Skip to main content

The Lack of an Obligation to Select the Best Child: Silencing the Principle of Procreative Beneficence

  • Chapter
  • First Online:

Part of the book series: International Library of Ethics, Law, and the New Medicine ((LIME,volume 69))

Abstract

This chapter aims to show that prospective parents are not bound in their reproductive decision making by a principle of procreative beneficence. That is, they have no obligation (as Julian Savulescu, the principle’s originator, famously thinks they have) to choose the possible child, from a range of possible children they might have, who is likely to lead the best life. I will summarise and clarify the content of previous papers of mine, in which I argue that since the sorts of considerations that underlie the principle of procreative beneficence do not constitute reasons when viewed from a perspective that it is fitting and appropriate for a prospective parent to take up, there can be no requirement for prospective parents to be moved by those considerations.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   79.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    When talking about prospective parents, I will throughout use the pronouns “she” and “her”. This is only for the sake of ease, and to avoid the repeated use of unwieldy constructions such as “he or she” and “his or her”.

  2. 2.

    For a (justified) complaint that there is something implausible about the claim that we ought to do what he have most reason to do, see Hotke (2014). In what follows, I tacitly adopt Ben Saunders’ “charitable” interpretation of Savulescu as holding that we morally ought to do what we have most moral reason to do. See Saunders (2014).

  3. 3.

    It seems to me, incidentally, that there is an unremarked flaw in Savulescu’s example, though not one that damages the point he wishes to make about the existence of non-person-affecting wrong. That is, there presumably is a particular set of individuals whose lives are made worse by the occurrence of the accident: namely, the individuals alive at the time that it happened, in so far as they were subject to much more worry and concern than they would have been had the unsafe reactor not been opened. I am not sure that that level of worry could realistically be compensated for by their having previously had greater opportunity to stay up late, or by the novelty of having sex later in the evening.

  4. 4.

    If it is difficult to see how these two propositions differ in content, compare the two claims “It is equally the case that Michael and Gertrude are tall”, and “It is the case that Michael and Gertrude are equally tall”. The former may be true while the latter is false.

  5. 5.

    The rejection of PPB does not entail that there are no situations in which a better-life embryo B ought to be selected over a worse-life embryo A. Suppose, for example, that A*’s life would be likely to be of such poor quality that it would not be worth living. In such a case, A ought not to be selected. But the reason for choosing B over A in such a situation would not be that B*’s life would be better than A*’s. Instead, it would simply be that B* would be the only one of the two possible future persons whose life would be worth living.

References

  • Bennett, R. 2009. The fallacy of the principle of procreative beneficence. Bioethics 23(5): 265–273.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dancy, J. 1992. Moral reasons. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Herissone-Kelly, P. 2006. Procreative beneficence and the prospective parent. Journal of Medical Ethics 32(3): 166–169.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Herissone-Kelly, P. 2009. Two varieties of “better-for” judgements. In Harming future persons: Ethics, genetics and the non-identity problem, ed. M. Roberts and D.T. Wasserman, 249–263. Heidelberg: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Herissone-Kelly, P. 2011. Reasons, rationalities and procreative beneficence: Need Häyry stand politely by while Savulescu and Herissone-Kelly disagree? Cambridge Quarterly of Healthcare Ethics 20(2): 258–267.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Herissone-Kelly, P. 2012. Wrongs, preferences, and the selection of children: A critique of Rebecca Bennett’s argument against the principle of procreative beneficence. Bioethics 26(8): 447–454.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hotke, A. 2014. The principle of procreative beneficence: Old arguments and a new challenge. Bioethics 28(5): 255–262.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. 1984. Reasons and persons. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parker, M. 2007. The best possible child. Journal of Medical Ethics 33(5): 279–283.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ross, W.D. 2002. The right and the good. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Saunders, B. 2014. Is procreative beneficence obligatory? Journal of Medical Ethics 41(2): 175–178.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Savulescu, J. 2001. Procreative beneficence: Why we should select the best children. Bioethics 15(5/6): 413–426.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Savulescu, J. 2014. The nature of the moral obligation to select the best children. In The future of bioethics: International dialogues, ed. A. Akabayashi, 170–182. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Savulescu, J., and G. Kahane. 2009. The moral obligation to create children with the best chance of the best life. Bioethics 23(5): 274–290.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Peter Herissone-Kelly .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Herissone-Kelly, P. (2017). The Lack of an Obligation to Select the Best Child: Silencing the Principle of Procreative Beneficence. In: Hens, K., Cutas, D., Horstkötter, D. (eds) Parental Responsibility in the Context of Neuroscience and Genetics. International Library of Ethics, Law, and the New Medicine, vol 69. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-42834-5_10

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics