Skip to main content

Understanding Reality

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Human Being, the World and God
  • 332 Accesses

Abstract

What can we say about reality as such, the reality of the world around us? How can we explain, understand our universe and everything in it? As argued in chapter two, human experiences are real but real on different levels. Some are merely real in a subjective way while others real in an intersubjective manner. Because humans are intertwined with the reality they live in, they cannot describe reality as it really is. They have to conceptualize reality in order to understand and describe it. It is here the philosophical question comes in, what do we mean by the concept of reality?

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    This is not to be confused with Thomas Nagel’s view of realism. He argues that we cannot grasp the world as it is due to limited knowledge as well as to what we are able to conceive. In his words: “The world extends beyond the reach of our minds” (Nagel 1986: 90).

  2. 2.

    There are several interpretations of the Quantum Mechanical Theory: the micro-macro interpretation along the Bohr line, better known as the Copenhagen Interpretation, the mind-body interpretation along the Wigner line also known as the Princeton interpretation, The Many Worlds interpretation of Everett III, the Many Minds interpretation by Albert & Loewer and later David Deutsch. Furthermore there is the interpretation by Penrose taking gravitation as the cause of the collapse, and there is the Pilote Wave interpretation along the de Broglie-Bohm line. Furthermore, there are the more recent interpretations, for example the modal interpretation and the interpretation based on decoherence.

  3. 3.

    The basic physical quantity used in quantum mechanics is the wave function, i.e. Ψ as described by the Schrödinger equation. The Schrödinger equation tells us that, if we know Ψ at time zero and we know the Hamiltonian, then we can calculate Ψ for all future times. The first postulate of quantum mechanics is that all information about a physical system is to be found in the wave function, i.e. Ψ of that system. If we manipulate the wave function Ψ as we measure and/or observe a particle, then we receive information about the location, energy, velocity of that particle. It might be interesting to note that Schrödinger gave the wave function Ψ an ontological meaning; he meant that the wave function Ψ exists independently of our knowledge about it. Also von Neumann had a realistic view on the wave function. Bohr and Heisenberg on the other hand had a non-realistic view on the wave function and hence avoided the measurement problem.

  4. 4.

    Deconstructivism derives from the philosophy of language of Jacques Derrida (1982). A word receives it meaning as a function of how it differs from another word. What Derrida means is that complete meaning is always differential and postponed in language; there is never a moment when meaning is complete and total (Glendinning 2004: 7). Richard Rorty (1931–2007) argued that an “‘accidental’ feature of a text can be seen as betraying, subverting, it’s purportedly ‘essential message’” (1995). Translated to deconstructivist subjectivity of experiences this means that the reports of the experiences have little to do with reality.

  5. 5.

    Some still seem to hold on to a Popperian view of science which stipulates that only falsifiability is a viable methodological path. While Popper’s arguments have long since been refuted, for instance by Putnam and others, they are tenacious in some quarters, because they have teamed up in an unhealthy alliance with Fisherian statistics that allow only for deductive types of hypothesis testing which in turn look similar to falsifiability. Rarely is there a critical distinction made between the theory of science type of claim Karl Popper (1902–1994) makes, and the statistical procedure adopted, let alone their relative merits critically scrutinized. Hence we still hold on to the seemingly old-fashioned view that science has to do with verification, although certainly not in its original, simplistic and naïve positivist framework. See further Popper, K., 2005.

  6. 6.

    See again chapter two on the human experiencer.

  7. 7.

    I changed ‘man’s’ into ‘human’.

  8. 8.

    The Collected Works of John Dewey, Jo Ann Boydston, ed., 37 volumes (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press, 1967–1991).

  9. 9.

    Nagel 1986.

  10. 10.

    Hook 1961.

  11. 11.

    Sellars 1927.

  12. 12.

    My italics.

  13. 13.

    What I refer to as minimalist ontological naturalism should not be confused with Griffin’s idea that naturalism can be understood in a minimal or maximal sense (Griffin 2000: 11–12. What I mean by minimalist naturalism is naturalism useful within a specific realm or scope of inquiry.

  14. 14.

    Where ‘v’ stands for ‘inclusive v’.

  15. 15.

    Drees calls his ontological naturalism supernaturalistic religious naturalism. Furthermore, Drees defends the view of a physically closed universe. My italics.

  16. 16.

    My italics.

References

  • Adams, William A. 2006. Transpersonal heterophenomenology. Journal of Consciousness Studies 13(4): 89–93.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bohr, Hans. 1967. My father. In Niels Bohr: His life and work as seen by his friends, ed. Rozental Stefan, 328. Amsterdam: Elsevier/North-Holland Pub. Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchland, Patricia. 2002. Brain-wise. Cambridge/London: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Cupitt, Don. 2002. Is nothing sacred? The Non-realist philosophy of religion: Selected essays. New York: Fordham University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, Daniel. 1993. Consciousness explained. London: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Derrida, Jacques. 1982. Margins of philosophy. Trans. A. Bass. Chicago: Chicago University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Drees, Willem B. 1998. Religion, science, and naturalism. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Drees, Willem B. 2003. Naturalism. In The encyclopedia of science and religion, ed. Huyssteen Wentzel Van, 593–597. New York: Macmillan Reference.

    Google Scholar 

  • Drees, Willem B. 2010. Religion and science in context. Abingdon: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Flanagan, Owen. 2006. Varieties of naturalism. In The Oxford handbook of religion and science, ed. P. Clayton and Z. Simpson, 430–452. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Glendinning, Simon. 2004. Language. In Understanding Derida, ed. J. Reynolds and J. Roffe, 5–13. New York: Continuum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goetz, Stewart, and Charles Taliaferro. 2008. Naturalism. Cambridge: Wim B. Eerdmans Publising Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, Alvin. 1999. Naturalism. In The Cambridge dictionary of philosophy, ed. R. Audi, 596–599. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Griffin, David Ray. 2000. Reenchantment without supernaturalism: A process philosophy of religion (Cornell studies in the philosophy of religion). New York: Cornell University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guttenplan, Samuel. 2001. A companion of the philosophy of mind. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hançil, Tomas, and M. Ziemer. 2000. Evolutionary epistemology as a new challenge in the dialogue between theology and science. CTNS Bulletin 20(3).

    Google Scholar 

  • Herrmann, Eberhard. 2008. On the distinction between the concept of god and conceptions of god. International Journal for Philosophy of Religion 64: 63–73.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hook, Sidney. 1961. The quest for being, and other studies in naturalism and humanism. Westport: Greenwood Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacobs, Jon. 2008. Naturalism. Internet encyclopedia of philosophy. http://www.iep.utm.edu/naturali/. Accessed 2 Feb 2016.

  • Kant, Immanuel. [1781] 2004. Kritik av det rena förnuftet. Stockholm: Thales.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, Thomas. 1986. Utsikten från ingenstans. Nora: Nya Doxa.

    Google Scholar 

  • Overbye, Dennis. 1991. Lonely hearts of the cosmos: The scientific quest for the secret of the universe. New York: HarperCollins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Oviedo, Lluis. 2006. Religious experience: First-, second-, and third-person accounts. Archivio Di Filosofia 13: 391–401.

    Google Scholar 

  • Papineau, David. 2007. Naturalism. Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/naturalism/. Accessed 2 Feb 2016.

  • Plantinga, Alvin. 1982. The nature of necessity. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. 1998. Reason, truth and history. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Quine, Willard Van Orman. 1960. Word and object. Cambridge: M.I.T. Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raichle, Marcus E. 2010. The brain’s dark energy. Scientific American 1: 28–33.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rorty, Richard. 1995. Deconstruction. In From fromalism to postructuralism, the Cambridge history of literal criticism, ed. Raman Selden, vol. 8, 166–196.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rottschaefer, William Andrew. 2001. Emerging naturalism: William Rottschaefer and Willem Drees in converstation: How to make naturalism safe for supernaturalism: An evalutation of Willem Drees’s supernaturalistic naturalism. Zygon 36(3): 407–453.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Runehov, Anne L.C. 2007. SACRED or NEURAL? The potential of neuroscience to explain religious experience. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht GmbH & Co. KG.

    Google Scholar 

  • Searle, John R. 2008. Philosophy in a New century: Selected essays. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sellars, Roy Wood. 1927. Why naturalism and not materialism. Philosophical Review 36(3): 216–225.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Spurway, Neil. 2009. Theology, evolution and the mind. Newcastle upon Tyne: Cambridge Scholar Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tart, Charles T. 2006. Current status of transpersonal psychology. Journal of Consciousness Studies 13(4): 83–87.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walach, Harald. 2007. Mind – Body – Spirituality. Mind & Matter 5(2): 215–240.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walach, Harald, and Anne L.C. Runehov. 2010. The epistemology status of transpersonal psychology – The data-base argument revisited. Journal of Consciousness Studies 17(1–2): 145–165.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ward, A. 2005. Defending ethical naturalism: The roles of cognitive science and pragmatism. Zygon 40(1): 201–220.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1992. Tractatus logico-philosophicus. Stockholm: Thales.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Runehov, A.L.C. (2016). Understanding Reality. In: The Human Being, the World and God. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-44392-8_4

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics