Advertisement

Eudaimonia and ‘Species Being’: A Marxist Perspective

  • Hartley DeanEmail author
Chapter
Part of the International Handbooks of Quality-of-Life book series (IHQL)

Abstract

This chapter connects the concept of eudaimonia with Karl Marx’s concept of ‘species being’. It contends that whereas, for Aristotle, eudaimonia represented the natural purpose of a privileged minority of humanity; for Marx, it represented the historical and developmental purpose of an entire species, radically characterised by its specific forms of consciousness, work and sociality. The chapter additionally considers how in the light of subsequent historical events, Hannah Arendt saw eudaimonia in terms of what it means for a human being to live well in common with others. Seizing on the idea that in the contemporary era social policy and social development are, or ought to be, concerned not only with living well, but living better, the chapter seeks to build upon Marx’s particular concept of species being as the basis for a life-first ethic: an ethic that seeks consensually to define and prioritise human fulfilment and the essential meaning of social welfare and human well-being.

Keywords

Human fulfilment Well-being Eudaimonia Marx Species being Life-first ethic Welfare Social policy 

References

  1. Althusser, L. (1971). Lenin and philosophy and other essays (B. Brewster, Trans.). London: New Left Books.Google Scholar
  2. Arendt, H. (1951). The burden of our time. London: Secker & Warburg.Google Scholar
  3. Arendt, H. (1968). Life of mind: Vol. 2 willing. London: Secker & Warburg.Google Scholar
  4. Arendt, H. (1978). Life of mind: Vol. 1 thinking. London: Secker & Warburg.Google Scholar
  5. Aristotle. (c. 350 BCE). Eudemian ethics – Books I. II and VIII (1982 edn. M. Woods, Tran.). Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
  6. Beck, W., Van der Maesen, L., & Walker, A. (Eds.). (1997). The social quality of Europe. Bristol, UK: The Policy Press.Google Scholar
  7. Benton, T. (1988). Humanism = specieism: Marx on humans and animals. Radical Philosophy, 50, 4–18.Google Scholar
  8. Bourdieu, P. (1999). The weight of the world: Social suffering in contemporary society. Cambridge, UK: Polity.Google Scholar
  9. Chan, J. (1999). A Confucian perspective on human rights for contemporary China. In J. Bauer & D. Bell (Eds.), The east Asian challenge for human rights. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  10. Chitty, A. (2009). Species-being and capital. In A. Chitty & M. McIvor (Eds.), Karl Marx and contemporary philosophy. Basingstoke, UK: Palgrave Macmillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Davy, U. (2013). Social citizenship going international: Changes in the reading of UN-sponsored economic and social rights. International Journal of Social Welfare, 22(Supplement 1), S15–S31.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. De Sousa Santos, B. (2006). The rise of the global left: The world social forum and beyond. London: Zed Books.Google Scholar
  13. Deacon, B. (2007). Global social policy and governance. London: Sage.Google Scholar
  14. Dean, H. (2000). Towards an embodied account of welfare. In K. Ellis & H. Dean (Eds.), Social policy and the body: Transitions in corporeal discourse. Basingstoke, UK: Macmillan.Google Scholar
  15. Dean, H. (2012). Social policy (2nd ed.). Cambridge, UK: Polity.Google Scholar
  16. Dean, H. (2014). Life first welfare, the need/right to work and the scope for a ‘eudemonic ethic’ of social security. In M. Keune & A. Serrano (Eds.), Deconstructing flexicurity and developing alternative approaches: Towards new concepts and approaches for employment and social policy. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  17. Dean, H. (2015). Social rights and human welfare. Abingdon, UK: Routledge.Google Scholar
  18. Dean, H., & Khan, Z. (1997). Muslim perspectives on welfare. Journal of Social Policy, 26(2).Google Scholar
  19. Depew, D. (1992). The polis transfigured: Aristotle’s politics and Marx’s critique of Hegel’s philosophy of right. In G. McCarthy (Ed.), Marx and Aristotle: Nineteenth century German social theory and classical antiquity. Annapolis, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
  20. Dolan, P., & Metcalfe, P. (2012). Measuring subjective wellbeing: Recommendations for use by national governments. Journal of Social Policy, 41(2), 409–427.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Esping-Andersen, G. (1990). The three worlds of welfare capitalism. Cambridge, UK: Polity Press.Google Scholar
  22. Farnsworth, K., & Irving, Z. (Eds.). (2015). Social policy in times of austerity. Bristol, UK: The Policy Press.Google Scholar
  23. Ferguson, C. (1999). Global social policy: Human rights and social justice. London: Department for International Development.Google Scholar
  24. Foster, J. (1999). Marx’s theory of metabolic rift: Classical foundations for environmental sociology. American Journal of Sociology, 105(2), 366.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  25. Fraser, N. (1989). Unruly practices: Power, discourse and gender in contemporary social theory. Minneapolis, MN: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
  26. Friere, P. (1972). Pedagogy of the oppressed. Harmondsworth, UK: Penguin.Google Scholar
  27. Fromm, E. (1961). Marx’s concept of man. New York: Frederick Unger Publishing.Google Scholar
  28. Fukuyama, F. (1992). The end of history and the last man. New York: Basic Books.Google Scholar
  29. Gilbert, A. (1992). Marx’s moral realism: Eudaimonism and moral progress. In G. McCarthy (Ed.), Marx and Aristotle: Nineteenth century German social theory and classical antiquity. Annapolis, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
  30. Harari, Y. (2011). Sapiens: A brief history of humankind. London: Vintage.Google Scholar
  31. Hegel, G. (1805–1806). Jena lectures on the philosophy of spirit. In L. Rauch (Ed.), Hegel and the human spirit (1983). Dettroit, MI: Wayne State University Press.Google Scholar
  32. Hegel, G. (1821). In A. Wood (Ed.), Elements of the philosophy of rights (1991st ed.). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  33. Heller, A. (1974). The theory of need in Marx. London: Alison & Busby.Google Scholar
  34. Honneth, A. (1995). The struggle for recognition: The moral grammar of social conflicts. Cambridge, UK: Polity.Google Scholar
  35. International Labour Organisation (ILO). (1999). Report of ILO Director-General: Decent work, international labour conference, 87th session. Geneva, Switzerland: ILO.Google Scholar
  36. Jordan, B. (2008). Welfare and well-being: Social value in public policy. Bristol, UK: The Policy Press.Google Scholar
  37. Kabeer, N. (2004). Globalization, labor standards, and women’s rights: Dilemmas of collective (in)action in an interdependent world. Feminist Economics, 10(1), 3–35.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  38. Layard, R. (2005). Happiness: Lessons from a new science. New York: Penguin.Google Scholar
  39. Lockwood, D. (1996). Civic integration and class formation. British Journal of Sociology, 47(3), 531–550.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. M’Baye, K. (1972). Le Droit au Développement comme un droit de l’Homme. Revue des Droits de l’Homme, 5, 503–505.Google Scholar
  41. MacIntyre, A. (2007). After virtue (3rd ed.). Notre Dame, IN: Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
  42. Margolis, J. (1992). Praxis and meaning: Marx’s species being and Aristotle’s political animal. In G. McCarthy (Ed.), Marx and Aristotle: Nineteenth century German social theory and classical antiquity. Annapolis, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
  43. Márkus, G. (2014). Marxism & anthropology: The concept of ‘human essence’ in the philosophy of Marx (special, ed.). Sydney, Australia: Modem-Verlag.Google Scholar
  44. Marshall, T. H. (1950). Citizenship and social class. In T. Marshall & T. Bottomore (Eds.), Citizenship and social class (1992nd ed.). London: Pluto.Google Scholar
  45. Marx, K. (1844). Economic and philosophical manuscripts. In L. Colletti (Ed.), Early writings (1975th ed.). Harmondsworth, UK: Penguin.Google Scholar
  46. Marx, K. (1845). Theses from Fuerbach (extract from). In T. Bottomore & M. Rubel (Eds.), Karl Marx: Selected writings in sociology and social philosophy. Harmondsworth, UK: Penguin.Google Scholar
  47. Marx, K. (1857). Grundrisse (1973rd ed.). London: Penguin.Google Scholar
  48. Marx, K. (1887). Capital (1970th ed., Vol. I). London: Lawrence & Wishart.Google Scholar
  49. McCarthy, G. (Ed.). (1992). Marx and Aristotle: Nineteenth century German social theory and classical antiquity. Annapolis, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
  50. Miller, R. (1992). Marx and Aristotle: A kind of consequentialism. In G. McCarthy (Ed.), Marx and Aristotle: Nineteenth century German social theory and classical antiquity. Annapolis, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
  51. Nussbaum, M. (2000). Women and human development: The capabilities approach. Cambridge, MA: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  52. Parekh, S. (2008). Hannah Arendt and the challenge of modernity. Abingdon, UK: Routledge.Google Scholar
  53. Ramose, M. (2003). Globalisation and ubuntu. In P. Coetzee & A. Roux (Eds.), The African philosophy reader. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  54. Rorty, R. (1982). Consequences of pragmatism. Minnesota, MD: University of Minnesota.Google Scholar
  55. Russell, B. (1961). History of western philosophy (2nd ed.). London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  56. Sahlins, M. (1974). Stone age economics. Chicago: Aldine.Google Scholar
  57. Searle, J. (1997). The mystery of consciousness. London: Granta.Google Scholar
  58. Sen, A. (1982). Equality of what? In A. Sen (Ed.), Choice, welfare and measurement. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  59. Sen, A. (1999). Development as freedom. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  60. Sennett, R. (1998). The corrosion of character: The personal consequences of work in the new capitalism. New York: Norton.Google Scholar
  61. Sevenhuijsen, S. (1998). Citizenship and the ethics of care. London: Routledge.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  62. Smith, S. (1992). The origins of the dialectic: Hegel’s appropriation of the ancient skeptics. In G. McCarthy (Ed.), Marx and Aristotle: Nineteenth century German social theory and classical antiquity. Annapolis, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
  63. Smyth, B. (2012). Review of Zurn, F. and Schmidt Am Busch, H-C (Eds.) The philosophy of recognition. Marx & Philosophy Review of Books. Retrieved December 2, 2015, from, http://marxandphilosophy.org.uk/reviewofbooks/reviews/2012/632
  64. Soper, K. (1981). On human needs. Brighton, UK: Harvester.Google Scholar
  65. Standing, G. (2011). The Precariat: The new dangerous class. London: Bloomsbury.Google Scholar
  66. Stenner, P., & Taylor, D. (2008). Psychosocial welfare: Reflections on an emerging field. Critical Social Policy, 28(4), 415–437.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  67. Stiglitz, J., Sen, A., & Fitoussi, J.-P. (2009). Report by the commission on the measurement of economic performance and social progress. See www.stiglitz-sen-firoussi.fr
  68. Titmuss, R. (1970). The gift relationship. London: Allen and Unwin.Google Scholar
  69. Tronto, J. (1994). Moral boundaries: A political argument for an ethic of care. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
  70. Turner, B. (2006). Vulnerability and human rights. Harrisburg, PA: Pennsylvania State University.Google Scholar
  71. Twine, F. (1994). Citizenship and social rights: The interdependence of self and society. London: Sage.Google Scholar
  72. United Nations General Assembly. (2000). United nations millennium declaration (resolution 2 session 55). New York: UN.Google Scholar
  73. van der Maesen, L., & Walker, A. (2014). The development of social quality between 1994 and 2014 (Working Paper Series nr. 13). Amsterdam: IASQ. www.socialquality.org
  74. Vygotsky, L. (1978). Mind and society: The development of higher mental processes. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  75. Weisman, T. (2014). Hannah Arendt and Karl Marx. Annapolis, MD: Lexington Books.Google Scholar
  76. Williamson, J. (1990). What Washington means by policy reform. In J. Williamson (Ed.), Latin American adjustment: How much has happened? Washington, DC: Institute for International Economics.Google Scholar
  77. Woodiwiss, A. (2005). Human rights. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  78. World Bank. (2001). World development report 2000/2001. Retrieved from Oxford.Google Scholar
  79. Yarbrough, J., & Stern, P. (1981). Vita activa and vita contemplativa: Reflections on Hannah Arendt’s political thought in life of mind. The Review of Politics, 43(3), 323–354.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2016

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Department of Social PolicyLondon School of EconomicsLondonUK

Personalised recommendations