Skip to main content

A Model of Categorization and Compositionality (Sense Determination) in the Light of a Procedural Model of Language (Based on Selection and the Communicative Field)

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Pragmemes and Theories of Language Use

Part of the book series: Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology ((PEPRPHPS,volume 9))

  • 855 Accesses

Abstract

Traditional models of language are based on the Aristotelian model of a category, and assume that linguistic symbols are correlated with senses defined by sets of necessary features (properties and relations), which allow one to identify category members. A linguistic pattern (syntax), in turn, defines the order in which the senses related to individual symbols combine to convey the sense of the linguistic constructions they form. Determining the sense of the combination of linguistic items typically involves taking the cross-section of the features indicated by each category. As we all know, neither the models of language based on Aristotle’s model of a category, nor those based on modern successors of Aristotle’s category – a prototype model of a category, or a fuzzy set model of a category – let us reflect natural language categorization, or compositionality sufficiently well. Therefore, in this paper, we propose another, more adequate model of linguistic sense categorization and compositionality.

We propose that in addition to traditionally acknowledged encoding mechanism of linguistic categorization represented by an Aristotelian type of category models, speakers and listeners can use the sense correlated with a given linguistic symbol (or linguistic construction) to identify its referent also in a different, selective, manner. To let me explain what selective mode of language use is, first note that even before actually hearing the item to be interpreted in a given utterance, we form some expectations as to what that item may be. In this paper, we call a set of such expected, potential senses and referents, along with their respective probabilities of occurrence, a communicative field (CF.) Now, on hearing a linguistic symbol (or construct) to be interpreted whose encoded interpretation does not result in a relevant interpretation of the utterance, interlocutors use its encoded (i.e., traditionally defined) sense to select in the given communicative field the item whose sense matches the encoded sense of the item being interpreted most closely. On some occasions, a given linguistic item can be used both selectively to select some referent and encodingly to predicate about it.

Note, that in the selective mode of language use, although the item selected as the referent, or sense, for a given linguistic item is not calculable from the Aristotelian sense of that linguistic item (or items), yet, such a referent, sense, or the other way around, form, can be singled out through unambiguous procedures from the communicative field. Hence, I call this proposal a procedural model of language, or a field model of language – to stress the role of the communicative field in the selection process.

I would like to express my deep gratitude to Professor Helene Wlodarczyk and Professor Andre Wlodarczyk for inspiring me with their research, especially with the role of meta-information (informational structure of utterances) and a statistical analysis of data possible with SEMENA software, as well as for their interest in my research. In particular, I would like to thank them for inviting me to MIC 2012 workshop held at CELTA, Sorbonne, to present the procedural model of language. The discussion with the conference participants helped me develop further some aspects of the model and present the whole model more clearly and succinctly than before. I would also like to express my gratitude to Prof. Alessandro Capone, Jacob Mey and Charles Sides, who have been helping me to develop and popularize the model of language I am currently working on. Last, but not least, I would like to thank the anonymous reviewer of this paper, whose comments helped me significantly both to resolve some inconsistencies in the definition of the communicative field I had not noticed myself and to focus this paper on what matters most making my article much more comprehensible.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 149.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 199.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 219.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Since the concepts theme vs. rheme, correspond to either topic/comment or new/old (given), using this pair might be more convenient for me. Yet, since these terms are no longer common nowadays, I decided to refer directly to the terms NEW, GIVEN; Topic, Comment. Also for the sake of wide readership, I decided not to follow an even better fitting framework based on Center of Attention and Predication introduced by Helene and Andre Włodarczyk and presented, for instance, in André Włodarczyk and Hélène Włodarczyk (2008, 2013).

  2. 2.

    Mind you, that the examples of the accounts offered in this paper serve to show how the interpretation process could go, not how it necessarily went. From my perspective, models serve to describe only statistical trends and do not account for particular usage. At this stage, I only meant to show that assuming selection and communicative field may allow sensible interpretations, and thus, it makes sense to proceed with the model and look for statistical data which would support its validity the way it is done in quantitative linguistics and empirical sciences.

  3. 3.

    I use the term “an Aristotelian category” in a more general sense to refer to a category defined by a given set of features. At this point I do not want to commit myself to any specific proposal of establishing such a set. The relevant set could be defined in relation to a prototypical category member, statistically averaged category member, or yet something else.

References

  • Benes, M. (2011). K problému kompozicionality jazykového významu. Prague: Ústav pro jazyk český AV ČR.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bruza, P. D. (2010). Quantum memory. Australasian Science, 31(1), 34–35.

    Google Scholar 

  • Capone, A. (2005). Pragmemes (a study with reference to English and Italian). Journal of Pragmatics, 37, 1355–1371.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Capone, A. (2006). On Grice’s circle (a theory-internal problem in linguistic theories of the Gricean type). Journal of Pragmatics, 38, 645–669.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Capone, A. (2010). On the social practice of indirect reports (further advances in the theory of pragmemes). Journal of Pragmatics, 42(2), 377–391.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Carey, S., & Bartlett, E. (1978). Acquiring a single new word. Proceedings of the Stanford Child Language Conference. 15, pp. 17–29. (republished in Papers and Reports on Child Language Development 15, 17–29).

    Google Scholar 

  • Kecskes, I. (2013). Intercultural pragmatics. Oxford: OUP.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Lakoff, G. (1987). Women, fire, and dangerous things: What categories reveal about the mind. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Langacker, R. (1987). Foundations of cognitive grammar (Vol. 1). Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mey, J. L. (2001). Pragmatics. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Palmer, F. R. (1976). Semantics. Cambridge: CUP.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rosch, E. H. (1973). Natural categories. Cognitive Psychology, 4(3), 328–350.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schank, R. C., & Abelson, R. (1977). Scripts, plans, goals, and understanding. Hillsdale: Earlbaum Assoc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Skousen, R. (1989). Analogical modelling of language. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sperber, D., & Wilson, D. (1986). Relevance: Communication and cognition. Oxford: Blackwell Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wierzbicka, A. (2010). Bilingualism and cognition: The perspective from semantics. In V. Cook & B. Bassetti (Eds.), Language and bilingual cognition. New York: Psychology Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Włodarczyk, André. (2011). Distributed grammar. www.celta.paris-sorbonne.fr/anasem/intexASMIC.html.

  • Włodarczyk André, & Hélène Włodarczyk. (2013). Meta-informative centering in utterances between semantics and pragmatics [Studies in Language Companion Series, 143].

    Google Scholar 

  • Włodarczyk, H., & Wlodarczyk, A. (2006). Focus in the meta-informative centering theory. In A. Wlodarczyk & H. Wlodarczyk (Eds.), La Focalisation dans les langues. Paris: Coll. Sémantiques, L’Harmattan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Włodarczyk, H., & Włodarczyk, A. (2008). Agents, roles and other things we talk about: Associative semantics and meta-informative centering theory (Intercultural Pragmatics 5–3 Forum, pp. 345–365). Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zadeh, L. (1965). Fuzzy sets. Information and Control, 8, 338–353.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zadeh, L. (2002). From computing with numbers to computing with words – From manipulation of measurements to manipulation of perceptions. International Journal of Applied Mathematics and Computer Science, 12(3), 307–324.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zielinska, D. (1997). A note on the extended functional analysis. Journal of Pragmatics, 27, 841–843.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zielinska, D. (1999). The selective mode of language use; The way nature language adopted itself to describing the word around us. Zeszyty Naukowe UJ, 119, 173–176.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zielinska, D. (2007a). The selective mode of language use and the quantized communicative field. Journal of Pragmatics, 39(5), 813–830.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zielinska, D. (2007b). Proceduralny model języka. Językoznawstwo z pozycji teorii modeli nauk empirycznych. Kraków: WUJ.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zielinska, D. (2010). Prepositions and the explicature from the perspective of the selective mode of language use. In A. Capone (Ed.), Perspectives on language, use and pragmatics (pp. 181–210). Muenchen: Lincom Europa.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zielinska, D. (2013). The mechanism of the form-content correlation process in the paradigm of empirical sciences. In C. Alessandro, P. Franco Lo, & C. Marco (Eds.), Perspectives on pragmatics and philosophy. Milan: Springer Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zielińska, Dorota. (2007a). A Polish-English contrastive study of the order of premodifying adjectives: A procedural model account. Proceedings of the Corpus Linguistics Conference CL2007 UB UK Edited by Matthew Davies, Paul Rayson, Susan Hunston, Pernilla Danielsson article #5.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zielinska, Dorota. (2014). Procedurální model jazyka Lingvistika z pohledu teorie modelu empirickych ved (trans: Martin Benes). Olomouc Univerzita Palackého, Olomouc.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Dorota Zielińska .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Zielińska, D. (2016). A Model of Categorization and Compositionality (Sense Determination) in the Light of a Procedural Model of Language (Based on Selection and the Communicative Field). In: Allan, K., Capone, A., Kecskes, I. (eds) Pragmemes and Theories of Language Use. Perspectives in Pragmatics, Philosophy & Psychology, vol 9. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-43491-9_41

Download citation

  • DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-43491-9_41

  • Published:

  • Publisher Name: Springer, Cham

  • Print ISBN: 978-3-319-43490-2

  • Online ISBN: 978-3-319-43491-9

  • eBook Packages: Social SciencesSocial Sciences (R0)

Publish with us

Policies and ethics