Skip to main content

The Virtues and Vices of Kotarbiński’s Praxiology

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
  • 166 Accesses

Abstract

The chapter defends the view that Kotarbiński’s ‘theory of efficient action’ (or ‘praxiology’) is an example of the fully fledged philosophy of action. It shows its key virtues and explains why it has been gone nearly unnoticed for over a half of the century. This explanation discloses serious interpretative difficulties which partially come from the presence of reism in Kotarbiński’s theorizing. In the last step, the chapter sketches the framework, which is projected both to remove internal difficulties related to the original exposition of Kotarbiński’s theory and to reveal its connections with other contemporary theories.

Wenn ich meine Teufel vertreibe,

dann vertreibe ich auch meine Engel.

Rilke (‘If my devils are to leave me, I am afraid my angels will take flight as well’ (quoted by Rollo May, Love and Will. New York: Delta 1969: 122))

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution.

Buying options

Chapter
USD   29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD   79.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD   99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD   99.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Learn about institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Where possible, I give references to English editions or versions of Kotarbiński’s works. In the case of the translation of Treatise, I have changed, when necessary, the term work to job (for Polish robota), which satisfies better both philological and philosophical needs.

  2. 2.

    It is good to note that there is also the French root of praxiology connected with the work of Louis Bourdeau and Alfred Espinas (see e.g. Alexandre and Gasparski 1999). Kotarbiński used to stress that praxiology has some predecessors (e.g. Kotarbiński 1965: Chap. 1), but I agree with those who claim that it was just a result of his modesty. In fact, these two French authors had had an indiscernible influence on the shape of praxiology in the Treatise. Compare: Stonert (1970: 257).

  3. 3.

    The birth of praxiology can be dated from 1910 when Kotarbiński wrote his address: The Goal of An Act and the Task of An Agent (Kotarbiński 1983a). For more (see e.g. Gasparski 1993, 1996). The term praxiology was first used in a 1923 paper Zasady teorii czynu (Kotarbiński 1927). I will not go into historical details of the birth of praxiology since it is beyond the interest of this study.

  4. 4.

    This statement refers to praxiology understood as the philosophy of action. From the perspective of economics, the matter may look differently.

  5. 5.

    Kotarbiński himself considered eclecticism as the most unjust criticism of his philosophy (see Woleński 1985: Chap. XI).

  6. 6.

    In fact, Kotarbiński’s followers quickly realized this fact (see e.g. Szaniawski 1972: 10–12).

  7. 7.

    Such a study of the dynamics of progress in efficiency would be methodologically similar to, say, the history of biology or the history of physics. Kotarbiński was aware that its role would be ‘ancillary to the preceding two’ (Kotarbiński 1965: 8), so I ignore it in what follows.

  8. 8.

    I shall have something more to say about this issue in the conclusion of this chapter.

  9. 9.

    The idea of bridging theory and practice—which is at stake here—is an old and complex issue. Naturally, I do not claim that there is no such thing as a connection between empirical practical sciences and practical philosophy. (Nor do I want to claim that philosophy does not have a practical import at all). But this is a different problem than the problem of praxiology as a systematized, unified ‘science’ with something like ‘bridging laws’ between simple practical advices and abstract praxiological norms.

    Notice also that the relation which is criticized here is a bit similar to the relation between the Kantian categorical imperative and individual rules of actions (‘maxims’). I cannot go into details of this comparison; it will be enough to say that such similarity is only structural (and one cannot save praxiology as a ‘science’ from the Kantian position).

  10. 10.

    In Poland, many of Kotarbiński’s pupils and followers could take this manoeuvre as unacceptable (odd at best). This might be so because the idea of praxiology as a science gave birth to a great number of more or less viable and interesting proposals. To list only a few: praxiometrics, an attempt at strictly quantitative account of praxiological concepts and relations (see e.g. Gasparski 1969); formal praxiology, a project of the deductive science of action with a new conceptual-logical apparatus (Stonert 1967, 1968; Konieczny and Stonert 1971); praxiosemantics (or praxiosemiotics), a theory of optimal sign (Wójcik 1969), praxiological organization science (e.g. Zieleniewski 1969). I cannot discuss these proposals here. Nevertheless, many of them deserve much attention—not only for historical purposes. At any rate, the reader should also be aware of the following: the strategy I use in this book is not meant to undermine the weight of all the valuable applications, or extensions of praxiology that emerged from Kotarbiński’s Treatise.

  11. 11.

    Again, this is what makes the Kotarbińskian approach to praxiology much more refined than the von Misesian.

  12. 12.

    There are also other terms, such as ‘general methodology’, or ‘methodology of practical skills’ (Kotarbiński 1937, 1971), but for the purposes of this book, I prefer to stick to the term action theory.

  13. 13.

    Those authors who think that praxiology does not have much in common with the analytical action theory probably treat the latter too rigidly. It is well established that philosophy in the Lvov-Warsaw School—even the philosophy of Kotarbiński himself—shared its specificity with the Vienna Circle. We have strong reasons to treat Kotarbiński’s praxiology as belonging to the analytic tradition, even if it stands out of its mainstream.

  14. 14.

    Translation slightly altered (optional impulse instead of free impulse). The need of such alterations is explained in what follows.

  15. 15.

    ‘States of affairs’ in the English edition of Treatise appear, misleadingly, as ‘states of things’ (Ibidem.).

  16. 16.

    Kotarbiński to highlight this phenomenon recalls the French dictum: embarrass de richesse (Kotarbiński 1965: 43).

  17. 17.

    In English translation all these three are called tests, which is, again, somewhat misleading. I discuss the problem of Kotarbiński’s language (and its translation into English) in section 1.3.

  18. 18.

    Translation slightly altered.

  19. 19.

    In what follows we shall see that Kotarbiński’s language of action is peculiar which makes his praxiology significantly different from the mainstream action theory.

  20. 20.

    Needless to say, his approach remains unknown for the research on foundationalism. See Sandis 2010: 10–17; Lavin 2013.

  21. 21.

    Again, if we want to find Kotarbiński’s ideas in the works from this field, we are faced with a rather mind-bending task.

  22. 22.

    For a complex discussion of this idea in Aristotle, see my paper (Makowski 2009).

  23. 23.

    Compound act in Wojtasiewicz’ translation.

  24. 24.

    The pun proposed by Professor Wojciech Gasparski (e.g. Gasparski 2000: 192).

  25. 25.

    If we browse through the titles which I have listed at the beginning (Preface), we will get a set of examples for this strategy. It is also present in the works of praxiologists (see e.g. Gasparski 1983b: 81).

  26. 26.

    I defend the view that the standards of natural languages in practical philosophy should be accepted as long as we do not have reasons not to do so: they are a default option in action theory. This view is a departure from the Kotarbińskian ambitions to improve natural language (see sections “Why Has the Theory of Efficient Action Not Been Efficient? Problems with ‘The Grammar of Action”, “Kotarbiński’s Conception of Efficiency: A Critical Analysis” and “Efficiency and Economy”).

  27. 27.

    In Wojtasiewicz’s translation: ‘non-effective’.

  28. 28.

    This chapter contains also a separate heading of the activization of an agent, which should be understood as an autonomous norm. Kotarbiński treats it as subsidiary, to some extent, to other norms, but it does not mean that it is normatively or ontologically negligible. I shall turn back briefly to this issue in the next chapter.

  29. 29.

    After Von Neumann and Morgenstern (1944), this absence can be perceived as a serious vice of Kotarbiński’s account.

  30. 30.

    What is historically understandable, Kotarbiński, in some places of his works, refers to various aspects of the matter of the planned economy. In this sense, the Marxist ideology left an imprint on his practical philosophy. But this does not mean that praxiology has been an attempt at offering a theoretical grounding of the Soviet understanding of economy and society. It seems that the exactly opposite thought has made Ludwig von Mises avoid the Polish approach to praxiology. See his thoughts on the socialist society (Mises 1945: Chap. XXV).

    The relation between the Soviet science and Kotarbiński’s philosophy becomes more explicit when we realize that Kotarbiński needed to defend his ontological doctrine (especially, the conception of reism) from the criticism of dialectic materialism, which, as we know, has been an official world-view of Marxism (see Woleński 1985: 216–219). I discuss Kotarbiński’s ontology in the next section.

  31. 31.

    Wojtasiewicz’s translation is generally good; the fact that he was not a philosopher—he was a linguist and a sinologist (sic!)—partially explains why his translations are sometimes surprising.

  32. 32.

    By using this term, I refer to Putnam and his well-known comparison between Leśniewski’s and Carnap’s approach to ontology (‘world a la Carnap and ‘Same’ world a la Polish logician’) (Putnam 1987: 18–19). Putnam says that Leśniewski’s description of the world is ‘partisan’ in comparison to the ‘neutral’ description offered by Carnap. Pace neutralism, I think that there is a deeper analogy between Leśniewski’s ontology and Carnap’s, on the one hand, and the Kotarbińskian language of action and the language widely accepted in practical philosophy, on the other. Nevertheless, although it is a fascinating topic, I shall not discuss it here.

  33. 33.

    Here is Carnap: ‘Tadeusz Kotarbinski’s ideas were related to our physicalism. He maintained conceptions which he called “reism” and “pansomatism”, i.e., the conception that all names are names of things and that all objects are material things’ (Carnap 1963: 31).

  34. 34.

    Woleński thinks likewise (Woleński 1985: 210, fn. 6; Woleński 2012).

  35. 35.

    Brentano’s reism is dualistic: bodies and souls exist (cf. Kotarbiński 1976; Woleński 1985: 213).

  36. 36.

    Naturally, we can express propositional attitudes without that-clauses, but for the sake of simplicity I do not discuss this issue here. It is enough to know that other forms of expressing propositional attitudes also fall under the method of reistic translation, so they do not pose difficulties to the argument I offer.

  37. 37.

    Similar criticism has been proposed by Tadeusz Ciecierski (2013: 168–169).

  38. 38.

    In his discussion of reism, Woleński seems to hesitate on whether reism preserves intentionality or not. On the one hand, he suggests that there is no apparent reason to think that it cannot embrace intentionality, since Kotarbinski cultivated his philosophical connections with Brentano and Twardowski, and intentionality is the key theme in these authors. On the other hand, he stresses that reism was ‘revisionist’ (Woleński 1985: 226). I take the revisionist ambitions of reism, together with its approach to propositional attitudes, as harmful for the picture of intentionality. As a result, I interpret reism as offering a distorted view of intentionality.

  39. 39.

    In English translation of the Treatise, we usually find ‘agent’, so the concretistic language is not visible in this case. Still, we can interpret the original term in its semantic context.

  40. 40.

    One might reply: reism cannot be related to conceptual fecundity, because it is devised to eliminate redundant entities. I believe that the opposite is more correct: to eliminate something one needs to name it. And only those names which occur to be apparent can be eliminated.

  41. 41.

    ‘The agent’s point of view’ is an idea proposed by Hilary Putnam (discussed also by many others). I shall turn back to it later (Chap. 3).

  42. 42.

    Translation slightly altered.

  43. 43.

    Naturally, on the opposite camp we can find valuable criticisms of this approach.

  44. 44.

    I do not know of any study that investigates such support more explicitly than Pacherie’s (2008). Nonetheless, it is plain that the phenomenology of action uses the informal conceptual apparatus of BDI, and that it proposes a phenomenologically sound, partial embedding of BDI. In this sense, the support is bilateral, or, as Pacherie says, action is ‘both conceptually and empirically motivated’ (Pacherie 2008: 181).

  45. 45.

    There is a research in neuroscience that questions such a primary role of intentions in human agency (cf. Uithol et al. 2014). Neural data, they claim, do not support the idea that discrete mental states (as intentions) cause and control agency. Causation and control are dynamic processes, so we should revise our conception of intentional action and search for other conceptual apparatuses that capture them better. But notice that the acceptance of the highlighted role of intentions does not obligate us to causalism (more on this in Chap. 6). Also, the virtues of folk psychology inherited by BDI and the phenomenology of action are not overridden by the neuropsychological data. Of course, what I suggest does not mean that neuroscience is useless in the philosophy of action—quite the opposite.

  46. 46.

    For an excellent discussion of this issue, see Di Nucci (2014: Chap. 3).

  47. 47.

    Some authors claim that folk-psychological intentionality attribution requires thinking in terms of BDI (see e.g. Malle 2010). Nevertheless, I suppose that cases of automated actions show that this is a bit more complex problem. This is an issue for future studies. I shall have something to say about this in Chap. 6.

  48. 48.

    On the basis of Pacherie’s great account of a complex ‘intentional cascade’ (Pacherie 2008) we can see how such a web may look like. I shall briefly return to Pacherie’s proposal in Chap. 6.

  49. 49.

    Even such a general claim—namely: doing things for reasons implies a relation between beliefs, desires and intentions—is implicitly a stance concerning how to conceive the idea of reasons in general. I shall turn back to this issue in Chap. 4.

  50. 50.

    The terminology itself is subject to dispute (see e.g. Lenman 2011).

  51. 51.

    Michael Smith takes both types of reasons as completely different (Smith 1994: 96). Here I am on the side of the others (e.g. Garrard and McNaughton 1998: 48; Heuer 2004: 45) who see the possibility where these two can be identical.

  52. 52.

    To avoid possible confusions—which may appear especially if the reader is a theorist of law or a Kantian—let me note that in this book I do not distinguish norms, rules and standards. However important these distinctions are, they are out of the scope of this study.

  53. 53.

    This is not reserved only for action theory. In his classic book The Foundations of Statistics, Leonard Savage used the dictum ‘look before you leap’ as a metaphor of a principle in the theory subjective utility (Savage 1972: 16–17).

  54. 54.

    This methodological issue has been studied in many disciplines (as economics, decision theory or set theory). For a good discussion of it, see for example Szaniawski (1974) and Sen (1997).

References

  • Kotarbiński, T. (1927). Zasady teorii czynu. Przegląd Filozoficzny, 30(4). (Księga Pamiątkowa Pierwszego Polskiego Zjazdu Filozoficznego, Lwów 1923): 273–274 [P1: 132–133].

    Google Scholar 

  • Kotarbiński, T. (1937). Idée de la méthodologie générale. Praxéologie. In Actualités Scientifiques et Industrielles No. 533. Travaux du IX Congrès International de Philosophie. Paris 1937: 190–194 [O istocie i zadaniach metodologii ogólnej (prakseologii). Przegląd Filozoficzny, 41(1)(1938): 68–75, P1: 57–62].

    Google Scholar 

  • Kotarbiński, T. (1938). Z zagadnień ogólnej teorii walki. Warszawa: SPTWW [P1: 166–198].

    Google Scholar 

  • Kotarbiński, T. (1948). Sur l’attitude rèiste (ou concrétiste). Synthese, 7(4–5), 262–273 [O postawie reistycznej, czyli konkretystycznej. Myśl Współczesna, 10 (1949): 3–11].

    Google Scholar 

  • Kotarbiński, T. (1955). The fundamental ideas of pansomatism (trans: Tarski, A. & Rynin, A.). Mind, 64(256), 488–500 [Zasadnicze myśli pansomatyzmu. Przegląd Filozoficzny, 1935(4): 282–294].

    Google Scholar 

  • Kotarbiński, T. (1960). The concept of action. The Journal of Philosophy, 57, 215–22 [P1: 319–325].

    Google Scholar 

  • Kotarbiński, T. (1961). The property of a good plan. Methodos, 13(51/52), 189–201 [Walory dobrego planu. Nauka Polska, 9(1)(1961): 47–58; P1: 292–304].

    Google Scholar 

  • Kotarbiński, T. (1962a). Przegląd ocen praktycznych działania. In his Myśli o dobrej robocie (pp. 5–18). Warszawa: [P1: 351–361].

    Google Scholar 

  • Kotarbiński, T. (1962b). Kryształy myśli praktycznej. In his Myśli o dobrej robocie (pp. 32–34). Warszawa: [P2: 40–41].

    Google Scholar 

  • Kotarbiński, T. (1962c). Praxiological sentences and how they are proved. In E. Nagel, P. Suppes, & A. Tarski (Eds.), Logic, methodology, and philosophy of science (pp. 211–223). Stanford: Stanford University Press [Rodzaje zdań prakseologicznych i sposoby ich uzasadniania. Kultura i Społeczeństwo, 4 (1960): 3–16; P2: 83–95].

    Google Scholar 

  • Kotarbiński, T. (1965). Praxiology: An introduction to the sciences of efficient action (trans: Wojtasiewicz, O.). Oxford: Pergamon Press/Warszawa: PWN [Traktat o dobrej robocie, Ossolineum, Wrocław 1955].

    Google Scholar 

  • Kotarbiński, T. (1969). Reism: Issues and prospects. Logique et Analyse, 44, 441–458.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kotarbiński, T. (1971). The methodology of practical skills: Concepts and issues. Metaphilosophy, 2(2), 158–170 [Metodologia umiejętności praktycznych: pojęcia i zagadnienia. Projektowanie i Systemy, 4(1983): 11–20; P2: 341–351].

    Google Scholar 

  • Kotarbiński, T. (1976). Franz Brentano as reist. In L. McAlister (Ed.), The philosophy of Franz Brentano (pp. 194–203). London: Duckworth [Franciszek Brentano jako reista. Studia Filozoficzne, 2(1967)].

    Google Scholar 

  • Kotarbiński, T. (1983a). The goal of an act and the task of the agent. In: W. W. Gasparski & T. Pszczołowski (Eds.). Praxiological studies: Polish contributions to the science of efficient action (pp. 1–19). Warsaw/Dordrecht: PWN/Reidel [Cel czynu a zadanie wykonawcy. In T. Kotarbiński, Szkice praktyczne, Warszawa: Wydawnictwo Kasy im. Mianowskiego 1913: 1–31; P1: 6–19].

    Google Scholar 

  • Kotarbiński, T. (1986). Drogi dociekań własnych. Fragmenty filozoficzne. Warszawa: PWN.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gasparski, W. W. (1969). The praxiometrical model of production relationships. Prakseologia, 33, 33–52.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gasparski, W. W. (1983b). Comments on the concept of efficiency. In W. W. Gasparski & T. Pszczołowski (Eds.), Praxiological studies (pp. 61–83). Warszawa: PWN.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Gasparski, W. W. (1993). A philosophy of practicality: A treatise on the philosophy of Tadeusz Kotarbiński. Helsinki: Societas Philosophica Fennica.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gasparski, W. W. (1996). Between logic and ethics: The origin of praxiology. Axiomathes, 7(3), 385–394.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gasparski, W. W. (2000). Polish ethical and praxiological tradition and the ethics of business society. In T. Airaksinen & O. L. Kola (Eds.), New ethics--New society, or the dawn of justice (Acta Philosophica Fennica, Vol. 65, pp. 189–202). Helsinki: Societas Philosophica Fennica.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gasparski, W. W. (2013). Human action as an ultimate given: Ludwig von Mises’ praxeology as seen from a business ethics angle. Studia Humana, 2(1), 3–14.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gasparski, W. W., & Airaksinen, T. (Eds.). (2008). Praxiology and philosophy of technology. New Jersey: Transaction Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Konieczny, J., & Stonert, H. (1971). Prakseologia formalna. Główne założenia i program badań. Prakseologia, 37, 39–52.

    Google Scholar 

  • Piłejko, K. (1967). Prakseologia a postulaty konkretyzmu i adekwatności twierdzeń. Na osiemdziesięciolecie Tadeusza Kotarbińskiego. Prakseologia, 24, 3–16.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stonert, H. (1967). Analiza logiczna pojęć nauki o działaniu. Cz. I. Prakseologia, 27, 85–123.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stonert, H. (1968). Analiza logiczna pojęć nauki o działaniu. Cz. II. Prakseologia, 29, 57–113.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stonert, H. (1970). Review: Jerzy Kurnal, Zarys teorii organizacji i zarządzania. Prakseologia, 35, 255–267.

    Google Scholar 

  • Szaniawski, K. (1972). Prakseologia i jej twórca. In T. Kotarbiński (Ed.), Abecadło praktyczności (pp. 3–13). Warszawa: Wiedza Powszechna.

    Google Scholar 

  • Szaniawski, K. (1974). Logiczne aspekty optymalizacji. Biuletyn Naukowy Instytutu Nauk Ekonomicznych, 32, 41–53.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wójcik, T. (1969). Prakseosemiotyka. Zarys teorii optymalnego znaku. Warszawa: PWN.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zieleniewski, J. (1969). Organizacja i zarządzanie. Warszawa: PWN.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexandre, V., & Gasparski, W. W. (Eds.). (1999). The roots of praxiology. French action theory from Bourdeau and Espinas to present days (Praxiology: The International Annual of Practical Philosophy and Methodology, Vol. 7). New Brunswick: Transaction Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alvarez, M. (2010). Kinds of reasons. An essay in the philosophy of action. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Anscombe, G. E. M. (1963). Intention (2nd ed.). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press (1st ed., 1957).

    Google Scholar 

  • Bittner, R. (2001). Doing things for reasons. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Bratman, M. E. (1983). Taking plans seriously. Theory and Social Practice, 9(2–3), 272–287.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bratman, M. E. (1987). Intention, plans, and practical reason. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carnap, R. (1963). Intellectual autobiography. In A. Schilpp (Ed.), The philosophy of Rudolf Carnap (pp. 3–43). La Salle: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Carr, D. (1979). The logic of knowing how and ability. Mind, New Series, 88(351), 394–409.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Casati, R., & Varzi, A. (2014). Events. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2014 Edition), E. N. Zalta (Ed.), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2014/entries/events/

  • Chrudzimski, A., & Smith, B. (2004). Brentano’s ontology: From conceptualism to reism. In D. Jacquette (Ed.), The Cambridge companion to Brentano (pp. 197–219). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ciecierski, T. (2013). Nastawienia sądzeniowe. Warszawa: PWN.

    Google Scholar 

  • Danto, A. C. (1973). Analytical philosophy of action. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Davidson, D. (1967). Causal relations. The Journal of Philosophy, 64, 691–703 [reprinted in Davidson 1990, pp. 149–162].

    Google Scholar 

  • DeHelian, L., & McClennen, E. F. (1993). Planning and the stability of intention. A comment. Mind and Machines, 3, 319–333.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ginet, C. (1975). Knowledge, perception, and memory. Dordrecht: D. Reidel Publishing Company.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Gollwitzer, P. M. (1993). Goal achievement: The role of intentions. In W. Stroebe & M. Hewstone (Eds.), European review of social psychology (Vol. 4, pp. 141–185). Chichester: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gollwitzer, P. M. (1999). Implementation intentions: Strong effects of simple plans. American Psychologist, 54, 493–503.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gollwitzer, P. M., & Brandstätter, V. (1997). Implementation intentions and effective goal pursuit. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 73, 186–199.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heuer, U. (2004). Reasons for actions and desires. Philosophical Studies, 121(1), 43–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hilpinen, R. (2011). Artifact. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2011 Edition), E. N. Zalta (Ed.), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2011/entries/artifact/

  • Lavin, D. (2013). Must there be basic action? Noûs, 47(2), 273–301.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lejewski, C. (1979). On the dramatic stage in the development of Kotarbinski’s pansomatism. In P. Weingartner & E. Morscher (Eds.), Ontologie und Logik. Vorträge und Diskussion eines Internationalen Kolloquiums (pp. 197–214). Berlin: Duncker & Humblot.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lenman, J. (2011). Reasons for action: Justification vs. explanation. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2011 Edition), E. N. Zalta (Ed.), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2011/entries/reasons-just-vs-expl/

  • Makowski, P. T. (2009). Metaphysics of practical philosophy. The concept of capacity in Aristotle. In G. Arabatzis (Ed.), Studies on supernaturalism (pp. 59–73). Berlin: Logos Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Malle, B. F. (2010). Intentional action in folk psychology. In T. O’Connor & C. Sandis (Eds.), A companion to the philosophy of action (pp. 357–365). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • McClure, P. T. (1971). Review: Praxiology: An introduction to the sciences of efficient action by Tadeusz Kotarbinski; O. Wojtasiewicz. Policy Sciences, 2(2), 198–200.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mele, A. R. (1992). Springs of action: Understanding intentional behaviour. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morgenbesser, S., & Ullmann-Margalit, E. (1977). Picking and choosing. Social Research, 44(4), 757–785.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Brien, L., & Sotteriou, M. (Eds.). (2009). Mental actions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ostrowski, J. J. (1968). Review: Praxiology: An introduction to the science of efficient action by Tadeusz Kotarbinski; Olgierd Wojtasiewicz. Philosophy, 43(166), 402–404.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Pacherie, E. (2005). Perceiving intentions. In J. Sàágua (Ed.), A Explicação da Interpretação Humana (pp. 401–414). Lisbon: Edições Colibri.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pacherie, E. (2008). The phenomenology of action: A conceptual framework. Cognition, 107 (1), 179–217.

    Google Scholar 

  • Parfit, D. (2011). On what matters. Oxford/New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Paternotte, C. (2014). Constraints on joint action. In M. Gallotti & J. Michael (Eds.), Perspectives on social ontology and social cognition (pp. 103–124). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Pollock, J. (1947–48). My painting. Possibilities I, New York.

    Google Scholar 

  • Proffitt, D. R. (2006). Embodied perception and the economy of action. Perspectives on Psychological Science, 1(2), 110–122.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Putnam, H. (1987). Many faces of realism(The Paul Carus lectures). LaSalle: Open Court.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roth, A. S. (2003). Practical intersubjectivity. In F. F. Schmitt (Ed.), Socializing metaphysics. The nature of social reality (pp. 65–91). Lanham: Rowmand & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ryle, G. (1949). The concept of mind. Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sandis, C. (2010). Basic actions and individuation. In T. O’Connor & C. Sandis (Eds.), A copanion to the philosophy of action (pp. 10–17). Oxford: Blackwell.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Scanlon, T. M. (1996). The status of well-being (Tanner lectures on human values 16, pp. 91–143). http://tannerlectures.utah.edu/_documents/a-to-z/s/Scanlon%20well-being.pdf. Retrieved December 03, 2015.

  • Scott, W. A. (1962). Cognitive complexity and cognitive flexibility. Sociometry, 25(4), 405–414.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Searle, J. R. (1990). Collective intentions and actions. In P. Cohen, J. Morgan, & M. Pollack (Eds.), Intentions in communication (pp. 401–415). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Singh, M. P. (1994). Multiagent systems. A theoretical framework for intentions, know-how and communications. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sinisi, V. F. (1965). Kotarbiński’s theory of pseudo-names. Theoria, 31(3), 218–241.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Smith, B. (1990). On the phases of reism. In Woleński (1990), 137–183.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, M. (1994). The moral problem. Oxford: Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Stanley, J. (2011). Know how. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Uithol, S., Burnston, D. C., & Haselager, P. (2014). Why we may not find intentions in the brain. Neuropsychologia, 56, 129–139.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Von Neumann, J., & Morgenstern, O. (1944). Theory of games and economic behavior. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woleński, J. (1985). Filozoficzna Szkoła Lwowsko-Warszawska. Warszawa: PWN.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woleński, J. (Ed.). (1990). Kotarbiński: Logic, semantics and ontology. Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woleński, J. (2012). Reism. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2012 Edition), E. N. Zalta (Ed.), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2012/entries/reism/

  • Woleński, J. (2013). Lvov-Warsaw School. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Spring 2014 Edition), E. N. Zalta (Ed.), http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/lvov-warsaw/

  • Yaffe, G. (2010). Attempts: In the philosophy of action and the criminal law. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2017 The Author(s)

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Makowski, P.T. (2017). The Virtues and Vices of Kotarbiński’s Praxiology. In: Tadeusz Kotarbiński’s Action Theory. Palgrave Macmillan, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-40051-8_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics