Advertisement

Ethics and Eudaimonic Well-Being

  • Johannes HirataEmail author
Chapter
Part of the International Handbooks of Quality-of-Life book series (IHQL)

Abstract

Happiness and well-being are concepts with an evaluative dimension, so happiness research must come to terms with this evaluative content and cannot possibly remain value-free. The recent interest in the concept of eudaimonic well-being can be interpreted as an explicit acknowledgement of the ethical dimension of well-being and the need to preserve its normativity, rather than trying to sideline it. An important corollary of acknowledging the ethical dimension of well-being, however, is an acknowledgement of the person’s freedom of will and the indeterminacy of the right arbitration between competing ends. It is also argued that the ethical aspects of eudaimonic well-being include the two specific conditions (1) that the person feels no (strong) sense of guilt for enjoying whatever benefits she enjoys and (2) that, in case she suffers from (serious) deprivation, she must not be ignorant of any underlying injustices. Eudaimonic well-being is an essential aspect of the good life, but it is not unconditionally good in a comprehensive sense.

Keywords

Well-being Ethics Eudaimonia 

Notes

Acknowledgements

I am grateful for very helpful reviews of an earlier manuscript by Paul McNamara and by Lorraine Besser-Jones.

References

  1. Apel, K.-O. (1973). Das Apriori der Kommunikationsgemeinschaft und die Grundlagen der Ethik: Zum Problem einer rationalen Begründung der Ethik im Zeitalter der Wissenschaft. In K.-O. Apel (Ed.), Transformation der Philosophie, Vol. 2: Das Apriori der Kommunikationsgemeinschaft (engl.: Towards a Transformation of Philosophy, London: Routledge, 1980) (pp. 358–435). Frankfurt a. M, Germany: Suhrkamp.Google Scholar
  2. Aristotle. (1934). Nicomachean ethics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  3. Bayertz, K. (2013). Happiness by maximization? In H. Brockmann & J. Delhey (Eds.), Human happiness and the pursuit of maximization (pp. 41–54). Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  4. Davidson, R. J. (1992). Anterior cerebral asymmetry and the nature of emotion. Brain and Cognition, 20(1), 125–151.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  5. Diener, E. (1984). Subjective well-being. Psychological Bulletin, 95(3), 542–575.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Diener, E., Sandvik, E., Pavot, W., & Gallagher, D. (1991). Response artifacts in the measurement of subjective well-being. Social Indicators Research, 24, 35–56.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Frankfurt, H. G. (1999). Necessity, volition, and love. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  8. Hardie, W. F. R. (1965). The final good in Aristotle’s ethics. Philosophy, 40(154), 277–295.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Haybron, D. M. (2008). The pursuit of unhappiness: The elusive psychology of well-being. Oxford, NY: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  10. Hirata, J. (2011). Happiness, ethics, and economics. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
  11. Hossenfelder, M. (1998). Die Rolle des Glücksbegriffs in der Moralphilosophie. In J. Schummer (Ed.), Glück und Ethik (pp. 169–187). Würzburg, Germany: Königshausen und Neumann.Google Scholar
  12. Keynes, J. M. (1972/1928). Economic possibilities for our grandchildren. In J. M. Keynes (Ed.), Collected writings, vol. IX (pp. 321–332). London: Royal Economic Society/Macmillan Press.Google Scholar
  13. Nozick, R. (1989). Happiness. In R. Nozick (Ed.), The examined life: Philosophical meditations (pp. 99–117). New York: Simon and Schuster.Google Scholar
  14. Ryan, R. M., & Deci, E. L. (2001). On happiness and human potentials: A review of research on hedonic and eudaimonic well-being. Annual Review of Psychology, 52, 141–166.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Ryff, C. D. (1989). Happiness is everything, or is it? Explorations on the meaning of psychological well-being. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 57, 1069–1081.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  16. Sen, A. K. (1977). Rational fools: A critique of the behavioural foundations of economic theory. Philosophy & Public Affairs, 6(4), 317–344.Google Scholar
  17. Sen, A. K. (2009). The idea of justice. London: Penguin.Google Scholar
  18. Spaemann, R. (2000/1989). Happiness and benevolence. Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.Google Scholar
  19. Tiberius, V. (2013a). Maximization and the good. In H. Brockmann & J. Delhey (Eds.), Human happiness and the pursuit of maximization (pp. 55–67). Dordrecht, The Netherlands: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  20. Tiberius, V. (2013b). Recipes for a good life: Eudaimonism and the contribution of philosophy. In A. S. Waterman (Ed.), The best within us: Positive psychology perspectives on eudaimonia (pp. 19–38). Washington, DC: American Psychological Association.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Tiberius, V., & Hall, A. (2010). Normative theory and psychological research: Hedonism, eudaimonism, and why it matters. The Journal of Positive Psychology, 5(3), 212–225.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Weber, M. (1985). Der Sinn der „Wertfreiheit“ der soziologischen und ökonomischen Wissenschaften. In J. Winckelmann (Ed.), Gesammelte Aufsätze zur Wissenschaftslehre (6th ed., pp. 489–540). Tübingen, Germany: Mohr.Google Scholar
  23. Wierzbicka, A. (1999). Emotions across languages and cultures: Diversity and universals. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2016

Authors and Affiliations

  1. 1.Hochschule Osnabrück, University of Applied SciencesOsnabrückGermany

Personalised recommendations