The Nature of Scientific Knowledge pp 57-92 | Cite as
Justification
- 166k Downloads
Abstract
This chapter focuses on the final component of the traditional account of knowledge: justification. Traditionally, justification has been understood as having good reasons for believing that a particular claim is true. The nature of these good reasons is examined in this chapter. In particular, practical reasons for accepting a particular claim are distinguished from epistemic reasons for accepting a particular claim. It is the epistemic reasons that are necessary for knowledge. Additionally, a major contemporary debate in epistemology concerning whether one always needs good reasons in order to be justified is explored in this chapter. Internalists say “yes”, but externalists say “no”. Some of the major moves in this debate are explained in this chapter. However, it becomes clear by the chapter’s end that whether internalists or externalists are correct in general, the sort of justification required for scientific knowledge does require good reasons, which are best understood as evidence.
Keywords
Good Reason True Belief Visual Experience Justify Belief Basic BeliefReferences
- Alston, W. P. (1985). Concepts of epistemic justification. The Monist, 68, 57–89.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Alston, W. P. (1988). The deontological conception of epistemic justification. Philosophical Perspectives, 2, 257–299.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Angere, S. (2007). The defeasible nature of coherentist justification. Synthese, 157, 321–335.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Angere, S. (2008). Coherence as a heuristic. Mind, 117, 1–26.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Armstrong, D. M. (1973). Belief, truth and knowledge. London: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Audi, R. (1988). Belief, justification, and knowledge. Belmont: Wadsworth.Google Scholar
- Audi, R. (1993). Contemporary foundationalism. In L. Pojman (Ed.), The theory of knowledge: Classic and contemporary readings (pp. 206–213). Belmont: Wadsworth.Google Scholar
- Audi, R. (2011). Epistemology: A contemporary introduction to the theory of knowledge (3rd ed.). New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
- Baehr, J. (2011). The inquiring mind: On intellectual virtues and virtue epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Bergmann, M. (2006). Justification without awareness: A defense of epistemic externalism. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Bishop, M. (2010). Why the generality problem is everybody’s problem. Philosophical Studies, 151, 285–298.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- BonJour, L. (1978). Can empirical knowledge have a foundation? American Philosophical Quarterly, 15, 1–13.Google Scholar
- BonJour, L. (1980). Externalist theories of empirical knowledge. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 5, 53–73.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- BonJour, L. (1985). The structure of empirical knowledge. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
- BonJour, L. (2000). Toward a defense of empirical foundationalism. In M. DePaul (Ed.), Resurrecting old-fashioned foundationalism (pp. 21–40). Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
- BonJour, L. (2006). Replies. Philosophical Studies, 131, 743–759.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- BonJour, L. (2010). Epistemology: Classic problems and contemporary responses (2nd ed.). Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
- Bosanquet, B. (1920). Implication and linear inference. London: Macmillan.Google Scholar
- Bovens, L., & Hartmann, S. (2003). Bayesian epistemology. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
- Brewer, B. (1997). Foundations of perceptual knowledge. American Philosophical Quarterly, 34, 41–55.Google Scholar
- Burge, T. (1986). Individualism and psychology. Philosophical Review, 95, 3–45.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Chisholm, R. M. (1956). Epistemic statements and the ethics of belief. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 16, 447–460.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Chisholm, R. M. (1966). Theory of knowledge. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
- Chisholm, R. M. (1977). Theory of knowledge (2nd ed.). Englewood Cliffs: Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
- Chisholm, R. M. (1982). The foundations of knowing. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.Google Scholar
- Chisholm, R. M. (1989). Theory of knowledge (3rd ed.). Englewood Cliffs: Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
- Cohen, G. (1996). Memory in the real world (2nd ed.). East Sussex: Psychology Press.Google Scholar
- Cohen, S. (1984). Justification and truth. Philosophical Studies, 46, 279–295.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Cohen, S. (2002). Basic knowledge and the problem of easy knowledge. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 65, 309–329.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Comesaña, J. (2006). A well-founded solution to the generality problem. Philosophical Studies, 129, 27–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Comesaña, J. (2010). Evidentialist reliabilism. Nous, 44, 571–600.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Conee, E. (1988). The basic nature of epistemic justification. Monist, 71, 389–404.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Conee, E. (2013). The specificity of the generality problem. Philosophical Studies, 163, 751–762.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Conee, E., & Feldman, R. (1998). The generality problem for reliabilism. Philosophical Studies, 89, 1–29.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Conee, E., & Feldman, R. (2004). Making sense of skepticism. In E. Conee & R. Feldman (Eds.), Evidentialism (pp. 277–306). New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Conee, E., & Feldman, R. (2011). Replies. In T. Dougherty (Ed.), Evidentialism and its discontents (pp. 428–501). New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
- Dancy, J. (1985). Introduction to contemporary epistemology. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
- Davidson, D. (1986). A coherence theory of knowledge and truth. In E. Lepore (Ed.), Truth and interpretation (pp. 307–319). Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
- DePaul, M. (2014). Foundationalism. In S. Bernecker & D. Pritchard (Eds.), The Routledge companion to epistemology (pp. 235–244). New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
- Descartes, R. (1641/1988). Meditations on first philosophy. In J. Cottingham, R. Stoothoff, & D. Murdoch (Trans.), Descartes: Selected philosophical writings (pp. 73–123). Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
- Dietrich, F., & Moretti, L. (2005). On coherent sets and the transmission of confirmation. Philosophy of Science, 72, 403–424.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Douven, I., & Meijs, W. (2007). Measuring coherence. Synthese, 156, 405–425.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Engel, M. (1992). Personal and doxastic justification. Philosophical Studies, 67, 133–151.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Ewing, A. C. (1934). Idealism: A critical survey. London: Methuen.Google Scholar
- Feldman, R. (1985). Reliability and justification. Monist, 68, 159–174.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Feldman, R. (1988). Epistemic obligations. Philosophical Perspectives, 2, 235–256.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Feldman, R. (2003). Epistemology. Upper Saddle River: Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
- Feldman, R. (2005). Justification is internal. In M. Steup & E. Sosa (Eds.), Contemporary debates in epistemology (pp. 270–284). Malden: Blackwell.Google Scholar
- Feldman, R., & Conee, E. (1985). Evidentialism. Philosophical Studies, 45, 15–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Feldman, R., & Conee, E. (2001). Internalism defended. American Philosophical Quarterly, 38, 1–18.Google Scholar
- Fumerton, R. (1995). Metaepistemology and skepticism. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
- Fumerton, R. (2000). Classical foundationalism. In M. DePaul (Ed.), Resurrecting old-fashioned foundationalism (pp. 3–20). Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
- Fumerton, R. & Hasan, A. (2010). Foundationalist theories of epistemic justification. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Summer 2010 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2010/entries/justep-foundational/
- Gertler, B. (2012). Understanding the internalism-externalism debate: What is the boundary of the thinker? Philosophical Perspectives, 26, 51–75.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Ginet, C. (1975). Knowledge, perception, and memory. Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Ginet, C. (2005a). Infinitism is not the solution to the regress problem. In M. Steup & E. Sosa (Eds.), Contemporary debates in epistemology (pp. 140–148). Malden: Blackwell.Google Scholar
- Ginet, C. (2005b). Reply to Klein. In M. Steup & E. Sosa (Eds.), Contemporary debates in epistemology (pp. 153–155). Malden: Blackwell.Google Scholar
- Glass, D. H. (2007). Coherence measures and inference to the best explanation. Synthese, 157, 257–296.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Goldberg, S. (Ed.). (2007). Internalism and externalism in semantics and epistemology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
- Goldman, A. I. (1979). What is justified belief? In G. Pappas (Ed.), Justification and knowledge (pp. 1–23). Dordrecht: Reidel.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Goldman, A. I. (1986). Epistemology and cognition. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
- Goldman, A. I. (1988). Strong and weak justification. Philosophical Perspectives, 2, 51–69.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Goldman, A. I. (1992). Epistemic folkways and scientific epistemology. In A. I. Goldman (Ed.), Liaisons: Philosophy meets the cognitive and social sciences (pp. 155–175). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
- Goldman, A. I. (1999). Internalism exposed. Journal of Philosophy, 96, 271–293.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Goldman, A. I. (2008). Immediate justification and process reliabilism. In Q. Smith (Ed.), Epistemology: New essays (pp. 63–82). New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Goldman, A. I. (2009). Internalism, externalism, and the architecture of justification. Journal of Philosophy, 106, 309–338.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Goldman, A. I. (2011a). Reliabilism. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2011 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2011/entries/reliabilism/
- Goldman, A. I. (2011b). Toward a synthesis of reliabilism and evidentialism? or: Evidentialism’s troubles, reliabilism’s rescue package. In T. Dougherty (Ed.), Evidentialism and its discontents (pp. 393–426). New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
- Greco, J. (2000). Putting skeptics in their place: The nature of skeptical arguments and their role in philosophical inquiry. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Greco, J. (2005). Justification is not internal. In M. Steup & E. Sosa (Eds.), Contemporary debates in epistemology (pp. 257–270). Malden: Blackwell.Google Scholar
- Greco, J. (2010). Achieving knowledge. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Greco, J. (2011). Evidentialism about knowledge. In T. Dougherty (Ed.), Evidentialism and its discontents (pp. 167–178). New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Haack, S. (1993). Evidence and inquiry. Oxford: Blackwell.Google Scholar
- Harman, G. (1973). Thought. Princeton: Princeton University Press.Google Scholar
- Henderson, D. K., & Horgan, T. (2011). The epistemological spectrum: At the interface of cognitive science and conceptual analysis. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Huemer, M. (2007). Weak Bayesian coherentism. Synthese, 157, 337–346.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Huemer, M. (2011). Does probability theory refute coherentism? Journal of Philosophy, 108, 35–54.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Klein, P. (1999). Human knowledge and the infinite regress of reasons. Philosophical Perspectives, 13, 297–325.Google Scholar
- Klein, P. (2005). Infinitism is the solution to the epistemic regress problem. In M. Steup & E. Sosa (Eds.), Contemporary debates in epistemology (pp. 131–140). Malden: Blackwell.Google Scholar
- Klein, P. (2007). Human knowledge and the infinite progress of reasoning. Philosophical Studies, 134, 1–17.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Klein, P. (2014a). Infinitism. In S. Bernecker & D. Pritchard (Eds.), The Routledge companion to epistemology (pp. 245–256). New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
- Klein, P. (2014b). No end in sight. In R. Neta (Ed.), Current controversies in epistemology (pp. 95–115). New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
- Kornblith, H. (1989). The unattainability of coherence. In J. W. Bender (Ed.), The current state of the coherence theory: Critical essays on the epistemic theories of Keith Lehrer and Laurence BonJour, with replies (pp. 207–214). Dordrecht: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Kripke, S. (1972). Naming and necessity. Oxford: Blackwell.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Kvanvig, J. (1992). The intellectual virtues and the life of the mind: On the place of the virtues in contemporary epistemology. Savage: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
- Kvanvig, J. (2012). Coherentism and justified inconsistent beliefs: A solution. Southern Journal of Philosophy, 50, 21–41.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Kvanvig, J. (2014). Epistemic justification. In S. Bernecker & D. Pritchard (Eds.), The Routledge companion to epistemology (pp. 25–36). New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
- Lau, J. & Deutsch, M. (2014). Externalism about mental content. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Summer 2014 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/sum2014/entries/content-externalism/
- Lehrer, K. (1974). Knowledge. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
- Lehrer, K. (2000). Theory of knowledge (2nd ed.). Boulder: Westview Press.Google Scholar
- Lehrer, K., & Cohen, S. (1983). Justification, truth, and coherence. Synthese, 55, 191–207.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Lewis, C. I. (1946). An analysis of knowledge and valuation. LaSalle: Open Court.Google Scholar
- Littlejohn, C. (2009). The new evil demon problem. Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://www.iep.utm.edu/evil-new/#SH2a
- Locke, J. (1690/1975). An essay concerning human understanding. Oxford: Clarendon Press.Google Scholar
- Lycan, W. G. (1988). Judgement and justification. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
- Lycan, W. G. (2012). Explanationist rebuttals (coherentism defended again). Southern Journal of Philosophy, 50, 5–20.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Lyons, J. (2009). Perception and basic beliefs: Zombies, modules, and the problem of the external world. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Maffie, J. (1990). Recent work on naturalizing epistemology. American Philosophical Quarterly, 27, 281–293.Google Scholar
- Matheson, J. (2015). Is there a well-founded solution to the generality problem? Philosophical Studies, 172, 459–468.Google Scholar
- McCain, K. (2014). Evidentialism and epistemic justification. New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
- McCain, K. (2015a). A new evil demon? No problem for moderate internalists. Acta Analytica, 30, 97–105.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- McCain, K. (2015b). Is forgotten evidence a problem for evidentialism? Southern Journal of Philosophy, 53, 471–480.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- McCain, K. (2015c). No knowledge without evidence. Journal of Philosophical Research, 40, 369–376.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- McGrew, T. (1995). The foundations of knowledge. Lanham: Littlefield Adams Books.Google Scholar
- Montmarquet, J. (1993). Epistemic virtue and doxastic responsibility. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
- Moon, A. (2012a). Knowing without evidence. Mind, 121, 309–331.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Moon, A. (2012b). Three forms of internalism and the new evil demon problem. Episteme, 9, 345–360.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Moser, P. K. (1989). Knowledge and evidence. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
- Neurath, O. (1932). Protokollsätze. Erkenntnis, 3, 204–214.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Nozick, R. (1981). Philosophical explanations. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.Google Scholar
- Olsson, E. (2005). Against coherence: Truth, probability, and justification. Oxford: Clarendon Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Olsson, E. (2014a). Coherentism. In S. Bernecker & D. Pritchard (Eds.), The Routledge companion to epistemology (pp. 257–267). New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
- Olsson, E. (2014b). Coherentist theories of epistemic justification. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2014 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/justep-coherence/
- Olsson, E., & Schubert, S. (2007). Reliability conducive measures of coherence. Synthese, 157, 297–308.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Plantinga, A. (1993a). Warrant and proper function. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Plantinga, A. (1993b). Warrant: The current debate. New York: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Pollock, J. (1984). Reliability and justified belief. Canadian Journal of Philosophy, 14, 103–114.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Pollock, J. (1986). Contemporary theories of knowledge. Totowa: Rowman & Littlefield.Google Scholar
- Post, J. (1980). Infinite regress of justification and of explanation. Philosophical Studies, 38, 32–37.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Poston, T. (2008). Internalism and externalism in epistemology. Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://www.iep.utm.edu/int-ext/
- Poston, T. (2014). Reason & explanation: A defense of explanatory coherentism. New York: Palgrave-MacMillan.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Pritchard, D. (2005). Epistemic luck. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Pritchard, D. (2010). Knowledge and understanding. In D. Pritchard, A. Millar, & A. Haddock (Eds.), The nature and value of knowledge: Three investigations (pp. 5–88). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Pryor, J. (2001). Highlights of recent epistemology. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 52, 95–124.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Putnam, H. (1975). Philosophical papers, vol. 2: Mind, language, and reality. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Quine, W. V. O., & Ullian, J. S. (1970). The web of belief. New York: Random House.Google Scholar
- Rescher, N. (1973). The coherence theory of truth. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
- Roush, S. (2005). Tracking truth: Knowledge, evidence, and science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Russell, B. (1912a). The problems of philosophy. London: Williams and Norgate.Google Scholar
- Russell, B. (1912b/2001). Truth and falsehood. In M. P. Lynch (Ed.), The nature of truth: Classic and contemporary perspectives (pp. 17–24). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
- Schupbach, J. N. (2008). On the alleged impossibility of Bayesian coherentism. Philosophical Studies, 141, 323–331.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Sellars, W. (1956). Empiricism and the philosophy of mind. Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 1, 239–252.Google Scholar
- Smithies, D. (2014). Can foundationalism solve the regress problem? In R. Neta (Ed.), Current controversies in epistemology (pp. 73–94). New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
- Sosa, E. (1980). The raft and the pyramid. Midwest Studies in Philosophy, 5, 3–25.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Sosa, E. (1991). Knowledge in perspective. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Sosa, E. (2007). A virtue epistemology: Apt belief and reflective knowledge (Vol. I). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Sosa, E. (2009). Reflective knowledge: Apt belief and reflective knowledge (Vol. I). Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Sosa, E. (2011). Knowing full well. Princeton: Princeton University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Steup, M. (1996). An introduction to contemporary epistemology. Upper Saddle River: Prentice Hall.Google Scholar
- Thagard, P. (2000). Coherence in thought and action. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.Google Scholar
- Thagard, P. (2005). Testimony, credibility, and explanatory coherence. Erkenntnis, 63, 295–316.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Toulmin, S. E. (2003). The uses of argument. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Turri, J. (2014). Epistemology: A guide. Malden: Wiley Blackwell.Google Scholar
- Vahid, H. (2014). Externalism/internalism. In S. Bernecker & D. Pritchard (Eds.), The Routledge companion to epistemology (pp. 144–155). New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
- Vogel, J. (2000). Reliabilism leveled. Journal of Philosophy, 97, 602–623.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Wedgwood, R. (2002). Internalism explained. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 65, 349–369.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Williamson, T. (2000). Knowledge and its limits. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
- Zagzebski, L. (1996). Virtues of the mind: An inquiry into the nature of virtue and the ethical foundations of knowledge. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar