The Nature of Scientific Knowledge pp 219-234 | Cite as
Anti-realism About Science
- 166k Downloads
Abstract
This chapter discusses one of the major debates in philosophy of science related to scientific knowledge, the debate between realists and anti-realists. Realists maintain that our best-confirmed scientific theories are true (or at least approximately true), but anti-realists think we should only accept that our best-confirmed scientific theories are useful in some sense without committing to their truth, approximate or otherwise. Some of the major arguments on both sides of this debate are evaluated in this chapter, though special attention is paid to the so-called “miracle argument” for scientific realism. Throughout the chapter a realist stance, which allows for genuine scientific knowledge, is defended. Ultimately, the chapter concludes that while anti-realist arguments are important and worth taking seriously, they do not pose an insurmountable threat to a realist conception of science. Such a conception holds that in the case of our best-confirmed theories the truth of those theories best explains their success, which gives us justification for believing that they are true.
Keywords
Good Explanation Scientific Theory Equivalent Theory Scientific Realism Empirical SuccessReferences
- Barnes, E. C. (2008). The paradox of predictivism. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Bird, A. (2007). Nature’s metaphysics: Laws and properties. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Boyd, R. (1983). On the current status of the issue of scientific realism. Erkenntnis, 19, 45–90.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Chakravartty, A. (1998). Semirealism. Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 29, 391–408.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Chakravartty, A. (2007). A metaphysics for scientific realism: Knowing the unobservable. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Chakravartty, A. (2008). What you don’t know can’t hurt you: Realism and the unconceived. Philosophical Studies, 137, 149–158.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Chakravartty, A. (2014). Scientific realism. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.), The Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy (Spring 2014 Edition). http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2014/entries/scientific-realism/
- Churchland, P. M. (1985). The ontological status of observables: In praise of the superempirical virtues. In P. Churchland & C. Hooker (Eds.), Images of science: Essays on realism and empiricism (pp. 35–47). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
- Dicken, P., & Lipton, P. (2006). What can Bas believe? Musgrave and van Fraassen on observability. Analysis, 66, 226–233.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Doppelt, G. (2007). Reconstructing scientific realism to rebut the pessimistic meta-induction. Philosophy of Science, 74, 96–118.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Gauch, H. G., Jr. (2012). Scientific method in brief. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Giere, R. N. (1988). Explaining science: A cognitive approach. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Giere, R. N. (2006). Scientific perspectivism. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Godfrey-Smith, P. (2008). Recurrent transient underdetermination and the glass half full. Philosophical Studies, 137, 141–148.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Harker, D. (2006). Accommodation and prediction: The case of the persistent head. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 57, 309–321.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Harker, D. (2008). On the predilections for predictions. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 59, 429–453.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Hitchcock, C., & Sober, E. (2004). Prediction versus accommodation and the risk of overfitting. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 55, 1–34.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Hoefer, C., & Rosenberg, A. (1994). Empirical equivalence, underdetermination, and systems of the world. Philosophy of Science, 61, 592–607.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Horwich, P. (1982). Probability and evidence. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
- Kitcher, P. (1993). The advancement of science: Science without legend, objectivity without illusions. New York: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
- Kornblith, H. (2013). Is philosophical knowledge possible? In D. E. Machuca (Ed.), Disagreement and skepticism (pp. 260–276). New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
- Kukla, A. (1993). Laudan, Leplin, empirical equivalence and underdetermination. Analysis, 53, 1–7.Google Scholar
- Kukla, A. (1996). Does every theory have empirically equivalent rivals? Erkenntnis, 44, 137–166.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Ladyman, J. (1998). What is structural realism? Studies in the History and Philosophy of Science, 29, 409–424.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Ladyman, J. (2011). Structural realism versus standard scientific realism: The case of phlogiston and dephlogisticated air. Synthese, 180, 87–101.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Lange, M. (2002). Baseball, pessimistic inductions and the turnover fallacy. Analysis, 62, 281–285.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Laudan, L. (1981). A confutation of convergent realism. Philosophy of Science, 48, 19–48.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Laudan, L. (1984). Science and values. Berkeley: University of California Press.Google Scholar
- Laudan, L., & Leplin, J. (1991). Empirical equivalence and underdetermination. Journal of Philosophy, 88, 449–472.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Leplin, J. (1997). A novel defense of scientific realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.Google Scholar
- Leplin, J., & Laudan, L. (1993). Determination underdeterred: Reply to Kukla. Analysis, 53, 8–16.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Lewis, P. (2001). Why the pessimistic induction is a fallacy. Synthese, 129, 371–380.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Lipton, P. (2004). Inference to the best explanation (2nd ed.). New York: Routledge.Google Scholar
- McCain, K. (2012). Inference to the best explanation and the external world: A defense of the explanationist response to skepticism. PhD dissertation, University of Rochester.Google Scholar
- McCain, K., & Poston, T. (2014). Why explanatoriness is evidentially relevant. Thought, 3, 145–153.Google Scholar
- McGrew, T. (2003). Confirmation, heuristics, and explanatory reasoning. British Journal for the Philosophy of Science, 54, 553–567.Google Scholar
- Mizrahi, M. (2013). The pessimistic induction: A bad argument gone too far. Synthese, 190, 3209–3226.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Musgrave, A. (1985). Constructive empiricism and realism. In P. Churchland & C. Hooker (Eds.), Images of science: Essays on realism and empiricism (pp. 197–221). Chicago: University of Chicago Press.Google Scholar
- Musgrave, A. (1988). The ultimate argument for scientific realism. In R. Nola (Ed.), Relativism and realism in science (pp. 229–252). Dordrecht: Kluwer.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Okasha, S. (2000). Van Fraassen's critique of inference to the best explanation. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science, 31, 691–710.Google Scholar
- Poincaré, H. (1905/1952). Science and hypothesis. New York: Dover.Google Scholar
- Psillos, S. (1996). On van Fraassen’s critique of abductive reasoning. Philosophical Quarterly, 46, 31–47.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Psillos, S. (1999). Scientific realism: How science tracks truth. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
- Putnam, H. (1975). Philosophical papers, vol. 1: Mathematics, matter and method. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.Google Scholar
- Putnam, H. (1978). Meaning and the moral sciences. London: Routledge.Google Scholar
- Saatsi, J. T. (2005). On the pessimistic induction and two fallacies. Philosophy of Science, 72, 1088–1098.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Schlesinger, G. (1987). Accommodation and prediction. Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 65, 33–42.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Smart, J. J. C. (1963). Philosophy and scientific realism. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.Google Scholar
- Stanford, P. K. (2006). Exceeding our grasp: Science, history, and the problem of unconceived alternatives. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- van Fraassen, B. C. (1980). The scientific image. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- van Fraassen, B. C. (1989). Laws and symmetry. Oxford: Oxford University Press.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Weisberg, J. (2009). Locating IBE in the Bayesian framework. Synthese, 167, 125–143.Google Scholar
- White, R. (2003). The epistemic advantage of prediction over accommodation. Mind, 112, 653–683.CrossRefGoogle Scholar
- Worrall, J. (1989). Structural realism: The best of both worlds? Dialectica, 43, 99–124.CrossRefGoogle Scholar