Advertisement

Interests, Embodiment, and Constraint by the World

  • Michael P. Wolf
  • Jeremy Randel Koons
Chapter
  • 164 Downloads

Abstract

Thus far, we have made three central claims. First, we have argued that some form of naturalism, or at least allegiance to versions of some tenets associated with it, is a preferred methodological starting point for philosophy. Second, we have argued that efforts to solve the placement problem for normative discourse via reduction or non-reductive supervenience approaches cannot deliver convincing accounts. Third, we have argued that this sort of moderate naturalism should not lead us to abandon an understanding of our own normative discourse that is both truth-apt and constrained by the world in an important sense. Few philosophers have tried to reconcile all three of these themes. Those who say we cannot place the normative in the natural world tend to eviscerate normative discourse, replacing it with some form of projectivism or norm-expressivism (e.g., Blackburn, Gibbard), while others opt to eliminate it altogether or treat it fictionally (e.g., Mackie, Joyce). Those moved to keep a world with robust normativity often find themselves moving explicitly away from naturalism (e.g., McDowell, Wiggins), or toward supernaturalism (e.g., Adams, Craig). To many, there will be at least a whiff of an inconsistent triad in these three claims.

Keywords

Higgs Boson Large Hadron Collider Social Practice Normative Practice Normative Concept 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

References

  1. Brandom, Robert. 1994. Making It Explicit. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  2. CERN Press Office. 2012. CERN experiments observe particle consistent with long-sought Higgs boson. CERN. July 4. http://press.web.cern.ch/press-releases/2012/07/cern-experiments-observe-particle-consistent-long-sought-higgs-boson. Accessed 23 July 2013.Google Scholar
  3. Chemero, Anthony. 2009. Radical Embodied Cognitive Science. Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.Google Scholar
  4. Dewey, John. 1925/1958. Experience and Nature. New York: Dover Publications.Google Scholar
  5. Honneth, A. 2008. Reification: A New Look at an Old Idea. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. James, William. 1904. A World of Pure Experience I. The Journal of Philosophy, Psychology, and Scientific Methods 1(20): 533–543.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  7. Kukla, R., and M. Lance. 2014. Intersubjectivity and Receptive Experience. The Southern Journal of Philosophy 52(1): 22–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  8. McDowell, John. 1981. Non-Cognitivism and Rule-Following. In Wittgenstein: To Follow a Rule, eds. S. Holtzman, and Christopher M. Leich, 141–162. New York, NY: Routledge.Google Scholar
  9. Nussbaum, Martha. 2000. Women and Human Development: The Capabilities Approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  10. Rupert, Robert D. 2004. Challenges to the Hypothesis of Extended Cognition. The Journal of Philosophy 101(8): 389–428.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Sellars, Wilfrid. 1956/1997. Empiricism and the Philosophy of Mind. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
  12. Wagman, Jeffrey, and Anthony Chemero. 2014. The End of the Debate Over Extended Cognition. In Neuroscience, Neurophilosophy, and Pragmatism: Brains at Work with the World, ed. T. Solymosi and J.R. Shook. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.Google Scholar

Copyright information

© The Author(s) 2016

Authors and Affiliations

  • Michael P. Wolf
    • 1
  • Jeremy Randel Koons
    • 2
  1. 1.Washington, PAUSA
  2. 2.DohaQatar

Personalised recommendations