Skip to main content

Deconstructive Ethics—Handling Human Plurality (Shaped) by Normative (Enabling) Conditions

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Order Ethics: An Ethical Framework for the Social Market Economy

Abstract

On the following pages, I present a programmatic proposal for an ethical model that sets out by analysing norms—that is, it does not start with a certain idea of what human beings ‘are’ or ‘must be’ in order to ground normativity . That means to presuppose no kind of reasoning grounded in any so-called autonomous subject, nor in any other kind of prescribed determinations of, or properties belonging to, human lives. Starting with a formal analysis of norms and with their categorization rather than with grounding norms at first might provide an answer to severe objections against the basis of European enlightened ethics.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 84.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 109.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    There are different possibilities to distinguish ethical models: One contemporary pattern is to draw a distinction between normative, descriptive, and meta-ethics, or between applied and grounding ethics. A third could be to distinguish ethics from theories concerning the social which have a strong ethical impetus, but refuse to provide an explicit ethical model, at least a model which has systematic features—let’s call them ethical non-ethics or positively: deconstructive ethics. Calling them non-ethics indicates the prevailing refusal of their representatives to theorize systematically their mostly extensive ethical considerations. Thus their theoretical status is a bit strange, insofar as they describe in a critical way how ethics and norms work—this is the deconstructive side—but without stating explicitly what theoretical basis legitimates such a critique. Therefore they are subject to a lot of accusations from theorists who find themselves very well legitimated due to their last foundation in e.g. Aristotle, Kant or God, to name but a few. This is true for Habermas’ discourse ethics which is based on a very strict (western) idea of reason and the ability to take part in rational negotiations. It is also true for Martha Nussbaum’s enabling ethics grounded above all in Aristotle. Although the traditions that I refer to as deconstructive ethics see themselves in the tradition of European Enlightenment, they try to avoid some of the aporias introduced by the dialectics of Enlightenment: moral rationality in its modern formation and hence modern morality was not able to avert ‘Auschwitz’ and other genocides during the 20th century. More than that, it was neither able to avert a lot of other iniquities such as colonization or two world wars. Furthermore, there are a lot of voices which do not only wonder about its power to avert horrible developments, but ask to what extent this concept of rationality is also the ultimate cause of such developments. Although the following theorists argue from very different standpoints—though they are all but one voice—see e.g. Spivak (1988), Spivak (2004), Žižek (1994). See also Adorno and Horkheimer (1943/1996), Sartre (1983/1992), Luhmann (1990), Butler (2003/2005), etc.

  2. 2.

    Kant, Sartre, Levinas, or Jean-Luc Nancy, to name but a few, presuppose plurality without giving a reason for its provenance. Hegel prominently answered this question by stating a consciousness which differentiates (and connects at once) by negating (and synthesizing). He is followed by a wide range of theorists which could be subsumed under the label: philosophers of difference. My suggestion here is not to take one of these alternatives but to claim that norms are the differentiating power.

  3. 3.

    The double effect of distinguishing and connecting at once refers, of course, to Hegel and also to G. Spencer Brown’s Laws of Form. The first chapter starts with the definition: “Distinction is perfect continence”. LoF:1.

  4. 4.

    The difference between necessary and sufficient conditions is a very crucial point which will come up again in different contexts: a necessary condition designates what is necessary in order to make something happen; it determines the event in no way; a sufficient condition determines what happens in any case—therefore the difference should not be ignored.

  5. 5.

    Judith Butler distinguishes “necessary and variable norms”. I think this naming is misleading, because it could imply that necessary norms are not variable, which is not the case. See Butler (2002, here: 205–207).

  6. 6.

    The philosophical discourse which is relevant here refers to Lacan and his difference between the ‘symbolic real’ and ‘reality’. Whereas the latter never pervades perfectly in the formatting normative ‘symbolic real’, the ‘symbolic real’ always refers to something more, superfluous, excluded, which becomes visible only with regard to the symbolic and which is therefore somehow produced, or at least defined by it. Thus the ‘symbolic real’ would stand for the normalized which is shaped out of ‘reality’ and which can be thought and seen only through the symbolic. See Lacan (1955/1973).

  7. 7.

    It is crucial to distinguish between prohibitions and commandments: While the first just describe one action which is not allowed and thus leave all the remaining possible actions untouched, the latter describe an action positively. A prohibition is therefore just a negative determination which excludes just one concrete action but does not determine any other action. A commandment, on the other hand, determines the action positively. It is interesting to see that the Bible offers in the Decalogue—after the first three commandments which refer directly to interactions with God—only one further commandment: the fourth, which is about honoring father and mother in order to allow you to live longer (!) on the arable soil given to you by Him (after the translation of Buber/Rosenberg). So it is a kind of conjunction between the first three and the rest. The other six only formulate prohibitions—so that the social is far away from being positively determined by the Decalogue. It is just limited insofar as some actions are excluded—to make social life possible. Of course, they refer to the very condition of life—not to be killed—and to property. But this is another topic.

  8. 8.

    See Butler (2005, especially 65–81). In her description, she refers to Emmanuel Levinas and to psychoanalysis.

  9. 9.

    I have Michel Foucault’s and Niklas Luhmann’s analysis in mind. Both argue that organizations, i.e. every kind of organized plurality, work through exclusionary functions. See Foucault (1972), Luhmann (2000).

  10. 10.

    This formulation is reminiscent of Kant’s and Isaiah Berlin’s distinction between positive and negative freedom: the latter means to be free of pain, determinations etc.; the former means to be free to live one’s life as one wants to. See Kant (1795).

  11. 11.

    I would suggest to interpret the Kantian categorical imperative as two-tiered as well: The ‘subjective maxims’ are the rules orienting singular actions and behaviors on the level of singularities. The test if these ‘subjective maxims’ can serve as an ‘objective right’ should be taken literally: check whether your personal rules could be formulated as a right, one might say as a condition, which does not limit the possibilities of others—in the sense of the basic Right.

    We can find this idea of a necessary two-tier model also in Dewey (1915, 1935/1999).

  12. 12.

    Most norms receive their legitimization ex post as well, as they only become explicit in the moment of severe social transformations, and thus in times of uncertainty and angst. See Brandom (1998).

References

  • Adorno, Theodor W., Horkheimer, Max. 1943/1996. Dialectic of enlightenment. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Brandom, Robert. 1998. Making it explicit. Reasoning, representing and discoursive commitment. Boston: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Butler, Judith. 2002. The question of social transformation. In Undoing gender, ed. idem (2004), 204–231. NY/London: Routledge.

    Google Scholar 

  • Butler, Judith. 2003/2005. Giving an account of oneself. NY: Fordham University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Butler, Judith. 2005. Giving an account of oneself. NY: Fordham Univ. Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Butler, Judith. 2009. Introduction. In: idem (2009). Frames of war. When is life grieveable. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, John. 1915. German philosophy and German politics.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dewey, John. 1935/1999. Liberalism and social action. Prometheus Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, Michel. 1972. L’ordre du discours. Paris: Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, Michel. 1984. ‘L’éthique de souci de soi comme pratique de la liberté’ in: idem. (2001). Dits et Ecrits. tome 2. 1976–1988, no 356. Paris: Gallimard.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foucault, Michel. 1994. The order of things. Vintage Books edition, Copyright © 1970 by Random House, Inc.

    Google Scholar 

  • Habermas, Jürgen. 2011. “The political”: The rational meaning of a questionable inheritance of political theology. In The power of religion in the public sphere, ed. Judith Butler, Jürgen Habermas, Charles Taylor, Cornel West, 15–34. NY: Columbia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1795. Groundwork for an Ethics, Third Part. In Liberty: Incorporating four essays on liberty, ed. Isaiah Berlin (1969/2002). Oxford: OU Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1797. Metaphysics of morals. AA 6:230.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lacan, Jacques. 1955/1973. Seminar on ‘The Purloined Letter’ from Écrits’. Yale French Studies 48:39–72 (translated by Jeffrey Mehlmann).

    Google Scholar 

  • Luhmann, Niklas. 1990. Paradigm Lost. Über die ethische Reflexion der Moral. Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Luhmann, Niklas. 2000. Organisation und Entscheidung. Opladen/Wiesbaden: Westdeutscher Verlag.

    Google Scholar 

  • Mayer, Hans 1975/2007. Aussenseiter. Frankfur/Main: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Menke, Christoph. 2009. Das Nichtanerkennbare. Oder warum das modern Recht keine »Sphäre der Anerkennung« ist. In Sozialphilosophie und Kritik, ed. Rainer Forst et al., 87–108. Frankfurt/Main: Suhrkamp.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sartre, Jean-Paul. 1983/1992. Notebooks for an ethics. Chicago: UC Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spivak, Gayatri C. 1988. ‘Can the subaltern speak?’ In Colonial discourse and post-colonial theory: A reader, ed. Patrick Williams, Laura Chrisman (1994), 66–111. New York: Harvester/Wheatsheaf.

    Google Scholar 

  • Spivak, Gayatri C. 2004. ‘Righting wrongs’. The South Atlantic Quaterly 103:2/3.

    Google Scholar 

  • Watzlawick, Paul. 1999/2011. Pragmatics of human communication. W. W. Norton & Company.

    Google Scholar 

  • Žižek, Slavoj. 1994. ‘Introduction’. In Mapping ideology, ed. idem (1994), 1–33. London: Verso.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

I would like to thank Hans G. Ulrich and Stephan Packard for their critical comments, helping to clear up this paper; and especially Stephan Packard for his judicious re-reading of my English. The work on this paper was possible due to a generous Heisenberg-grant sponsored by the German Research Foundation (SCHO 1077/3-1).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Tatjana Schönwälder-Kuntze .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Schönwälder-Kuntze, T. (2016). Deconstructive Ethics—Handling Human Plurality (Shaped) by Normative (Enabling) Conditions. In: Luetge, C., Mukerji, N. (eds) Order Ethics: An Ethical Framework for the Social Market Economy . Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-33151-5_12

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics