Advertisement

A Problem for the Traditional Account of Knowledge

  • Kevin McCain
Chapter
  • 166k Downloads
Part of the Springer Undergraduate Texts in Philosophy book series (SUTP)

Abstract

This chapter begins by briefly recapping what has been discovered about the traditional account of knowledge throughout the previous chapters. The traditional account of knowledge holds that one has knowledge of some proposition just in case one justifiedly believes the proposition, and the proposition is true. As earlier chapters showed, believing a proposition requires having an appropriate mental representation of the proposition, being justified in believing the proposition requires believing on it on the basis of sufficiently strong evidence, and a proposition’s being true consists of it accurately describing objective reality. After the traditional account of knowledge has been made clear, a decisive objection to that account of knowledge is explained: the Gettier Problem. In addition to explaining how the Gettier Problem shows that the traditional account of knowledge is incomplete this chapter explores some promising responses to the Gettier Problem. Finally, the chapter concludes by noting that even without an answer to the Gettier Problem we can use the traditional account of knowledge as a framework for understanding scientific knowledge.

Keywords

Perceptual Experience Visual Experience Justify Belief Fourth Condition Gettier Case 
These keywords were added by machine and not by the authors. This process is experimental and the keywords may be updated as the learning algorithm improves.

References

  1. BonJour, L. (2010a). Epistemology: Classic problems and contemporary responses (2nd ed.). Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
  2. BonJour, L. (2010b). The myth of knowledge. Philosophical Perspectives, 24, 57–83.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  3. Butchvarov, P. (1970). The concept of knowledge. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.Google Scholar
  4. Chisholm, R. M. (1977). Theory of knowledge (2nd ed.). Englewood Cliffs: Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
  5. Clark, M. (1963). Knowledge and grounds: A comment on Mr. Gettier’s paper. Analysis, 24, 46–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  6. Descartes, R. (1641/1988). Meditations on first philosophy. In J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, & D. Murdoch (Trans.), Descartes: Selected philosophical writings (pp. 73–123). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
  7. Elgin, C. Z. (1996). Considered judgment. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  8. Feldman, R. (1974). An alleged defect in Gettier counter-examples. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 52, 68–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  9. Feldman, R. (2003). Epistemology. Upper Saddle River: Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
  10. Gendler, T. S., & Hawthorne, J. (2005). The real guide to fake barns: A catalogue of gifts for your epistemic enemies. Philosophical Studies, 124, 331–352.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  11. Gettier, E. L. (1963). Is justified true belief knowledge? Analysis, 23, 121–123.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  12. Goldman, A. I. (1976). Discrimination and perceptual knowledge. Journal of Philosophy, 73, 771–791.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  13. Goodman, N., & Elgin, C. Z. (1988). Reconceptions in philosophy & other arts & sciences. Indianapolis: Hackett.Google Scholar
  14. Greenough, P., & Pritchard, D. (2009). Williamson on knowledge. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  15. Harman, G. (1973). Thought. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  16. Hetherington, S. (1998). Actually knowing. Philosophical Quarterly, 48, 453–469.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  17. Hetherington, S. (2001). Good knowledge, bad knowledge: On two dogmas of epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  18. Hetherington, S. (2005). Gettier problems. Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://www.iep.utm.edu/gettier/
  19. Jenkins-Ichikawa, J. & Steup, M. (2014). The analysis of knowledge. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2014 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/knowledge-analysis/
  20. Kampourakis, K. (2014). Understanding evolution. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  21. Kaplan, M. (1985). It’s not what you know that counts. Journal of Philosophy, 82, 350–363.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  22. Kvanvig, J. (1998). Why should enquiring minds want to know? Meno problems and epistemological axiology. Monist, 81, 426–452.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  23. Kvanvig, J. (2003). The value of knowledge and the pursuit of understanding. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  24. Lehrer, K. (1971). Why not scepticism? Philosophical Forum, 2, 283–298.Google Scholar
  25. Lehrer, K. (1979). The Gettier Problem and the analysis of knowledge. In G. Pappas (Ed.), Justification and knowledge (pp. 65–78). Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  26. Lehrer, K. (2000). Theory of knowledge (2nd ed.). Boulder: Westview Press.Google Scholar
  27. Ludwig, K. (2007). The epistemology of thought experiments: First vs. third person approaches. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 31, 128–159.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  28. Lycan, W. G. (2006). On the Gettier Problem problem. In S. Hetherington (Ed.), Epistemology futures (pp. 148–168). Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  29. McCain, K., & Weslake, B. (2013). Evolutionary theory and the epistemology of science. In K. Kampourakis (Ed.), The philosophy of biology: A companion for educators (pp. 101–119). Dordrecht: Springer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  30. Russell, B. (1912). The problems of philosophy. London: Williams and Norgate.Google Scholar
  31. Shope, R. K. (1983). The analysis of knowing: A decade of research. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
  32. Sosa, E. (2007). Experimental philosophy and philosophical intuitions. Philosophical Studies, 132, 99–107.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  33. Sosa, E. (2009). A defense of the use of intuitions in philosophy. In D. Murphy & M. Bishop (Eds.), Stich and his critics (pp. 101–112). Malden: Blackwell.Google Scholar
  34. Steup, M. (1996). An introduction to contemporary epistemology. Upper Saddle River: Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
  35. Turri, J. (2012a). In Gettier’s wake. In S. Hetherington (Ed.), Epistemology: The key thinkers (pp. 214–229). London: Continuum.Google Scholar
  36. Turri, J. (2012b). Is knowledge justified true belief? Synthese, 184, 247–259.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  37. Turri, J. (2013). A conspicuous art: Putting Gettier to the test. Philosophers’ Imprint, 13http://quod.lib.umich.edu/p/phimp/3521354.0013.010/1
  38. Unger, P. (1971). A defense of skepticism. Philosophical Review, 30, 198–218.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  39. Weinberg, J., Nichols, S., & Stich, S. (2001). Normativity and epistemic intuitions. Philosophical Topics, 29, 429–460.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  40. Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
  41. Williamson, T. (2007). The philosophy of philosophy. Malden: Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
  42. Zagzebski, L. (1994). The inescapability of Gettier problems. Philosophical Quarterly, 44, 65–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar

Copyright information

© Springer International Publishing Switzerland 2016

Authors and Affiliations

  • Kevin McCain
    • 1
  1. 1.Department of PhilosophyUniversity of Alabama at BirminghamBirminghamUSA

Personalised recommendations