Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Annals of Theoretical Psychology ((AOTP,volume 14))

Abstract

This chapter lays out ten interrelated arguments about the purposes of history for contemporary psychology. These reasons are put forward here both as an introduction to the present volume and as arguments in their own right. All are present, but scattered and often enough implicit rather than spelt out, in the existing literature. These arguments constitute reasons why history has, or might have, or should have significance for psychologists. It may be helpful for further discussion to have reasons such as fostering disciplinary identity, perspective, critique, advancing unifying theory, doing justice to the historical content of knowledge, and so on, expressed in a systematic (if not comprehensive) way. At the heart of the reasons are, first, philosophical questions about the nature of scientific knowledge, the proper subject matters of psychology, and the authority of current approaches as science, and, second, practical, organizational, and social policy questions about the resources committed to psychology or, more precisely, distributed among the different domains of psychological activity. Most of the reasons speak to the world of psychologists, but the author, a historian of science and not a psychologist, argues that the deeper issues at stake, to do with the nature of psychology as science, raise wider questions about being human and the purposes for which knowledge is a goal at all.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    I comment on the sheer difficulty (perhaps impossibility) of agreeing a description, let alone definition, of psychology. One deep reason (to which Graham Richards, in particular, draws attention—Richards, 1987, 2002, pp. 6–7) is that one word refers both to states people have and to the study of those states, with the implication that history of psychology should encompass both the history of states people have and knowledge of those states. (For further comment, see argument 1.8.) There are no precise general descriptive terms for the (staggeringly) varied occupations called psychology. The once common terms, “applied psychology” and “scientific psychology”, will not do, as they imply a separation in principle between scientific and applied domains, which few people now accept; besides, there are marked differences between scientific psychology as a natural science and scientific psychology as a cultural, interpretive, or hermeneutic science and so on.

  2. 2.

    I doubt my list is comprehensive, but it is intended to be focused and systematic and to include the leading types of argument. I draw upon earlier talks and papers, including Smith (2007, 2010), the latter paper followed by commentaries.

  3. 3.

    All the same, as I argue below, I think it is incontrovertible to say that such research and practices nevertheless tacitly accept a certain version of historical knowledge, though it is so taken for granted that is invisible: the dismissal of history is itself a historically constructed position.

  4. 4.

    A good example is the presentation of the important figurehead of culture in Georgia, the physiologist and researcher of the brain, an opponent of Pavlovian science in the Soviet period, I. S. Beritashvili: Tsagereli and Doty (2009).

  5. 5.

    Brought into teaching clearly in Pickren and Rutherford (2010).

  6. 6.

    It was these weaknesses that first led me to venture into this kind of commentary: Smith (1988).

  7. 7.

    Bruce Alexander and Curtis Shelton even explicitly substitute “psychology” for “moral philosophy” in order to write more clearly for students, thus devaluing history, which is not at all their stated purpose (Alexander & Shelton, 2014, p. 309).

  8. 8.

    I leave it to Toomela’s contribution to deal with the conception of progress in science and the sense in which this conception requires history. Toomela, unlike Sarton, detaches progress in science and humane progress, and his chapter is about progress in science.

  9. 9.

    I place “schools” in scare quotes because of the difference between loose reference to a theoretical orientation and historically and socially precise delineation of a research and teaching institution (whether of associated people or with a specific institutional location).

  10. 10.

    He has done the same for mental illness: Pietikäinen (2007).

  11. 11.

    I also quoted this decisive passage, in the context of a larger argument for history, in Smith (2007, p. 207).

  12. 12.

    For reassertion of critique, faced by “the neuro-turn” in history, as in psychology, see Cooter (2014).

  13. 13.

    “Interprefactions” is the authors’ term for “the transmutation of interpretations and constructions into positive facts” (Borch-Jacobsen & Shamdasani, 2012, p. 144).

  14. 14.

    The authors are persuaded by a statement at the end of Daniel Robinson’s Intellectual History of Psychology, “that psychology is the History of Ideas”: Alexander and Shelton (2014, p. 458, Note 8); Robinson (1995, p. 366). The core difficulty, I think, is that Alexander and Shelton treat psychology as given, a universal category, even though they do not say what they think it denotes. They therefore treat what psychologists now do, which is broad enough, along with what they think they should do, which is even broader as it extends to both “wisdom” and political participation, as appropriately labelled by one term. They use one term to cover anything in the past that they find “speaks” to the actual or ideal activities of modern psychologists. Their humanistic goals are ones many people share. But scholarly history of psychology will question the unanalysed status of the category, psychology, and in particular will want to know when, where, and why such a category, in terms that historical actors themselves would recognize, came into use. Robinson’s position, as stated in the phrase quoted, would seem to equate human self-understanding with psychology. That appears intellectual imperialism of a high order.

  15. 15.

    For another good example of what might be involved in writing history of psychology in light of this (though the paper is not written under the heading of history of psychology—why should it be?), see Toews (2004).

  16. 16.

    Valsiner provides the example of the forgotten past of German post-Hegelian psychology and dialectics. While the psychology of Benecke and others is certainly now little known, to render this a persuasive resource for contemporary psychologists will, I suggest, require unpacking the apparatus of dialectical concepts and demonstration of relevance to specific modern psychological problems or research programmes.

  17. 17.

    For the earlier history, see Jahoda (2007). Psychologie und Geschichte (1989–2002) aimed to connect studies in history of psychology and historical psychology, but this proved hard to sustain. For an exposition of historical psychology, see Staeuble (1991, 1993). For Francophone work, especially of Ignace Meyerson, see Pizarroso (2013).

  18. 18.

    For the argument that cultural or historical psychology, through research on the psychological character of people, can play a mediating role between psychologists and historians of psychology, see Pettit and Davidson (2014).

  19. 19.

    The reasonableness of “folk” psychological understanding is ably defended in Kusch (1997, 1999, Part II).

  20. 20.

    I place a lot of emphasis on narrative as a source of meaning (MacIntyre, 1977; Smith, 2007). There is no agreed view about this, but this is not the place to go into the philosophical issues.

  21. 21.

    “Genealogy” is Nietzsche’s, and subsequently Foucault’s, term, taken from the study of family relations; see Nehamas (1985, pp. 100–105).

  22. 22.

    In more recent work, bringing a social science approach to social change linked with the neurosciences, Rose, though hardly interested in history, still finds it necessary to sketch in a lot of historical background (Rose & Abi-Rached, 2013). I hope my arguments explain why. It is this being “drawn into history”, in spite of an author’s stated purposes, that is of interest now. (A parallel might be made to the way even Rose and many scientists, in spite of antipathy, are “drawn into” philosophy.)

  23. 23.

    As argued most famously in British culture by John Henry Newman in the 1850s (Newman 1996, Discourse V).

References

  • Alexander, B. K., & Shelton, C. P. (2014). A history of psychology in Western civilization. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Arbib, M. A., & Hesse, M. B. (1986). The construction of reality. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Backhouse, R. G., & Fontaine, P. (Eds.). (2014). A historiography of the modern social sciences. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Borch-Jacobsen, M., & Shamdasani, S. (2012). The Freud files: An inquiry into the history of psychoanalysis. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Capshew, J. H. (2014). History of psychology since 1945: A North American review. In R. G. Backhouse & P. Fontaine (Eds.), A historiography of the modern social sciences (pp. 144–182). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Cooter, R. (2014). Natural veils and the will to historical critique: Why historians of science need to take the neuro-brain seriously. Isis, 105(1), 145–154.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Danziger, K. (1990). Constructing the subject: Historical origins of psychological research. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Danziger, K. (1994). Does the history of psychology have a future? Theory and Psychology, 4, 467–484.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Danziger, K. (1999). Natural kinds, human kinds, and historicity. In W. Maiers et al. (Eds.), Challenges to theoretical psychology. Selected/edited proceedings of the Seventh Biennial Conference of the International Society for Theoretical Psychology Berlin, 27 April–May 1997 (pp. 78–83).

    Google Scholar 

  • Danziger, K. (2003). Where history, theory, and philosophy meet: The biography of psychological objects. In D. B. Hill & M. J. Kral (Eds.), About psychology: Essays at the crossroads of history, theory, and philosophy (pp. 19–33). North York, Ontario: Captus University Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Danziger, K. (2008). Marking the mind: A history of memory. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dixon, T. (2003). From passions to emotions: The creation of a secular psychological category. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fleck, L. (1979). Genesis and development of a scientific fact In T. J. Trenn & R. K. Merton (Eds.), (trans: Bradley, F. & Trenn, T. J.) Chicago: University of Chicago Press. (Original work published 1935).

    Google Scholar 

  • Furumoto, L. (1989). The new history of psychology. Retrieved March, 2016, from http://www.chronicstrangers.com/history%20documents/Furumoto%20New%20History%20of%20Psychology%201989.pdf

  • Gergen, K. J. (1973). Social psychology as history. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 26, 309–320.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gergen, K. J., & Gergen, M. M. (Eds.). (1984). Historical social psychology. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goodey, C. F. (2011). A history of intelligence and “intellectual disability”: The shaping of psychology in early modern Europe. Farnham, Surrey: Ashgate.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gross, D. M. (2006). The secret history of emotion: From Aristotle’s “Rhetoric” to modern brain science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hacking, I. (1995). The looping effects of human kinds. In D. Sperber et al. (Eds.), Causal cognition: A multidisciplinary debate (pp. 351–394). Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harré, R., & Stearns, P. (Eds.). (1995). Discursive psychology in practice. London: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hayward, R. (2014). The transformation of the psyche in British primary care, 1870–1970. London: Bloomsbury.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hearnshaw, L. S. (1987). The shaping of modern psychology. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heller-Roazen, D. (2007). The inner touch: Archaeology of a sensation. New York: Zone Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jahoda, G. (2007). A history of social psychology: From the eighteenth-century Enlightenment to the Second World War. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klempe, S. H. (2014a). Kierkegaard and the rise of modern psychology. New Brunswik, NJ: Transaction.

    Google Scholar 

  • Klempe, S. H. (2014b). The explanatory power of agency. In C. W. Gruber et al. (Eds.), Constraints of agency: Exploration of theory in everyday life (Annals of theoretical psychology, Vol. 12, pp. 267–274). Cham, Switzerland: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kusch, M. (1997). The sociophilosophy of folk psychology. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 28(1), 1–25.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kusch, M. (1999). Psychological Knowledge: A Social History and Philosophy. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • MacIntyre, A. (1977). Epistemological crises, dramatic narrative and the philosophy of science. Monist, 60, 453–472.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merleau-Ponty, M. (2002). Phenomenology of perception (C. Smith, Trans., reprint). London: Routledge (Original work published 1945).

    Google Scholar 

  • Morawski, J. G. (2005). Reflexivity and the psychologist. History of the Human Sciences, 18(4), 77–105.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nehamas, A. (1985). Nietzsche: Life as Literature. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Newman, J. H. (1996). The Idea of a University. New Haven: Yale University Press. (Original lectures, 1852)

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, F. (1966). Beyond good and evil: Prelude to a philosophy of the future (W. Kaufmann, Trans.). New York: Vintage Books. (Original work published 1886)

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, F. (1969). On the genealogy of morals (W. Kaufmann & R. J. Hollingdale, Trans.). New York: Vintage Books. (Original work published 1887)

    Google Scholar 

  • Parkes, G. (1994). Composing the soul: Reaches of Nietzsche’s psychology. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pettit, M., & Davidson, I. (2014). Can the history of psychology have an impact? Theory and Psychology, 24(5), 709–716.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pickren, W., & Rutherford, A. (2010). A history of modern psychology in context. Holden, NJ: John Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pietikäinen, P. (2007). Neurosis and modernity: The age of nervousness in Sweden. Leiden: Brill.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Pizarroso, N. (2013). Mind’s historicity: Its hidden history. History of Psychology, 16(1), 72–90.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Rée, J. (1991). The varieties of historicism. New Literary History, 22, 961–983.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Richards, G. (1987). Of what is the history of psychology a history? British Journal for the History of Science, 20, 201–211.

    Article  PubMed  Google Scholar 

  • Richards, G. (2002). Putting psychology in its place: A critical historical overview (2nd ed.). Brighton, UK: Psychology Press, Routledge. (Original work published 1996)

    Google Scholar 

  • Robinson, D. N. (1995). An intellectual history of psychology (3rd ed.). London: Arnold. (Original work published 1976)

    Google Scholar 

  • Samelson, F. (1980). E. G. Boring and his history of experimental psychology. American Psychologist, 35, 467–470.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Secord, J. A. (2000). Victorian sensation: The extraordinary publication, reception, and secret authorship of Vestiges of the Natural History of Creation. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shuttleworth, S. (2010). The mind of the child: Child development in literature, science, and medicine, 1840–1900. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Small, H. (2013). The value of the humanities. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, R. (1988). Does the history of psychology have a subject? History of the Human Sciences, 1, 147–177.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, R. (1997). The Fontana history of the human sciences. London: Fontana. Retrieved from www.rogersmith.ru

  • Smith, R. (2007). Being human: Historical knowledge and the creation of human nature. Manchester, UK: Manchester University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, R. (2010). Why history matters. History and Philosophy of Psychology, 12, 26–38.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, R. (2013). Between mind and nature: A history of psychology. London: Reaktion Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Staeuble, I. (1991). “Psychological man” and human subjectivity in historical perspective. History of the Human Sciences, 4, 417–432.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Staeuble, I. (1993). History and the psychological imagination. In H. V. Rappard et al. (Eds.), Annals of theoretical psychology (Vol. 8, pp. 85–117). New York: Plenum Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Starobinski, J. (2003). Action and reaction: The life and adventures of a couple (S. Hawkes, Trans.). New York: Zone Books. (Original work published 1999)

    Google Scholar 

  • Steedman, C. (1987). Landscape for a good woman: A story of two lives. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Taylor, C. (2007). A secular age. Cambridge, MA: Belknap Press, Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thomson, M. (2006). Psychological subjects: Identity, culture, and health in twentieth-century Britain. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Tileagǎ, C., & Byford, J. (Eds.). (2014). Psychology and history: Interdisciplinary explorations. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Todes, D. P. (2014). Ivan Pavlov: A Russian life in science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toews, J. E. (2004). Refashioning the masculine subject in early modernism: Narratives of self-dissolution and self-construction in psychoanalysis and literature, 1900–1914. In M. S. Micale (Ed.), The mind of modernism: Medicine, psychology, and the cultural arts in Europe and America, 1880–1940 (pp. 298–335). Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tsagereli, M. G., & Doty, R. W. (2009). Ivan S. Beritashvili (1884–1974): From spinal cord reflexes to image-driven behavior. Neuroscience, 163, 848–856.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Valsiner, J. (2012). A guided science: History of psychology in the mirror of its making. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction.

    Google Scholar 

  • Valsiner, J. (2015). Historical leads for theory construction in psychology. In C. W. Gruber et al. (Eds.), Constraints of agency: Exploration of theory in everyday life (Annals of theoretical psychology, Vol. 12, pp. 45–48). Cham, Switzerland: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Vickers, N. (2011). Coleridge on “psychology” and “aesthetics.” In C. Barton (Ed.), Special issue, Psychology and aesthetics in the nineteenth century, 19: Interdisciplinary Studies in the Long Nineteenth Century, on line journal, no. 12. Retrieved September, 2015, from http://dx.doi.org/10.16995/ntn.609

  • Vidal, F. (2011). The sciences of the soul: The early modern origins of psychology (S. Brown, Trans.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press. (Original work published 2006)

    Google Scholar 

  • Young, R. M. (1966). Scholarship and the history of the behavioural sciences. History of Science, 5, 1–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Young, R. M. (1989). Persons, organisms … and primary qualities. In J. R. Moore (Ed.), History, humanity and evolution: Essays for John C. Greene (pp. 375–401). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Young, R. M. (1993). Darwin’s metaphor and the philosophy of science’ [written 1986]. Science as Culture, 3, 375–403. Retrieved from http://www.humannature.com/rmyoung/papers/paper131h.html

    Google Scholar 

  • Young, R. M. (2000). Science and the humanities in the understanding of human nature. Inaugural Lecture, University of Sheffield. Retrieved from http://www.humannature.com/rmyoung/papers/paper131h.html

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Roger Smith .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Smith, R. (2016). History of Psychology: What for?. In: Klempe, S., Smith, R. (eds) Centrality of History for Theory Construction in Psychology . Annals of Theoretical Psychology, vol 14. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-42760-7_1

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics