Skip to main content

Polarisation in Extended Scientific Controversies: Towards an Epistemic Account of Disunity

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Book cover Paradoxes of Conflicts

Part of the book series: Logic, Argumentation & Reasoning ((LARI,volume 12))

Abstract

The essay focuses on controversies where the debated issues are complex, the exchange involves several participants, and extends over long periods. Examples include the Methodenstreit, the Hering-Helmholtz controversy (Turner 1994) or the debates over Newton’s or Darwin’s views. In these cases controversies lasted for several generations, and polarisation is a recurring trait of the exchanges. The reconstructions and evaluations of the partly (but not only) polemical exchanges also exhibit heterogeneity and polarisation. Although I pick an early example of the Newtonian controversies, Darwin’s argument in The Origin of Species can also be variously reconstructed (Morrison 2000: 192–196). When scientific controversies that involve complex utterances (i.e. not single claims) are investigated, a specific problem arises, as in these situations the protagonist presenting a bundle of claims to a non-unified audience cannot fully control meaning-attribution of his utterances, and, given what we know about individual cognition, the more heterogeneous audience he succeeds in persuading, the less clear the meaning becomes. While the acceptance of a position increases potential for action, the growth in consent comes together with a fuzzy content. To problematise the role of polarisation, the significance of this description with respect to knowledge-production is investigated from both an individual and a social epistemological standpoint to answer the question: How is rhetoric epistemic in cases when at least two views on a given issue are seen as persuasively supported by communities? If engaging in a controversy is a means-to-an-end activity aimed at persuasion, directed at achieving attitude-change in recipients, how does the argumentative goal of an individual translate to epistémé in extended scientific controversies?

The work was supperted by the “Integrative Argumentation Studies” OTKA K 109456 grant. The author thanks István Danka for his comments and criticism of the manuscript.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    In Solomon’s framework of the cognitive division of labour if there are some empirical decision vectors for some view, it is rational to maintain it (Solomon 2001). This and other frameworks stress the benefit side of controversies, but little the cost side: how much effort is used to defend a difference of opinion that is exaggerated, thus the distortion of position is unaccounted for.

  2. 2.

    Most notably Robert L. Scott claimed that rhetoric is epistemic (Scott 1967), but after several rounds of debate it is hard to say what this exactly means (Harpine 2004), and it is even less clear how to proceed if granted that rhetoric is epistemic, as the claim was never meaningfully substantiated.

  3. 3.

    As Kauffeld recently noted: “…rhetoricians ought to dedicate clearer, more explicit attention to the normative dimensions of persuasive argumentation than has traditionally typified their studies.” (Kauffeld 2002: 115).

  4. 4.

    Around 1985 Latour still agreed with the proposal in the Postscript to the second edition of Laboratory Life (Latour and Woolgar 1986: 280) that there be “a ten-year moratorium on cognitive explanations of science” with the promise “that if anything remains to be explained at the end of this period, we too will turn to the mind!” In a less frequently quoted passage, the proposal continues: “If our French epistemologist colleagues are sufficiently confident in the paramount importance of cognitive phenomena for understanding science, they will accept the challenge.” The kind of cognitive explanations being rejected are those to be found in the works of Gaston Bachelard or in more general appeals to a scientific mentalité.

  5. 5.

    “Since, for the Fathers, according to their three acts of faith, (I) A and B address nature directly, (2) there are means for revealing its order, and (3) the use of such means is regulated by universal rules, they had an easy way (easy to define, if not always easy to apply) of settling this controversy. A wins a victory over B = A proves T or falsifies T. In this context, “victory” is a metaphoric concept. … For us, the Sons, the situation is different. As our loss of faith has induced us to maintain that there is neither a nature “out there’,“ speaking for itself nor neutral means or universal rules for discovering its structure, we have no other means of settling the controversy between A and B than the resources offered by the ongoing discussion between them. Our way, then, is like this: A wins a victory over B = A refutes B’ s arguments. Here “victory” is literal-it is a victory. It refers to the fact that A engages in a real discussion, a real exchange of arguments and counterarguments.” (Pera 2000: 52).

  6. 6.

    In Aristotle’s Rhetoric the enthymeme is an argument in a rhetorical speech - does not have formal qualities, like the scientific demonstration of the dialectical syllogism.Rhetorical proof is reasonable proof. (Bons 2002).

  7. 7.

    See e.g. (Bonevac 2003; van Rees 2003).

  8. 8.

    Just as sentence-variations changed the readings of Newton’s first letter, a similar sentence variation caused quite a stir in the reception of his major work, as some printed version contained and extra tanquam in a sentence on God (Koyre and Cohen 1961).

  9. 9.

    Turnbull 1959: 83.

  10. 10.

    Oldenburg also deleted the following passage from a later letter (21 September 1672): “To comply wth your intimation … I drew up a series of such Expts on designe to reduce ye Theory of colours to Propositions & prove each Proposition from one or more of those Expts by the assistance of common notions set down in the form of Definitions & Axioms in imitation of the Method by wch Mathematitians are wont to prove their doctrines” (Turnbull 1959: 237).

  11. 11.

    Here I assume some form of minimal theory of framing, as is developed in (Wohlrapp 2014).

  12. 12.

    As opposed to diachronic ‘styles of thinking’, an historical approach connected to the eary Kuhn’s work on paradigm-shifts, my interest is in the synchronic, coexisting ‘styles of thinking’ that results from, to use the late Kuhn’s phrase, the ‘speciation’ of lexicons. Foucault also first focused on the diachronic shifts in epistemé, and later allowed for the coexistence of these.

  13. 13.

    For the Duhemian indetermination-underdetermination distinction, see (Darling 2002, 522): “there are some cases in which indetermination is never completely overcome in practice and, … Duhem argues that the physicist always works with a mathematics of the approximate, in which the theoretical consequence of an approximately true proposition must be approximately exact (and the range of these two approximations must be delimited) in order to be useful.”

  14. 14.

    Dascal (2003); Wroblewski (1983).

References

  • Backhaus, J., & Hansen, R. (2000). Methodenstreit in der Nationalökonomie. Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 31, 307–336.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bacon, F. (1620). Novum Organum, in the works of Francis Bacon (7 vols.) (J. Spedding, R. L. Ellis, & D. D. Heath, Eds.). London: Longman, 1860, vol. 1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barnes, B., Bloor, D., & Henry, J. (1996). Scientific knowledge: A sociological analysis. London: Athlone.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloor, D. (1976). Knowledge and social imagery. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bloor, D. (1982). Durkheim and Mauss revisited. Classification and the sociology of knowledge. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 13(4), 267–298.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bloor, D. (1997). Remember the strong program? Science, Technology, and Human Values, 22(3), 373–385.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bloor, D. (1999a). Anti-Latour. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 30(1), 81–112.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bloor, D. (1999b). Reply to Bruno Latour. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 30(1), 131–136.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bonevac, D. (2003). Pragma-dialectics and beyond. Argumentation, 17, 451–459.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bons, J. A. E. (2002). Reasonable argument before Aristotle. In F. H. van Eemeren & P. Houtlosser (Eds.), Dialectic and rhetoric. The warp and woof of argumentation analysis (pp. 13–27). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Crombie, A. C. (1995). Styles of scientific thinking in the European tradition: the history of argument and explanation especially in the mathematical and biomedical sciences and arts. London: Duckworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Csibra, G., & Gergely, G. (2009). Natural pedagogy. Trends in Cognitive Sciences, 13, 148–153.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Darling, K. M. (2002). The complete Duhemianunderdetermination argument: Scientific language and practice. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 33, 511–533.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dascal, M. (2003). Interpretation and understanding. Amsterdam: John Benjamins.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dascal, M., & Gross, A. G. (1999). The marriage of pragmatics and rhetoric. Philosophy and Rhetoric, 32(2), 107–130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Donald, M. (1991). Origins of the modern mind: three stages in the evolution of culture and cognition. 2. [Dr.]. Aufl. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Donald, M. (2001). A mind so rare: The evolution of human consciousness. New York: Norton.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ducheyne, S. (2012). “The main business of natural philosophy” Isaac Newton’s Natural-Philosophical Methodology. New York: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Dunbar, K. (2002). Understanding the role of cognition in science: The science as category framework. In P. Carruthers, S. Stitch, & M. Siegal (Eds.), The cognitive basis of science (pp. 154–170). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Farrell, R. P. (2003). Feyerabend and scientific values: tightrope-walking rationality (Boston studies in the philosophy of science, 235). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Fleck, L. (1980). Entstehung und EntwicklungeinerwissenschaftlichenTatsache: Einführung in die LehrevomDenkstil und Denkkollektiv (L. Schäfer, & T. Schnelle, Trans.). Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. N. (1988). Explaining science: A cognitive approach. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. N. (1989). Units of analysis in science studies. In S. Fuller, M. DeMey, T. Shinn, & S. Woolgar (Eds.), The cognitive turn: Sociological and psychological perspectives on science (Sociology of the sciences yearbook, Vol. XIII, pp. 3–11). Dordrecht: D. Reidel.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. N. (2008). Cognitive studies of science and technology. In E. J. Hackett, O. Amsterdamska, M. Lynch, & J. Wajcman (Eds.), The handbook of science and technology studies (pp. 259–278). Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press, Published in cooperation with the Society for Social Studies of Science.

    Google Scholar 

  • Giere, R. N., & Moffatt, B. (2003). Distributed cognition: Where the cognitive and the social merge. Social Studies of Science, 33, 301–310.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilbert, N. H., & Mulkay, M. J. (1984). Opening Pandora’s box. A sociological analysis of scientists’ discourse. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gorman, M. E. (2005). Levels of expertise and trading zones: Combining cognitive and social approaches to technology studies. In M. E. Gorman, R. Tweney, D. Gooding, & A. Kincannon (Eds.), Scientific and technological thinking (pp. 287–302). Mahwah: Lawrence Erlbaum.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gross, A. G. (2000). Rhetoric as a technique and a mode of truth: Reflections on Chaim Perelman. Philosophy and Rhetoric, 33(4), 319–335.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gross, A. G., Harmon, J. E., & Reidy, M. S. (2000). Argument and 17th-century science: A rhetorical analysis with sociological implications. Social Studies of Science, 30(3), 371–396.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gruner, S. M. (1973). Defending Father Lucas: A consideration of the Newton-Lucas dispute on the nature of the spectrum. Centaurus, 17, 315–329.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Guicciardini, N. (2009). Isaac Newton on mathematical certainty and method. Cambridge, MA/London: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harpine, W. D. (2004). What do you mean, rhetoric is epistemic? Philosophy and Rhetoric, 37(4), 335–352.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Haskins, E. H. (2004). Endoxa, epistemological optimism, and Aristotle’s rhetorical project. Philosophy and Rhetoric, 37(1), 1–20.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hohmann, H. (2002). Rhetoric and dialectic. Some historical and legal perspectives. In F. H. van Eemeren, & P. Houtlosser (Eds.), Dialectic and rhetoric. The warp and woof of argumentation analysis. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hutchins, E. (1995). Cognition in the wild. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kauffeld, F. J. (2002). Pivotal issues and norms in rhetorical theories of argumentation. In F. H. van Eemeren & P. Houtlosser (Eds.), Dialectic and rhetoric. The warp and woof of argumentation analysis (pp. 97–118). Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knorr-Cetina, K. (1981). The manufacture of knowledge: an essay on the constructivist and contextual nature of science. Pergamon international library of science, technology, engineering, and social studies. Oxford/New York: Pergamon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Knorr-Cetina, K. (1999). Epistemic cultures: how the sciences make knowledge. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Koyre, A., & Cohen, I. B. (1961). The case of the missing Tanquam: Leibniz, Newton & Clarke. Isis, 52, 555–566.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. S. (1970). The structure of scientific revolutions (2nd ed.). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. S. (1990). The road since structure. PSA, 2, 3–13.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. S. (1993). Afterwords. In P. Horwich (Ed.), World changes: Thomas Kuhn and the nature of science (pp. 311–341). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Latour, Bruno; Woolgar, Steve. 1986. Laboratory Life: The Construction of Scientific Facts Introduction by JonasSalk With a new postscript and index by the authors. Princeton University Press

    Google Scholar 

  • Lehoux, D. (2003). Tropes, facts, and empiricism. Perspectives on Science, 11, 326–345.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. E. (1992). Essential tensions-Phase two: Feminist, philosophical and social studies of science. In E. McMullin (Ed.), The social dimensions of science (Vol. XI, 262 S). Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Machamer, P. K. (2000). The concept of the individual and the idea(l) of method in seventeenth-century natural philosophy. In M. Pera, P. K. Machamer, & A. Baltas (Eds.), Scientific controversies: Philosophical and historical perspectives (pp. 81–99). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Magnus, P. D. (2007). Distributed cognition and the task of science. Social Studies of Science, 37(2), 297–310.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Mamiani, M. (1991). The rhetoric of certainty: Newton’s method in science and in the interpretation of the Apocalypse. In M. Pera & W. R. Shea (Eds.), Persuading science: The art of scientific rhetoric (pp. 157–172). Canton: Science History Publications.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mannheim, K. (1936). In L. Wirth & E. Shils (Eds.), Ideology and utopia; an introduction to the sociology of knowledge. New York: Harcourt Brace.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mercier, H. (2011). When experts argue: explaining the best and the worst of reasoning. Argumentation, 25(3), 313–327. Available at SSRN: http://ssrn.com/abstract=1923096

  • Morrison, M. (2000). Unifying scientific theories. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Neurath, O. (1983). Philosophical papers, 1913-1946. Dordrecht: D. Riedel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Newton, I. (1671–1672). New theory about light and colors. Philosophical Transactions, (80):3075–3087.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pera, M. (2000). Rhetoric and scientific controversies. In M. Pera, P. K. Machamer, & A. Baltas (Eds.), Scientific controversies: Philosophical and historical perspectives (pp. 50–66). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pera, M., Machamer, P. K., & Baltas, A. (2000). Scientific controversies: Philosophical and historical perspectives. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pléh, C., Csibra, G., & Richerson, P. J. (2014). Naturalistic approaches to culture. Budapest: AkadémiaiKiadó.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rheinberger, H.-J. (1997). Toward a history of epistemic things: Synthetizing proteins in the test tube. Stanford: Stanford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Richerson, P. J., & Boyd, R. (2005). Not by genes alone: How culture transformed human evolution. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schaffer, S. (1989). Glass works: Newton’s prisms and the uses of experiment. In D. Gooding, T. Pinch, & S. Schaffer (Eds.), The uses of experiment: Studies in the natural sciences. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schumpeter, A. (1954). History of economic analysis. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Scott, R. L. (1967). On viewing rhetoric as epistemic. Central States Speech Journal, 18, 9–17.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, A. E. (1993). Fits, passions, and paroxysms: Physics, method, and chemistry and Newton’s theories of colored bodies and fits of easy reflection. New York/Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, A. E. (1996). The gradual acceptance of Newton’s theory of light and color, 1672–1727. Perspectives on Science, 4(1), 59–140.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, M. (2001). Social empiricism. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, M. (2006). Groupthink versus the wisdom of crowds: The social epistemology of deliberation and dissent. The Southern Journal of Philosophy, XLIV, 28–42.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein, C. R. (2003). Why societies need dissent. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tomasello, M. (1999). The cultural origins of human cognition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Toulmin, S. E. (1958). The uses of argument. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turnbull, H. W. (1959). The correspondence of Isaac Newton I. 1661–1675. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Turner, R. S. (1994). In the eye’s mind. Vision and the Helmholtz-Hering controversy. New Jersey: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Udehn, L. (2009). The ontology of the objects of historiography. In A. Tucker (Ed.), A companion to the philosophy of history and historiography (pp. 209–219). Chichester: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • van Rees, M. A. (2003). Within pragma-dialectics: Comments on Bonevac. Argumentation, 17, 461–464.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wohlrapp, H. R. (2014). The concept of argument: A philosophical foundation. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Wroblewski, J. (1983). Fuzziness of legal system. Essays in Legal Theory in Honour of KaarleMakkonenOikeustiede. Junsprudentia, XVI, 315–319.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zemplén, G. Á., & Demeter, T. (2010, October). Being charitable to scientific controversies – On the demonstrativity of Newton’s experimentum Crucis. The Monist, 93(4), 638–654.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Gábor A. Zemplén .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Zemplén, G.A. (2016). Polarisation in Extended Scientific Controversies: Towards an Epistemic Account of Disunity. In: Scarafile, G., Gruenpeter Gold, L. (eds) Paradoxes of Conflicts. Logic, Argumentation & Reasoning, vol 12. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-41978-7_5

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics