions of Newton and Leibniz, as well as provide a brief synopsis of the concepts that guided Descartes’ natural philosophy of space and motion. This section of the chapter will begin to reveal the extraordinary obstacles that face any attempt to draw a clear line of conceptual lineage from the natural philosophy of space typically practiced in the seventeenth century to the presuppositions that inform the modern dichotomy.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 69.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 89.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 119.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    No references will be offered here since one cannot cite every work on the philosophy of space that postdates Newton and Leibniz’s time (or, to be a bit more careful, nearly every work). However, Descartes is often paired with Leibniz as a chief early exponent of relationism.

  2. 2.

    The analysis of symmetries in physics is itself a contentious issue, especially in modern field theories, but the simplified description provided above is adequate apropos the relationship between the metaphysical spatiotemporal hypotheses and the type of classical mechanical concepts implicit in Newton and Leibniz’ natural philosophy. See, Earman (1989, chapter 2) for a detailed presentation of these spacetime structures, and, Slowik (2002, chapter 2), for an informal discussion that is similar to, but more elaborate than, the one offered above.

  3. 3.

    This is, in fact, the case with Huygens, who was originally content to side with an absolutist (or non-relational) understanding of rotation, but took the challenge of Newton’s spinning bucket and rotating globes thought experiments as a motivation to develop an account consistent with relational motion; see, Stein (1977a), Bernstein (1984).

  4. 4.

    As used in our investigation, “physical” will pertain to both matter and fields, since, for some readers, “matter” and “material” may not be associated with the modern field notion in physics.

  5. 5.

    See, e.g., Casey 1997. One should mention Foster’s (1982) spatial idealism, or anti-realism, in this context; see, Dainton (2010, chapter 10), for a detailed overview. In short, Foster’s arguments are as plausible as Berkeley’s, i.e., not very, despite their sophistication. Foster treats space as akin to an unobservable theoretical entity whose intrinsic character is forever unknowable, a conclusion that is part of his more general anti-realism about the entire physical world. This is different from geometric conventionalism, it should be noted, where only a finite and constrained class of possible geometries plus physical theories fits the evidence (see chapter 8). As noted above, some lived-space theorists seem to favor subjectivism or social constructivism, such that physical space and its properties are purely (or largely) relative to the individual or group—but this approach leads to a spatial form of solipsism, and the embarrassing scenario whereby the flat-earth believers live on a flat earth while the round-earth believers simultaneously live on a spherical earth. The fact that there are no substantive scientific disagreements on the earth’s shape, or other empirically accessible objects, undercuts these spatial subjectivisms, as well as raises doubts for Foster’s claim that the intrinsic nature of spatial geometric structure is unknowable—and, invoking the underdetermination of geometric structure across theory change (e.g., Newton’s Euclidean geometry replaced by Einstein’s non-Euclidean) does not help, since the history of these theoretical replacements reveals that the prior theory’s geometry has been upheld as limiting cases of the successor theory’s (e.g., Euclidean geometry is accurate except near the speed of light or near massive bodies like the sun).

  6. 6.

    DiSalle references Kant’s “empirical realism” about space in his interpretation of the definitional school’s metaphysical outlook, although it is unclear just what this entails as regards the standard dichotomy, or even scientific realism; see, DiSalle (2006, 67). Throughout the investigation, Stein will be listed as a member of the definitional approach, although it is unclear that he would accept this designation. But, since the conception that he advances, especially in the context of Newton (see chapter 2), seems quite close to DiSalle’s, the designation seems justified.

  7. 7.

    Impetus functions much like an impressed force for Buridan, and is the cause of local motion, although it is ontologically distinct from local motion (see, Maier 1982, 86–87). Impetus was a commonly accepted notion in the fourtheenth century, it should be noted.

  8. 8.

    Ockham’s nominalist conception of local motion and Buridan’s res pure successiva hypothesis can be seen, respectively, as variations on the concepts, forma fluens (that motion is the terminus or form acquired) and fluxus formae (that motion is an additional flux over and above the terminus or form acquired), put forth in previous centuries by Averroes and Albertus Magnus. In addition, Buridan’s idea was prompted by the concern over the rotation of the universe, where no new places (termini) are acquired, and thus a problem for Ockham’s nominalist account and, more generally, the forma fluens view (see, Murdoch and Sylla 1978, 215–219). Grant refers to Buridan’s res pure successiva account as establishing “the absolute nature of motion”, and as an accidental form possessed by the body (Grant 2010, 79).

  9. 9.

    In the discussion above, the problem of the motion of the outermost sphere of the universe has not been discussed, although it was one of the motivating factors behind the debates on the status of place: since the final sphere does not have an outer boundary, and hence is not in a place, many ideas were put forward to resolve this dilemma (such as the relationship of the parts of the final sphere to the inner parts, the latter providing a roundabout way of securing the place of the former). On the influence of late Scholastic ideas of place on Descartes, see also, Des Chene (1996), Ariew (1999, chapter 2). Ariew provides a nice summary of these conceptual developments: “In sum, while later Scholastics agreed in rejecting the independence of space from body, they disagreed about other important issues. Hidden within the debate between Thomists and Scotists on the question of the mobility/immobility of place and the place of the ultimate sphere were questions about the relativity of motion or reference of motion. Some thinkers supported a Thomist doctrine in which the motion of a body is referred to place, conceived as its relation to the universe as a whole, a universe which is necessarily immobile; others supported a Scotist doctrine in which the motion of an object is referred to its place, conceived as a purely relational property of bodies” (1999, 53). By the sixteenth century, various natural philosophers, such as J. C. Scaliger, resurrected the ancient atomist’s concept of a three-dimensional void space as a means of overcoming the inherent limitations involved with Aristotle’s conception of place; see, Grant (1981, chapters 7 and 8), and Leijenhorst and Lüthy (2002, 387).

  10. 10.

    More carefully, Descartes defines proper motion with respect to the “immediately contiguous” bodies, and does not mention the common surface between contained and containing bodies. However, as noted above, external place would seem to be implicated in this process. See, also, Zepeda (2014).

  11. 11.

    On Descartes’ conception, a “mode” of extension is a way that extension manifests itself, or as a property of extension (Pr I 53; for instance, shape is mentioned as a mode of extension). Presumably, claiming that motion is a mode of extension eliminates the possibility that motion is a feature of a body that is separate from extension, i.e., a “substance” in extension, the latter view seemingly implicit in Buridan’s concept.

  12. 12.

    Schmaltz (2008, 89) denies the relationist interpretation of Descartes theory of motion on these very grounds, i.e., that it is inconsistent with the details of his laws of motion. Others, such as Blackwell (1966, 227), have argued that the relational aspects of his theory of motion are not intended to be taken seriously, and are merely an attempt appease the Church’s potential condemnation of his Copernicanism (since Descartes’ puts the earth at rest in a vortex circling the sun, and so the earth does not move in the proper sense, as defined above).

  13. 13.

    The rejection of the idea that motion is a substance/property possessed by the moving body is also a feature of various Cartesian texts in the late seventeenth century, such as Rohault’s popular text (1969, 42–43). Likewise, various modern commentators have interpreted Descartes’ reciprocity of transfer hypothesis along these lines, e.g., Miller and Miller, in Descartes (1983, 51, n. 13).

  14. 14.

    A God-based conception of the Cartesian conservation law has also been suggested by Hübner (1983, 130), whereas Dugas (1958, 196) favors the material world at the initial moment of creation as the preferred frame (which, of course, only God can know). It should be added, furthermore, that Slowik (2002) does not actually reject a relationist interpretation of Descartes’ natural philosophy, since the main goal is to examine the prospects for a consistent relationist reconstruction. This chapter, in contrast, develops a case against relationism.

  15. 15.

    Given Ockham’s complex analysis of language, which employs “absolute” and “respective” in a more general sense, it is unclear how to interpret this passage as regards absolute and relative motion per se. However, the use of these terms was likely common by the seventeenth century, since one can find various natural philosophers in the first quarter of that century that refer to space/place as ens absolutum or ens relativum, such as Balthasar Meisner (see, Leijenhorst and Lüthy 2002, 392). From the perspective of our investigation, the main question concerns the specific historical source and inspiration behind Newton’s adoption of those terms and concepts, hence our treatment of this (immense) topic is fairly limited.

  16. 16.

    Huygens’ acceptance of atoms and an intercorpuscular void stand out in this regard, i.e., as particularly anti-Cartesian: see, Snelders (1980, 120), Westman (1980); and, for more on Huygens’ physics and the center-of-mass frame, see, Barbour (1989, 473–478), and Slowik (2002, chap. 8).

  17. 17.

    As an interesting admission of his lack of interest in theological matters, as well as a sign of the impending decline of the theological component of natural philosophy in the following century, Huygens adds in the margin: “Perhaps there is no need to involve God in this matter, after all” (H 27).

  18. 18.

    Throughout our investigation, “center-of-mass” will be used interchangeably with “center-of-gravity”, although the two are only identical if the gravitational field is uniform in the region that the bodies occupy.

  19. 19.

    Huygens also discovered the laws for the conservation of momentum (mv) and, roughly, kinetic energy (mv 2), the latter eventually embraced by Leibniz, of course. However, as a devotee of Descartes’ concept of speed over the concept of velocity (speed in a given direction), Huygens continued to favor the Cartesian conservation law for the quantity of motion (ms, where s is the scalar quantity, speed), via his revision of Descartes’ first collision rule and his use of the center-of-mass frame. Westfall concludes that “the concept [of velocity] did not please him greatly, however, and he continued to speak formally of quantity of motion in the Cartesian sense, a scalar quantity which is always positive in value” (Westfall 1971, 156).

  20. 20.

    As Elzinga explains, “Ignace Gaston Pardies (1636–1673) seems to have been the first (or at least one of the first) to have applied Huygens’ relativity principle [i.e., relational motion and the center-of-mass method] to the study of impact after Huygens himself—in a work, Discours du mouvement local (1670). Edne Mariotte (1620–1684) also made use of it in, Traité de la Percussion ou Choq des Corps (1673, 1674, 1676). Huygens was suspicious of Mariotte for borrowing his ideas without mentioning Huygens [see, H 51, above]. Another who soon used Huygens’ principle and method was C. F. M. Déchales, Cursus seu Mundus Mathematicus (1674)” (Elzinga 1972, 134).

  21. 21.

    Westfall (1983, 242–245) recounts Newton’s correspondence with Pardies on optics in 1672. Furthermore, Marius Stan, who provided the translation of Huygens’ codex 7A, comments that the term “absolute” (as regards place/space or motion) does not appear often in the fragments that comprise the codex. He adds that “[t]his suggests that [Huygens] was familiar with this notion (true motion as translation in world space) before 1687, and rejected it before the first edition of Newton’s Principia came to light”, and that Huygens “speaks of ‘they’ who explicate true motion as change of absolute place”, which “may be Borelli, Pardies, and Mariotte” (H 45). That is, Huygens had objected to the use of absolute space (or world space) prior to Newton’s more famous treatment of the concept.

References

  • Ariew, R. 1999. Descartes and the last Scholastics. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barbour, J. 1989. Absolute or relative motion? The discovery of dynamics, vol. 1. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barbour, J. 1999. The end of time. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barbour, J., and B. Bertotti. 1977. Gravity and inertia in a Machian framework. Nuovo Cimento 38B: 1–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Barbour, J., and B. Bertotti. 1982. Mach’s principle and the structure of dynamical theories. Proceedings of the Royal Society 382: 295–306.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Belot, G. 2000. Geometry and motion. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 51: 561–595.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Belot, G. 2011. Geometric possibility. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bernstein, H. 1984. Leibniz and Huygens on the ‘relativity’ of motion. Studia Leibnitiana 13: 85–101.

    Google Scholar 

  • Blackwell, R. 1966. Descartes’ laws of motion. Isis 57: 220–234.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Borelli, G. 1667. De Vi Percussionis. Bologna: Ex typographia Iacobi Montii.

    Google Scholar 

  • Casey, E. 1997. The fate of place. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Clagett, M. 1959. The science of mechanics in middle ages. Madison: University of Wisconsin Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dainton, B. 2010. Time and space, 2nd ed. Montreal: McGill-Queen’s University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Des Chene, D. 1996. Physiologia: Natural philosophy in late Aristotelian and Cartesian thought. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Descartes, R. 1983. Principles of Philosophy. Trans. V.R. Miller and R.P. Miller. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • DiSalle, R. 1994. On dynamics, indiscernibility, and spacetime ontology. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 45: 265–287.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • DiSalle, R. 2006. Understanding space-time. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dorato, M. 2000. Substantivalism, relationism, and structural spacetime realism. Foundations of Physics 30: 1605–1628.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dugas, R. 1958. Mechanics in the Seventeenth Century. Trans. F. Jaquot. Neuchatel: Griffon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Earman, J. 1989. World enough and space-time. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Earman, J., and J. Norton. 1987. What price space-time substantivalism?: The hole story. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 38: 515–525.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Elzinga, A. 1972. On a research program in early modern physics. New York: Humanities Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foster, J. 1982. The case for idealism. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Friedman, M. 1983. Foundations of space-time theories. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Garber, D. 1992. Descartes’ metaphysical physics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grant, E. 1981. Much Ado about nothing: Theories of space and vacuum from the Middle Ages to the acientific revolution. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Grant, E. 2010. The nature of natural philosophy in the late Middle Ages. Washington, DC: Catholic University of America Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hoefer, C. 1996. The metaphysics of space-time substantivalism, 5–27. XCIII: Journal of Philosophy.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hübner, K. 1983. Critique of Scientific Reason. Trans. P.R. Dixon and H.M. Dixon. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Huggett, N. 2006a. Can Spacetime Help Settle any Issues in Modern Philosophy?”, philsci-archive.pitt.edu/id/eprint/3085.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jammer, M. 1993 [1954]. Concepts of space, 3rd ed. New York: Dover Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, W.E. 1964 [1922]. Logic, vol. II. New York: Dover Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leijenhorst, C. 2002. The Mechanisation of Aristotelianism. Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leijenhorst, C., and C. Lüthy. 2002. The erosion of Aristotelianism: Confessional physics in early modern Germany and the Dutch Republic. In The dynamics of Aristotelian natural philosophy from antiquity to the seventeenth century, ed. C. Leijenhorst, C. Lüthy, and J. Thijssen, 349–374. Leiden: Brill.

    Google Scholar 

  • Maier, A. 1982. On the Threshold of Exact Science. Trans. S.D. Sargent. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Manders, K. 1982. On the spacetime ontology of physical theories. Philosophy of Science 49: 575–590.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Murdoch, J.E., and E.D. Sylla. 1978. The science of motion. In Science in the middle ages, ed. D.C. Lindberg. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ockham, W. 1967. Philosophical Writings. Trans and Ed. P. Boehner. London: Thomas Nelson.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pardies, I. 1670. A Discourse of Local Motion (Discours du mouvement local). Trans. A. M. London: Moses Pitt.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rohault, J. 1969 [1723]. A System of Natural Philosophy. Trans. J. Clarke and S. Clarke. New York: Johnson Reprint Corp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosen, G. 2010. Metaphysical dependence: Grounding and reduction. In Modality: metaphysics, logic, and epistemology, ed. B. Hale and A. Hoffman, 109–136. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rovelli, C. 1997. Halfway through the Woods: Contemporary research on space and time. In The cosmos of science, ed. J. Earman and J. Norton, 180–224. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rynasiewicz, R. 2000. On the distinction between absolute and relative motion. Philosophy of Science 67: 70–93.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schmaltz, T. 2008. Descartes on causation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shea, W. 1991. The magic of numbers and motion: The scientific career of René Descartes. Canton: Science History Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sklar, L. 1974. Space, time, and spacetime. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slowik, E. 2002. Cartesian spacetime. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Slowik, E. 2010. The fate of mathematical place: Objectivity and the theory of lived-space from Husserl to Casey. In Space, time, and spacetime, ed. V. Petkov, 291–312. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Snelders, H. 1980. Christiaan Huygens and the concepts of matter. In Studies on Christiaan Huygens, ed. H. Bos et al., 104–125. Swetz & Zeitlinger: Linse.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stein, H. 1967. Newtonian space-time. Texas Quarterly 10: 174–200.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stein, H. 1977a. Some philosophical prehistory of general relativity. In Foundations of space-time theories, Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science, vol. 8, ed. J. Earman, C. Glymour, and J. Stachel, 3–49. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stein, H. 1977b. On space-time and ontology: Extract from a letter to Adolf Grünbaum. In Foundations of space-time theories, Minnesota studies in the philosophy of science, vol. 8, ed. J. Earman, C. Glymour, and J. Stachel, 374–403. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Suárez, F. 1965 [1597]. Disputationes Metaphysicae, vol. 2. Hildesheim: Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tahko, T.E. and E.J. Lowe. 2015. Ontological dependence. In The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, ed. E. Zalta. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2015/entries/dependence-ontological/.

  • Toletus, F. 1589. Commentaria una cum quaestionibus in Octo Libros Aristotelis de Physica Auscultatione, 4th ed. Venice: Iuntas.

    Google Scholar 

  • Westfall, R. 1971. Force in Newton’s physics. New York: Elsevier.

    Google Scholar 

  • Westfall, R. 1983. Never at rest: A biography of Isaac Newton. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Westman, R.S. 1980. Huygens and the problem of Cartesianism. In Studies of Christiaan Huygens, ed. H. Bos et al. Linse: Swetz & Zeitlinger.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zepeda, J. 2014. The concept of space and the metaphysics of extended substance in Descartes. History of Philosophy Quarterly 31: 21–40.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Slowik, E. (2016). A (Contrarian’s) Reappraisal of the History and Current State of the Ontology Debate in the Philosophy of Space. In: The Deep Metaphysics of Space. European Studies in Philosophy of Science. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-44868-8_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics