Skip to main content

A Two- and Threefold Self

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Human Being, the World and God
  • 319 Accesses

Abstract

Before beginning this chapter, one term has to be explained, namely, ‘being’. What is meant by being? Indeed, the English term being is confusing, which has led to the problem that it is difficult to know what exactly is meant by being, especially when it comes to scientific research. Clarifying a term is important when one’s research crosses the border of other disciplines or when one tries to make scientific finding understandable for non-scientists. Terms in need of clarification are, amongst others, experience, mind, consciousness, awareness, self, intelligence, affection and emotion, what is called the ego, the self and being.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    I mean after-Cartesian dualism because, Cartesian dualism is, according to me misunderstood. Furthermore it is not my aim to dig into dualism more than necessary for my purpose.

  2. 2.

    Gregersen 2008. http://www.metanexus.net accessed 27 May 2015.

  3. 3.

    To Alexander this specific complexity has the quality of consciousness.

  4. 4.

    Eccles and Popper 1981.

  5. 5.

    in Skirry 2016.

  6. 6.

    Bonaventura 1990.

  7. 7.

    Gabrielsson 1926.

  8. 8.

    To Alexander this specific complexity has the quality of consciousness. (Alexander 1920: 5).

  9. 9.

    http://mic.com/articles/91329/science-shows-how-piano-players-brains-are-actually-different-from-everybody-elses, accessed 27th May 2015.

  10. 10.

    I say ‘thus far’ because there is still more to tell about the self.

  11. 11.

    Also the right occipital region seems to some extent to have a role to play in self-experiences.

  12. 12.

    The function of the left hemisphere is associated with sequential analyses such as systematic, logical interpretation of information; interpretation and production of symbolic information language; mathematics, abstraction and reasoning and also with memory storage in a language format. The function of the right hemisphere then is associated with holistic functioning such as processing multi-sensory input simultaneously to provide a ‘holistic’ picture of one’s environment; visual spatial skills. Holistic functions such as dancing and gymnastics are coordinated by the right hemisphere. Memory is stored in auditory, visual and spatial modalities.

  13. 13.

    Hypermetabolism in the posterior cingulated gyrus was also associated with very-early Alzheimer’s disease, because this is the period when patients clearly start to show difficulties with memory. This hyperbolism was also exhibited by individuals who are at genetic risk from Alzheimer’s. Johnson et al. 2002: 1811. Stuss et al. 2001. Ochsner et al. 2004. Discussion of the results: pages: 1749–1750, 1752–1754, 1765.

  14. 14.

    This was regardless of the positive or negative input.

  15. 15.

    Sitaram 2013, http://www.bme.ufl.edu/labs/wp-content/blogs.dir/12/files/2013/10/NeuroimagingMeditation.pdf Accessed 1 February 2016.

  16. 16.

    For a complete analysis and evaluation of these studies, see Runehov (2007) Chap. 5 and 6.

  17. 17.

    Depending on one’s personal and spiritual outlook they are regarded as potentially stabilizing or destabilizing. The crucial point seems to be that those with regular spiritual practice assess experiences of ego loss much more positively.

References

  • Alexander, Samuel. 1920. Space, time and deity. London: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barbour, Ian. 1999. Neuroscience, artificial intelligence and human nature: Theological and philosophical reflections. In Neuroscience and the person: Scientific perspectives on divine action, ed. R.J. Russel, N. Murphy, T.C. Meyering, and M.A. Arbib, 215–248. Vaticcan City State: Vatican Observatory Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bonaventura. 1990. The journey of the mind to god. Trans. Philotheus Boehner, ed. Stephen F. Brown. Indianapolis/Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brooke, John Hedley. 2006. Science and the self: What difference did Darwin make? In The evolution of rationality, ed. F.L. Shults, 253–277. Cambridge: Eerdmans Publishing Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Castro-Cladas, Alexander, Karl Magnus Petersson, A. Reis, Sharon Stone-Elander, and Martin Ingvar. 1998. The illiterate brain learning to read and write during childhood influences the functional organization of the adult brain. Brain 121: 1053–1063.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Clayton, Philip. 2004. Mind & emergence, from quantum to consciousness. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • d’Aquili, Eugene G., and Andrew B. Newberg. 1999. The mystical mind: Probing the biology of religious experience. Minneapolis: Fortress Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Decety, Jean, and J.A. Sommerville. 2003. Shared representations between self and other: A social cognitive neuroscientific view. Trend in Cognitive Science 7: 527–533.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, Daniel. 1992. The self as a center of narrative gravity. In Self and consciousness, multiple perspectives, ed. F. Kessel, P. Cole, and D. Johnson. Hillsdale: Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dennett, Daniel. 1993. Consciousness explained. London: Penguin Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Diniz, Breno S., Meryl A. Butters, Steven M. Albert, Mary Amanda Dew, and Charles F. Reynolds. 2013. Late-life depression and risk of vascular dementia and Alzheimer’s disease: Systematic review and meta-analysis of community-based cohort studies. The British Journal of Psychiatry 202(5): 329–335.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Eccles, John C., and Karl R. Popper. 1981. The self and its brain. Berlin/Heidelberg/London/New York: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Farrer, Chloe, N. Franck, N. Gerogieff, C.D. Frith, J. Decety, and M. Jeannerod. 2003. Modulating the experience of agency: A positron emission tomography study. NeuroImage 18: 324–333.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, Todd E., and Julian Paul Keenan. 2005. Where in the brain is the self? Consiousness and Cognition 14: 661–678.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Flanagan, Owen. 1992. Consciousness reconsidered. Cambridge: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fossati, P., S.J. Hevenor, S.J. Graham, C. Grady, M.L. Keightley, F. Craik, and H. Mayberg. 2003. In search of the emotional self: An fMRI study using positive and negative emotional words. American Journal of Psychiatry 160(11): 1938–1945.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Freud, Sigmund. 1961. Civilization and its discontent. New York: WW Norton & Co., Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gabrielsson, Johannes. 1926. Augustinus. Stockholm: A. Bonniers Förlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gazzaniga, Michael S. 2008. The split brain revisited. Groundbreaking work that began more than a quarter of a century ago has led to ongoing insights about brain organization and consciousness. http://www.utdallas.edu/~otoole/CGS2301_S09/7_split_brain.pdf. Accessed 25 Jan 2016.

  • Gregersen, Niels Henrik. 2004. Three varieties of Panentheism. In In whom we live and move and have our being, ed. Philip Clayton and Arthur Peacocke, 19–35. Cambridge: Eerdmans Publishing Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gregersen, Niels Henrik. 2008. Levels of complexity. www.metanexus.net. Accessed 27 May 2015.

  • Guttenplan, Samuel. 2001. A companion of the philosophy of mind. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heidegger, Martin. 1993. Sein und Zeit. Tübingen: Max Niemeyer Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hopkins, D. 1997. Failing brain, faithful community. In God never forgets, ed. Donald K. McKim, 72–87. Louisville: John Knox Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, David. 1978. In A treatise of human nature, ed. L.A. Selby-Bigge. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Husserl, Edmund. 1984. Logische Untersuchungen. Zweiter Band: Untersuchungen zur Phänomenolgie und Theorie der Erkenntnis. Den Haag: Nijhoff.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Johnson, Sterling C.J., Leslie C. Baxter, Lana S. Wilder, James G. Pipe, Joseph E. Heiserman, and George P. Prigatano. 2002. Neural correlates of self-reflection. Brain 125: 1808–1814.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Keck, David. 1996. Forgetting whom we are: Alzheimer’s disease and the love of god. Nashville: Abingdon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klunk, William, E. 2003. New imaging agent detects amyloid plagues in Alzheimer disease. Neurology Today, 3(12):1, 15–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kohls, Niko, and Harald Walach. 2006. Exceptional experiences and spiritual practice: A new measurement approach. Spiritual and Health International 7: 125–150.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lockwood, Michael. 1989. The mind, the brain and the quantum. Cambridge: Basil Blackwell Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, Nancey. 1998. Supervenience and the nonreducibility of ethics to biology. In Evolutionary and molecular biology: Scientific perspectives on divine action, ed. Robert John Russell, R. William, S.J. Stoeger, and Francisco J. Ayala, 463–489. Pasadena: Vatican Observatory.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nelkin, Norton. 2001. Subjectivity. In A companion to the philosophy of mind, ed. Samuel Guttenplan. Oxford: Blackwell Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newberg, Andrew B., Abass Alavi, Michael Baime, Michael Pourdehnad, Jill Santanna, and Eugene G. d’Aquili. 2001. The measurement of reginal cerebral blood flow during the complex cognitive task of meditation: A preliminary SPECT study. Psychiatry Research Neuroimaging Section 106: 113–122.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ochsner, Kevin N., Kyle Knierim, David H. Ludlow, Josh Hanelin, Tara Ramachandran, Gary Glover, and Sean C. Mackey. 2004. Reflecting upon feelings: An fMRI study of neural systems supporting the attribution of emotion to self and other. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 16(20): 1746–1772.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raichle, Marcus E. 2010. The brain’s dark energy. Scientific American 1: 28–33.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ruby, Perrine, and Jean Decety. 2004. How would you feel versus how do you think she would feel. A neuroimaging study of perspective-taking with social emotions. Journal of Cognitive Neuroscience 16: 988–999.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Runehov, Anne L.C. 2007. SACRED or NEURAL? The potential of neuroscience to explain religious experience. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht GmbH & Co. KG.

    Google Scholar 

  • Seigel, Jerrold. 2005. The idea of the self: Thought and experience in Western Europe since the seventeenth century. Cambridge/New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Semendeferi, K., A. Lu, N. Schenker, and H. Damasio. 2002. Humans and great apes share a large frontal cortex. Nature Neuroscience 5(3): 272–276.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Semendeferi, Katarina, Kate Teffer, Dan P. Buxhoeveden, Min S. Park, Sebastian Bludau, Katrin Amunts, Katie Travis, and Josephy Buckwalter. 2011. Spatial organization of neurons in the frontal pole sets humans apart from great Apes. Cerebral Cortex 21:1485–1497.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sitaram, Ranganatha. 2013. Neuroimaging meditation. http://www.bme.ufl.edu/labs/wp-content/blogs.dir/12/files/2013/10/NeuroimagingMeditation.pdf. Accessed 1 Feb 2016.

  • Skirry, Justin. 2016. René Descartes, the mind-body distinction. Internet encyclopedia of philosophy and its authors. http://www.iep.utm.edu/descmind/. Accessed 26 Jan 2016.

  • Stuss, D.T., G.G. Jr. Gallup, and M.P. Alexander. 2001. The frontal lobes are necessary for ‘theory of mind’. Brain 124(2):279–286.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor Sloan, J. 2014. Science shows how piano players’ brains are actually different from everybody elses. http://mic.com/articles/91329/science-shows-how-piano-players-brains-are-actually-different-from-everybody-elses#.fPcL3XMDR. Accessed 1 Feb 2016.

  • Trigg, Roger. 2009. Are we ghost or machines? In Theology, evolution and the mind, ed. Neil Spurway, 104–118. Cambridge: Cambridge Scholar Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Walach, Harald. 2007. Mind – Body – Spirituality. Mind & Matter 5(2): 215–240.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wittgenstein, Ludwig. 1953. Philosophical investigations. Trans. G.E.M. Anscombe. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Runehov, A.L.C. (2016). A Two- and Threefold Self. In: The Human Being, the World and God. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-44392-8_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics