Skip to main content

Knowledge in a Scientific Community

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Nature of Scientific Knowledge

Part of the book series: Springer Undergraduate Texts in Philosophy ((SUTP))

  • 165k Accesses

Abstract

In earlier chapters various social aspects of scientific knowledge have been explored. These have been aspects which allow for social evidence to provide scientific knowledge to an individual. The focus in this chapter, however, moves beyond the study of individualistic characteristics of scientific knowledge by looking at science itself as an epistemic system. The thoroughgoing social nature of science leads to some characteristics which make it an epistemic system particularly well suited for adding to the store of scientific knowledge. In particular, the social nature of science leads to a division of cognitive labor. This division of cognitive labor both makes it so that trust plays an integral role in the generation of scientific knowledge and so that scientific progress is enhanced by the scientific community hedging its bets by scientists pursuing a wide variety of research projects utilizing a variety of methods. Although the individual scientists who make up the scientific community are not perfect, various social institutions in science help to make good use of their baser motivations.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 39.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 54.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    See Durkheim (1893/1997), Hume (1739–1740/1978), and Smith (1776/1904).

  2. 2.

    See Goldman (1999, 2001), Hardwig (1985), Hull (1988), Kitcher (1993), Longino (2013), and Shapin (1994) for considerations in support of thinking that trust is integral to science.

  3. 3.

    See Cohen et al. (1982) and Fuchs et al. (1997).

  4. 4.

    Thagard (1993) claims that it should be somewhat unsurprising that group rationality and individual rationality diverge in science. He points out that such divergences have long been recognized in decision theory in situations such as the “prisoners’ dilemma” and the “tragedy of the commons”.

  5. 5.

    It is worth noting that this situation does assume that scientists do not have perfect knowledge of what every other scientist is doing. If each individual scientist had this knowledge and was altruistic, then some might rationally accept the lower chances of their making the discovery by pursing Project 2 for the greater good of the community. However, the assumptions that scientists do not have perfect knowledge of what each other is doing and that they are not perfectly altruistic are exceedingly plausible.

  6. 6.

    See, for example, Brock and Durlaf (1999), Goldman (1999), Goldman and Shaked (1991), Hagstrom (1965), Hull (1988), Kitcher (1993), Latour and Woolgar (1979), Merton (1973), Rescher (1990), and Strevens (2003). For criticisms of economic models of science see Hands (1995, 1997), Muldoon (2013), Muldoon and Weisberg (2011), Weisberg and Muldoon (2009), and Wray (2000). There are other ways of modeling science such as Thagard’s (1993) distributed A.I. approach, the ecological model, which Muldoon and Weisberg (2011) and Weisberg and Muldoon (2009) draw from “hill climbing” models in computer science, and various consensus models such as those put forward by Hegselman and Kraus (2006), Lehrer (1975), Lehrer and Wagner (1981), Wagner (1985), and Zollman (2010). Although these other models are interesting and worthy of careful consideration, we will limit our focus to the economic approach. The reason for this is twofold. First, such models are by far the most widely accepted approaches to modeling science and its distribution of cognitive labor. Second, the other primary ways of modeling science and the distribution of cognitive labor seem to agree with the economic models on the crucial points that hedging its bets is the best way for science to proceed. They also agree with economic models that there are social structures in place which help ensure that science has a diversity of cognitive labor.

  7. 7.

    Also see Hull (1988), Solomon (1992), and Thagard (1988).

  8. 8.

    There are, of course, a number of such social institutions present in science. We will limit our focus here to just one of the most prominent ones because doing so is sufficient for our current illustrative purposes.

  9. 9.

    Strevens (2003) suggests that the priority rule is perhaps simply a clear representation of a much more general reward scheme which we find in society as a whole. Namely, a reward scheme that rewards in proportion to the benefit provided to society as a whole. The priority rule exemplifies this rule because when it comes to scientific discovery only the first to make the discovery provides a benefit to society, so only the first to make a discovery gets rewarded.

  10. 10.

    For example see Merton’s (1973, 1988) discussion of the “Matthew effect” where more well-known scientists receive more credit than less well-known scientists do for the same achievements. The Matthew effect is a social institution in science which many believe is a misallocation of credit, and so, a negative side effect of credit-based motivational structures in science. Though see Strevens (2006) for persuasive arguments for thinking that the Matthew effect does in fact distribute credit fairly.

References

  • Adler, J. (2014). Epistemological problems of testimony. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2014 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/testimony-episprob/

  • Brock, B., & Durlaf, S. (1999). A formal model of theory choice in science. Economic Theory, 14, 113–130.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cohen, P. A., Kulik, J. A., & Kulik, C. C. (1982). Educational outcomes of tutoring: A meta-analysis of findings. American Educational Research Journal, 19, 237–248.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Durkheim, E. (1893/1997). The division of labor in society. New York: The Free Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fricker, E. (1994). Against gullibility. In B. K. Matilal & A. Chakrabarti (Eds.), Knowing from words (pp. 125–161). Dordrecht: Kluwer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Fuchs, D., Fuchs, L. S., Mathes, P. G., & Simmons, D. C. (1997). Peer-assisted learning strategies: Making classrooms more responsive to diversity. American Educational Research Journal, 34, 174–206.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Gleick, J. (2004). Isaac Newton. New York: Vintage Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. (1999). Knowledge in a social world. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. (2001). Experts: Which ones should you trust? Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 63, 85–110.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I. (2011). A guide to social epistemology. In A. Goldman & D. Whitcomb (Eds.), Social epistemology: Essential readings (pp. 11–37). New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldman, A. I., & Shaked, M. (1991). An economic model of scientific activity and truth acquisition. Philosophical Studies, 63, 31–55.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hagstrom, W. (1965). The scientific community. New York: Basic Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hands, D. W. (1995). Social epistemology meets the invisible hand: Kitcher on the advancement of science. Dialogue, 34, 605–621.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hands, D. W. (1997). Caveat emptor: Economics and contemporary philosophy of science. Philosophy of Science, 64, 107–116.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hardwig, J. (1985). Epistemic dependence. Journal of Philosophy, 82, 335–349.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hegselmann, R. & Krause, U. (2006). Truth and cognitive division of labour: First steps towards a computer aided social epistemology. Journal of Artificial Societies and Social Stimulation, 9. http://jasss.soc.surrey.ac.uk/9/3/10.html

  • Hull, D. (1988). Science as a process. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Hume, D. (1739–1740/1978). A treatise of human nature. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keil, F. C. (2006). Doubt, deference, and deliberation: Understanding and using the division of cognitive labor. In T. Z. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Oxford studies in epistemology: Volume 1 (pp. 143–166). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Keil, F. C., Stein, C., Webb, L., Billings, V. D., & Rozenblit, L. (2008). Discerning the division of cognitive labor: An emerging understanding of how knowledge is clustered in other minds. Cognitive Science, 32, 259–300.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kitcher, P. (1993). The advancement of science: Science without legend, objectivity without illusions. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kuhn, T. S. (1977). The essential tension: Selected studies in scientific tradition and change. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Latour, B., & Woolgar, S. (1979). Laboratory life: The social construction of scientific facts. Beverly Hills: Sage.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lehrer, K. (1975). Social consensus and rational agnoiology. Synthese, 31, 141–160.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Lehrer, K., & Wagner, C. (1981). Rational consensus in science and society. Dordrecht: Reidel.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Longino, H. (2013). The social dimensions of scientific knowledge. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2013 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2013/entries/scientific-knowledge-social/

  • Lutz, D. J., & Keil, F. C. (2002). Early understanding of the division of cognitive labor. Child Development, 73, 1073–1084.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Merton, R. (1973). The sociology of science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Merton, R. (1988). The Matthew effect in science, II: Cumulative advantage and the symbolism of intellectual property. Isis, 79, 607–623.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Muldoon, R. (2013). Diversity of the division of cognitive labor. Philosophy Compass, 8, 117–125.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Muldoon, R., & Weisberg, M. (2011). Robustness and idealization in models of cognitive labor. Synthese, 183, 161–174.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Rescher, N. (1990). Cognitive economy: The economic dimension of the theory of knowledge. Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sarkar, H. (1983). A theory of method. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shapin, S. (1994). A social history of truth: Civility and science in seventeenth-century England. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shatz, D. (2004). Peer review: A critical inquiry. Lanham: Rowman & Littlefield.

    Google Scholar 

  • Smith, A. (1776/1904). An inquiry into the nature and causes of the wealth of nations (5th ed.). London: Methuen & Co.

    Google Scholar 

  • Solomon, M. (1992). Scientific rationality and human reasoning. Philosophy of Science, 59, 439–455.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. (2003). The role of the priority rule in science. Journal of Philosophy, 100, 55–79.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. (2006). The role of the Matthew effect in science. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 37, 159–170.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. (2010). Reconsidering authority: Scientific expertise, bounded rationality, and epistemic backtracking. In T. Z. Gendler & J. Hawthorne (Eds.), Oxford studies in epistemology: Volume 3 (pp. 294–330). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. (1988). Computational philosophy of science. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Thagard, P. (1993). Societies of minds: Science as distributed computing. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 24, 49–67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wagner, C. (1985). On the formal properties weighted averaging as a method of aggregation. Synthese, 25, 233–240.

    Google Scholar 

  • Weisberg, M., & Muldoon, R. (2009). Epistemic landscapes and the division of cognitive labor. Philosophy of Science, 76, 225–252.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Wray, K. B. (2000). Invisible hands and the success of science. Philosophy of Science, 67, 163–175.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Zollman, K. J. S. (2010). The epistemic benefit of transient diversity. Erkenntnis, 72, 17–35.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

McCain, K. (2016). Knowledge in a Scientific Community. In: The Nature of Scientific Knowledge. Springer Undergraduate Texts in Philosophy. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-33405-9_16

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics