Skip to main content

Actuality from Potentiality

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Pythagorean World
  • 394 Accesses

Abstract

In this chapter, I am going to explore how actuality emerges from potentiality. In the last chapter I engaged in some speculative thinking about the general process but in this chapter, I want to be more specific and that will entail a retreat to a more manageable problem. I will be considering two paradigms: (1) Leibnizian possible worlds, which is rooted in classical physics, and (2) the consistent histories quantum theory of Griffiths, Gell-Mann, Hartle, and Omnès (I will refer to this as CHQT). Hence, at least initially, I will not be considering all of mathematics but merely that part which is required for these paradigms. It is a moot point how much mathematics that encompasses and I will have more to say about that at the conclusion.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 99.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 129.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Drawing on Leibniz’s dream of a universal science, Gödel dreamed of a theory of concepts which would go beyond the theory of sets (i.e. beyond mathematics). Whereas set theory deals with extensions, concept theory would deal with intensions. Note that different concepts can have the same extension whereas, by definition, different sets cannot since they are determined by their extension. For more on this topic, see Wang (1996): Chap. 8.

  2. 2.

    Heinrich Schepers said that “one can view Leibniz’s metaphysics as the work of rationally explicating the different expressions of the polarity of the One and the Many” (Schepers 2000: 171).

  3. 3.

    A Hermitian operator is an operator which is equal to its adjoint, so its eigenvalues are real numbers.

  4. 4.

    See, for example Zeilinger (1999), and Yu and Nikolic (2011).

  5. 5.

    See, for example, Griffiths (2002), Omnès (1994), and Gell-Mann and Hartle (1990).

  6. 6.

    A property of a system is given when one can assert that the value of an observable A is in some given set D of real numbers (Omnès 1992: 342).

  7. 7.

    More generally, an IGUS is a complex adaptive system which is coupled to its environment in some way, able to model its local environment by some form of logical processing, and able to act on the results of its computations. It could be biological, or it could be something like a thermostat or a robot (Hartle 2007b: 3111).

  8. 8.

    Intuitively, if the components of a quantum system are in a superposition, the only way they can decohere is through interaction with an environment, and an environment can only be defined by coarse-graining.

  9. 9.

    A projector is a Hermitian operator on the Hilbert space which is equal to its square, so its eigenvalues are 0 and 1.

  10. 10.

    For example, it is meaningless to ask which slit a photon passed through in Young’s double-slit experiment when an interference pattern is observed.

  11. 11.

    And because of complications such as thermodynamic irreversibility and chaos.

  12. 12.

    Omnès (1994) has applied the methods of quantum information theory to rigorously reconstruct measurement theory from the principles of CHQT—from quantum observables to macroscopic observables.

  13. 13.

    For example, delayed-choice paradoxes, indirect measurement paradoxes, incompatibility paradoxes and the EPR paradox. In each case, when the relevant experiment is clearly defined in a consistent histories framework, the paradox is shown to be the result of comparing, or combining, incompatible frameworks.

  14. 14.

    The table cannot be reproduced here for copyright reasons and the details are not of importance for the current discussion. The interested reader is referred to the original.

  15. 15.

    There are some events which have probability one in a particular framework but it is difficult to identify events which occur with probability one in any fundamental consistent set fine-graining the actual history (Dowker and Kent 1996: 1611–1616).

  16. 16.

    Note that “seemingly contradictory events” contradict our intuitions but do not lead to inconsistencies in the formalism.

  17. 17.

    The physical analogy is a Bose-Einstein condensate.

  18. 18.

    A force that originates in a system with many degrees of freedom by the statistical tendency to increase its entropy is called an entropic force. It has been suggested that gravity is an entropic force (Verlinde 2011).

  19. 19.

    Note that Appendix 2 considers problems which arise from postulating plenitude and offers a defence.

References

  • Benioff, P. 2002. Towards a Coherent Theory of Physics and Mathematics. Foundations of Physics 32: 989–1029.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2005. Towards a Coherent Theory of Physics and Mathematics: The Theory Experiment Connection. Foundations of Physics 35: 1825–1856.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Bernal, A., M. Sánchez, and F. Soler Gil 2008. Physics from Scratch: Letter on M. Tegmark’s “The Mathematical Universe”, arXiv:0803.0944, pp. 1–7.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. 1956. Empiricism, Semantics and Ontology. In Meaning and Necessity, 205–221. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dowker, F., and A. Kent. 1996. On the Consistent Histories Approach to Quantum Mechanics. Journal of Statistical Physics 82: 1575–1646.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Garber, D. 2009. Leibniz: Body, Substance, Monad. New York and Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gell-Mann, M., and J. Hartle. 1990. Quantum Mechanics in the Light of Quantum Cosmology. Proceedings of the 3rd International Symposium on the Foundations of Quantum Mechanics, Tokyo 1989: 321–343.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007. Quasiclassical Coarse Graining and Thermodynamic Entropy. Physical Review A 76: 022104–022122.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014. Adaptive Coarse Graining, Environment, Strong Decoherence, and Quasiclassical Realms. Physical Review A 89: 052125–052137.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Griffiths, R. 2002. Consistent Quantum Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2013. A Consistent Quantum Ontology. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 44: 93–114.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2014a. The New Quantum Logic. Foundations of Physics 44: 610–640.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hartle, J. 2004. The Quantum Mechanics of Closed Systems, arXiv:gr-qc/9210006v2, pp. 1–11.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007a. Quasiclassical Realms in a Quantum Universe, arXiv:gr-qc/9404017v4, pp. 1–8.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007b. Quantum Physics and Human Language. Journal of Physics A 40: 3101–3121.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007c. Generalizing Quantum Mechanics for Quantum Spacetime. In The Quantum Structure of Space and Time, Proceedings of the 23rd Solvay Conference on Physics, edited by D. Gross, M. Henneaux, and A. Sevrin. Singapore: World Scientific.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2011. The Quasiclassical Realms of this Quantum Universe. Foundations of Physics 41: 982–1006.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hersch, R. 1979. Some Proposals for Reviving the Philosophy of Mathematics. Advances in Mathematics 31: 31–50.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jolley, N. (ed). 1995. The Cambridge Companion to Leibniz. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Leibniz, G. 1850–1863. Leibnizens Mathematische Schriften, 7 vols., edited by C.I. Gerhardt. Berlin and Halle: Weidmann.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1875–1890. Die Philosophischen Schriften, 7 vols., edited by C.I. Gerhardt. Berlin: Weidmann.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1923–. Samtliche Schriften und Briefe, Deutsche Akademie der Wissenschaften zu Berlin (eds.), Berlin: Akademie-Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1989. Philosophical Essays. Edited and translated by R. Ariew and D. Garber. Indianapolis: Hackett.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1996. New Essays in Human Understanding. Edited and translated by P. Remnant and J. Bennett. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2007. The Leibniz-Des Bosses Correspondence. Edited and translated by B. Look and D. Rutherford. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Martin, G. 1964. Leibniz, Logic and Metaphysics. Manchester: Manchester University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Omnès, R. 1988. Logical Reformulation of Quantum Mechanics I. Foundations. Reviews of Modern Physics 64: 339–382.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1992. Consistent Interpretations of Quantum Mechanics. Journal of Statistical Physics 53: 893–932.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1994. The Interpretation of Quantum Mechanics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 2005. Converging Realities: Toward a Common Philosophy of Physics and Mathematics. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. 1980. Models and Reality. The Journal of Symbolic Logic 45: 464–482.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, N. 1967. The Philosophy of Leibniz. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schepers, H. 2000. Die Polarita ten des Einen und des Vielen im Begriff der Monade. In Unità e Molteplicità nel Pensiero Filosofico e Scientifico di Leibniz, edited by A. Lamarra and R. Palaia, 171–184. Florence: Olscki.

    Google Scholar 

  • Tegmark, M. 1998. Is “the Theory of Everything” Merely the Ultimate Ensemble Theory? Annals of Physics 270: 1–51.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hooft, G. 2012. Discreteness and Determinism in Superstrings, arXiv:1207.3612 [hep-th].

    Google Scholar 

  • Verlinde, E. 2011. On the Origin of Gravity and the Laws of Newton. Journal of High Energy Physics 4: 1–27.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wang, H. 1996. A Logical Journey: From Gödel to Philosophy. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wheeler, J. 1980. Law without Law. In Structure in Science and Art, edited by P. Medawar and J. Shelley, 132–154. New York: Elsevier North-Holland.

    Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1996. At Home in the Universe. New York: Springer-Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wigner, E. 1964. Two Kinds of Reality. The Monist 48: 248–264.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • ———. 1979. Symmetries and Reflections: Scientific Essays. Woodbridge, CT: Ox Bow Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilczek, F. 2005. In Search of Symmetry Lost. Nature 433: 239–247.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Yu, S., and D. Nikolic. 2011. Quantum Mechanics Needs No Consciousness. Reviews of Modern Physics 71: 931–938.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zeilinger, A. 1999. Experiment and the Foundations of Quantum Physics. Annals of Physics 523: S288–S297.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zurek, W. 2002. Decoherence and the Transition from Quantum to Classical—Revisited. Los Alamos Science 27: 1–25.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

McDonnell, J. (2017). Actuality from Potentiality. In: The Pythagorean World. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-40976-4_6

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics