Skip to main content

Towards a Third ‘Practice Turn’: An Inclusive and Empirically Informed Perspective on Risk

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Philosophy of Technology after the Empirical Turn

Part of the book series: Philosophy of Engineering and Technology ((POET,volume 23))

Abstract

In this chapter we identify three practice turns in the social and philosophical study of technology that we also relate to risk analysis. The first practice turn singled out technology as a topic meriting serious investigation as a social phenomenon, the second turn steered the field towards the consideration of philosophical problems directly relating to what technology is and what engineers do. The third practice turn explicitly aims at changing the field’s practice by close collaboration with the engineers. We argue that given the entanglement of evaluative and descriptive aspects of risk, it is important to develop approaches geared at this third turn, which is only now starting to take place. We propose that phronesis can play an important role in making context-sensitive assessments of evaluative aspects of risks, and that it can be assisted by emotions and art, as sources of moral reflection.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 109.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 139.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    While these are often referred to as ‘empirical turns’ in technology studies, we prefer the term ‘practice turn’, which brings us into line with other reflective disciplines such as sociology or philosophy of science.

  2. 2.

    Cf. McDowell (1981) and Williams (2006). Though the distinction between thin normative concepts and thick ones may not be a sharp one, it is nonetheless conceptually useful (e.g. Kirchin 2013).

  3. 3.

    Bayesian approaches can be seen as reasoning along these lines; however, they also face the problem that they cannot stop the regress by formal arguments alone (cf. Frisch 2015).

References

  • Asveld, L., & Roeser, S. (Eds.). (2009). The ethics of technological risk. London: Routledge/Earthscan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Beck, U. (1986). Risikogesellschaft. Auf dem Weg in eine andere Moderne. Suhrkamp: Frankfurt am Main.

    Google Scholar 

  • Biddle, J., & Winsberg, E. (2010). Value judgements and the estimation of uncertainty in climate modeling. In P. D. Magnus & J. Busch (Eds.), New waves in philosophy of science (pp. 172–197). New York: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Brook, B. W., Edney, K., Hillerbrand, R., Karlsson, R., & Symons, J. (forthcoming). Energy research within the UNFCCC: A proposal to guard against ongoing climate-deadlock. Climate Policy. doi: 10.1080/14693062.2015.1037820.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chang, R. (1997). Introduction. In R. Chang (Ed.), Incommensurability, incomparability, and practical reason (pp. 1–34). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchman, C. W. (1948). Theory of experimental inference. New York: Macmillan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Churchman, C. W. (1956). Science and decision making. Philosophy of Science, 22, 247–249.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Decker, M. (2013). Technikfolgen. In A. Grunwald (Ed.), Handbuch Technikethik (pp. 33–38). Stuttgart: Metzler.

    Google Scholar 

  • Douglas, H. (2000). Inductive risk and values in science. Philosophy of Science, 67, 559–579.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Douglas, M., & Wildavsky, A. (1982). Risk and culture. An essay on the selection of technological and environmental dangers. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, M. (1991). Governmentality. In G. Burchell, C. Gordon, & P. Miller (Eds.), The Foucault effect (pp. 87–104). Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Franssen, M. (2006). The normativity of artefacts. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 37(1), 42–57.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Frisch, M. (2015). Predictivism and old evidence: A critical look at climate model tuning. European Journal for Philosophy of Science, 5(2), 171–190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Fischhoff, B., Lichtenstein, S., Slovic, P., Derby, S. L., & Keeney, R. L. (1981). Acceptable risk (p. 185). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gessert, G., (2003). Notes on the art of plant breeding. In L’Art Biotech catalogue, exhibition catalog, Nantes: Le Lieu Unique, 47

    Google Scholar 

  • Giddens, A. (1990). Consequences of modernity. Cambridge: Polity Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer, G. (2007). Gut feelings: The intelligence of the unconscious. London: Viking.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gigerenzer, G., & Gaissmaier, W. (2011). Heuristic decision making. Annual Review of Psychology, 62, 451–482.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gilovich, T., Griffin, D., & Kahneman, D. (Eds.). (2002). Intuitive judgment: Heuristics and biases. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greene, J. (2013). Moral tribes. New York: Penguin.

    Google Scholar 

  • Haidt, J. (2012). The righteous mind: Why good people are divided by politics and religion. New York: Vintage Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hall, C. A. (2005). The trouble with passion: political theory beyond the reign of reason. New York: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Heilbroner, R. L. (1967). DO machines make history? Technology & Culture, 8, 335–345.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hillerbrand, R. (2010). Unintended consequences and risky technologies. A virtue ethical approach to the moral problems caused by genetic engineering. In D. Pavlich (Ed.), Environmental justice and global citizenship (pp. 167–183). Amsterdam: Rodopi.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hillerbrand, R. (2011). Von Risikoabschätzungen zum „guten Leben“, Aus Politik und Zeitgeschichte, Themenheft Ende des Atomzeitalters? 61. Jahrgang, 46–47(14), 42–48.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hillerband, R. (2015). The role of nuclear energy in the future energy landscape: Energy scenarios, nuclear energy and sustainability. In B. Taebi & S. Roeser (Eds.), The ethics of nuclear energy: Risk, justice, and democracy in the post-Fukushima era (pp. 231–249). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Höffe, O. (1993). Moral als Preis der Moderne: Ein Versuch über Wissenschaft, Technik und Umwelt. Frankfurt a.M: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Janssen, P. H. M., Petersen, A. C., van der Sluijs, J. P., Risbey, J. S., & Ravetz, J. R. (2005). A guidance for assessing and communicating uncertainties. Water Science and Technology, 52(6), 125–131.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jasanoff, S. (1993). Bridging the two cultures of risk analysis. Risk Analysis, 13(2), 123–129.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Jeffrey, R. (1954). Valuation and acceptance of scientific hypotheses. Philosophy of Science, 22, 237–246.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jonas, H. (1979). Das Prinzip Verantwortung: Versuch einer Ethik für die technologische Zivilisation. Frankfurt a.M: Insel Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahan, D. (2012). Cultural cognition as a conception of the cultural theory of risk. In S. Roeser, R. Hillerbrand, P. Sandin, & M. Peterson (Eds.), Handbook of risk theory: Epistemology, decision theory, ethics, and social implications of risk (pp. 725–760). London: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D. (2011). Thinking fast and slow. New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kahneman, D., & Tversky, A. (1974). Judgment under uncertainty: heuristics and biases. Science, 185(4157), 1124–1131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kaplan, S., & Garrick, B. J. (1981). On the quantitative definition of risk. Risk Analysis, 1(1), 11–27.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kasperson, R. E., Renn, O., Slovic, P., Brown, H. S., Emel, J., Goble, R., Kasperson, J. X., & Ratick, S. (1988). The social amplification of risk: A conceptual framework. Risk Analysis, 8, 177–187.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kirchin, S. (Ed.). (2013). Thick concepts. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kingston, R. (2011). Public passion: rethinking the grounds for political justice. Kingston: McGill-Queen’s Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kompridis, N. (Ed.). (2014). The aesthetic turn in political thought. London: Bloomsbury Academic.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kroes, P., & Meijers, A. (Eds.). (2000). The empirical turn in the philosophy of technology. Amsterdam: JAI.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kroes, P., & Meijers, A. (2006). The dual nature of technical artefacts. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part A, 37(1), 1–4.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Künneke, R., Mehos, D. C., Hillerbrand, R., & Hemmes, K. (2015). Understanding values embedded in offshore wind energy systems: Toward a purposeful institutional and technological design. Environmental Science & Policy, 53, 118–12.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lacewing, M. (2005). Emotional self-awareness and ethical deliberation. Ratio, 18, 65–81.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Little, M. (2000). Moral generalities revisited. In B. Hooker & M. Little (Eds.), Moral particularism (pp. 276–304). Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Loewenstein, G. F., Weber, E. U., Hsee, C. K., & Welche, N. (2001). Risk as feelings. Psychological Bulletin, 127(2), 267–286.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luntley, M. (2003). Ethics in the face of uncertainty: Judgement not rules. Business Ethics A European Review, 12(4), 325–333.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Maga, D. (2015). A methodology to assess the contribution of biorefineries to sustainable bio-based economy. Oberhausen: Karl Maria Laufen.

    Google Scholar 

  • McDowell, J. (1981). Non-cognitivism and rule-following. In S. Holtzman & C. Leich (Eds.), Wittgenstein: To follow a rule (pp. 141–162). London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

    Google Scholar 

  • Moore, G. E. (1988 [1903]). Principia Ethica. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Möller, N. (2012). The concepts of risk and safety. In S. Roeser, R. Hillerbrand, P. Sandin, & M. Peterson (Eds.), Handbook of risk theory: epistemology, decision theory, ethics, and social implications of risk (pp. 55–85). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Nihlén Fahlquist, J. (2015). Responsibility as a virtue and the problem of many hands. In I. van de Poel, L. Royakkers, & S. D. Zwart (Eds.), Moral responsibility and the problem of many hands (pp. 187–208). London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nihlén Fahlquist, J., & Roeser, S. (2015). Nuclear energy, responsible risk communication and moral emotions: A three level framework. Journal of Risk Research, 18(3), 333–346.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. (2001). Upheavals of thought. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Nussbaum, M. (2013). Political emotions: why love matters for justice. Cambridge, MA: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • O’Malley, P. (1999). Governmentality and the risk society. Economy and Society, 28(1), 138–148.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Peinke, J., Böttcher, F., & Barth, S. (2004). Anomalous statistics in turbulence, financial markets and other complex systems. Annals of Physics, 13(7–8), 450–460.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raynor, S., & Cantor, R. (1987). How fair is safe enough? The cultural approach to societal technology choice. Risk Analysis, 7(1), 3–9.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reichle, I. (2009). Art in the age of technoscience: Genetic engineering, robotics, and artificial life in contemporary art. Vienna: Springer.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Reitinger, C., Dumke, M., Barosevcic, M., & Hillerbrand, R. (2011). A conceptual framework for impact assessment within SLCA. The International Journal of Life Cycle Assessment, 16(4), 380–388.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Reitinger, C., Kopriwa, N., Penner, H., Piana, L., Dumke, M., Fayyaz, S., Hillerbrand, R., & Pfennig, A. (2012). Integration sozialer Aspekte bei der Prozessbewertung. In M. Decker, A. Grunwald, & M. Knapp (Eds.), Der Systemblick auf Innovation. Technikfolgenabschätzung in der Technikgestaltung, Tagungsband NTA 4 (pp. 419–423). Berlin: Sigma.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Roeser, S. (2006). The role of emotions in judging the moral acceptability of risks. Safety Science, 44, 689–700.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roeser, S. (2007). Ethical intuitions about risks. Safety Science Monitor, 11, 1–30.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roeser, S. (2009). The relation between cognition and affect in moral judgments about risk. In L. Asveld & S. Roeser (Eds.), The ethics of technological risk (pp. 182–201). London: Routledge/Earthscan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roeser, S. (Ed.). (2010a). Emotions and risky technologies. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roeser, S. (2010b). Intuitions, emotions and gut feelings in decisions about risks: Towards a different interpretation of “neuroethics”. The Journal of Risk Research, 13, 175–190.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roeser, S. (2010c). Emotional reflection about risks. In S. Roeser (Ed.), Emotions and risky technologies (pp. 231–244). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Roeser, S. (2011). Moral emotions and intuitions. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Roeser, S. (2012). Risk communication, public engagement, and climate change: A role for emotions. Risk Analysis, 32, 1033–1040.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Roeser, S., Fahlquist, J. N., Hillerbrand, R. (2015). Risk. In H. ten Have (ed.), Encyclopedia of Global Bioethics (pp. 1–10). Springer, online first.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roeser, S., & Pesch, U. (2016). An emotional deliberation approach to risk. Science, Technology & Human Values, 41, 274–297.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roeser, S., Hillerbrand, R., Sandin, P., & Peterson, M. (Eds.). (2012). Handbook of risk theory: Epistemology, decision theory, ethics, and social implications of risk. London: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ross, A., & Athanasoulis, N. (2012). Risk and virtue ethics. In S. Roeser, R. Hillerbrand, P. Sandin, & M. Peterson (Eds.), Handbook of risk theory: Epistemology, decision theory, ethics, and social implications of risk (pp. 833–856). London: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Rudner, R. (1953). The scientist qua scientist makes value judgments. Philosophy of Science, 20(1), 1–6.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shrader-Frechette, K. (1991). Risk and rationality. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slovic, P. (1999). Trust, emotion, sex, politics, and science: Surveying the risk-assessment battlefield. Risk Analysis, 19, 689–701.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slovic, P. (2000). The perception of risk. London: Earthscan.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slovic, S., & Slovic, P. (Eds.). (2015). Numbers and nerves: Information, emotion, and meaning in a world of data. Corvallis: Oregon State University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Slovic, P., Finucane, M. L., Peters, E., & MacGregor, D. G. (2004). Risk as analysis and risk as feelings: some thoughts about affect, reason, risk, and rationality. Risk Analysis, 24(2), 311–322.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Soler, L., Zwart, S., Lynch, M., & Israel-Jost, V. (Eds.). (2014). Science after the practice turn in the philosophy, history, and social studies of science. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Staiger, J., Cvetkovich, A., & Reynolds, A. (2010). Political emotions. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Starr, C. (1969). Social benefit versus technological risk. Science, 165, 1232–1238.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Steger, F., & Hillerbrand, R. (2013). Praxisfelder angewandter Ethik. Ethische Orientierung in Medizin, Politik, Technik und Wirtschaft. Münster: Mentis.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein, C. R. (2005). Laws of fear. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sunstein, C. R. (2010). Moral heuristics and risk. In S. Roeser (Ed.), Emotions and risky technologies (pp. 3–16). Dordrecht: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Taebi, B., & Kloosterman, J. L. (2008). To recycle or not to recycle? An intergenerational approach to nuclear fuel cycles. Science and Engineering Ethics, 14(2), 177–200.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Taebi, B., Roeser, S., & Van de Poel, I. (2012). The ethics of nuclear power: social experiments, intergenerational justice, and emotions. Energy Policy, 51, 202–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Tversky, A., & Kahneman, D. (1974). Judgment under uncertainty: Heuristics and biases. Science, 185, 1124–1131.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • van de Poel, I., & Royakkers, L. (2011). Ethics, technology and engineering. Oxford: Wiley-Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • van den Hoven, J., Vermaas, P. E., & van de Poel, I. (Eds.). (2015). Handbook of ethics, values, and technological design sources, theory, values and application domains. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Van der Burg, S., & Van Gorp, A. (2005). Understanding moral responsibility in the design of trailers. Science and Engineering Ethics, 11, 235–256.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williams, B. (2006). Ethics and the limits of philosophy. London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Zwijnenberg, R. (2009). Preface. In I. Reichle (Ed.), Art in the age of technoscience: Genetic engineering, robotics, and artificial life in contemporary art (pp. xii–xxix). Vienna: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgements

We would like to thank Peter Kroes and Maarten Franssen for their extremely helpful comments on earlier drafts on this chapter, and Veronica Alfano for proofreading and editing our text.

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Rafaela Hillerbrand .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Hillerbrand, R., Roeser, S. (2016). Towards a Third ‘Practice Turn’: An Inclusive and Empirically Informed Perspective on Risk. In: Franssen, M., Vermaas, P., Kroes, P., Meijers, A. (eds) Philosophy of Technology after the Empirical Turn. Philosophy of Engineering and Technology, vol 23. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-33717-3_9

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics