Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Law and Philosophy Library ((LAPS,volume 116))

  • 448 Accesses

Abstract

Andrei Marmor’s reading of Kelsen in his book Philosophy of Law (2011) exemplifies American and Anglophone interpretations, which see Kelsen as failing to consistently offer a pure theory of law. I argue that Marmor misreads Kelsen in three ways, each of which makes it appear as if Kelsen reduced the law to social facts. First, Marmor wrongly marginalizes the doctrine of the unity of law in Kelsen’s legal theory, thereby making Kelsen look as if he thought multiple independent legal systems, each dependent upon a human community, exist. Second, Marmor misreads Kelsen’s doctrine of efficacy as the view that the existence of a legal system fundamentally depends upon the norms of the system being followed by a community’s members. Third, Marmor misunderstands the Neo-Kantian nature of Kelsen’s legal theory, attributing to Kelsen the very psychologism that he argued against. Once these three mistakes are corrected, we can understand Kelsen as having offered a genuinely pure theory of law. But the question remains whether we have a reason to accept the theory. I end by briefly discussing some evidence from the conflict of laws that suggests that jurists treat the law as not reducible to social facts.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 119.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    Alfred Verdross was another member, with Kelsen, of the “Vienna School” of legal theory. Fritz Sander, a former student of Kelsen’s, became one his most prominent critics.

  2. 2.

    And to the extent that Kelsen offered insights that can be appreciated without accepting a pure theory of law, they assume that the same insights can be found, more clearly presented, in H.L.A. Hart’s writings (Murphy and Coleman 1990: 27).

  3. 3.

    I describe positivists as believing that law is ultimately determined solely by social facts, because inclusive legal positivists concede that social facts can make evaluative facts relevant to law’s existence and content. For exclusive legal positivists, by contrast, law always depends solely on social facts.

  4. 4.

    For an inclusive legal positivist, if evaluative facts disappeared, law that depends upon such facts could not exist (or its existence would be indeterminate). But there could still be law, for it is not necessary that law depends upon evaluative facts.

  5. 5.

    An example here is the “robust realist” and non-naturalist David Enoch, who believes that “there is no metaphysically possible world where the basic norms [of morality] are different.” (Enoch 2011: 146). It follows that the basic norms of morality were in place when dinosaurs roamed the earth.

  6. 6.

    An example is Enoch’s argument that robust realism about morality is supported by our willingness to “stand our ground” in cases of moral conflict, that is, to not arrive at an “impartial” resolution that seeks to accommodate the disputants’ actual preferences (Enoch 2011: 23–24).

  7. 7.

    This would mean treating Article VII as, in some sense, independent of the rest of the Constitution. It preceded the Constitution by providing the method for its enactment.

  8. 8.

    Granted, the positivist can accept that it was a conceptual truth even in the Jurassic Era that if the social facts that constitute the American legal system are in place, Article VII will be law. But he would deny that any legal facts existed in the Jurassic Era, in particular, that anyone was legally authorized to create Article VII. For the positivist, the existence of a legal authorization would require an actual human community.

  9. 9.

    The pure theorist of law is analogous to a robust moral realist like Enoch, who accepts that moral facts supervene upon natural facts, but who argues that this supervenience relation follows from moral principles that do not themselves depend upon natural facts (Enoch 2011: 140–50).

  10. 10.

    I will also occasionally refer to his article on the pure theory of law in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Marmor 2010), which overlaps substantially with his book.

  11. 11.

    The United States Constitution contains no provision authorizing the creation of state law. It presupposes state law’s existence. It does contain a provision (Art. IV, § 3) for the creation of new states, but it is not clear that this should be understood as the authorization of state law. And even if it is so understood, this authorization could not apply to the law of the thirteen original states.

  12. 12.

    The first constitution need not be written. Kelsen argued, for example, that the first constitution of international law is that the custom of states creates valid law. Furthermore, this constitution was itself created through custom (Kelsen 1960a: 226, 323).

  13. 13.

    Marmor argues that, for Kelsen, someone treating the law as valid thereby also treats the law as providing a practical reason for action, that is, “a justified demand on practical deliberation ” (Marmor 2011: 25). According to Marmor, Kelsen rejects sociological accounts of the law because of their inability to explain the reason-giving character of legal norms. Later in the chapter, Marmor argues that Kelsen should have distinguished between the question of the validity of law and its normativity (in the sense of its practical reason-giving character). In fact, it is unclear whether Kelsen believed that someone who recognizes a legal norm as valid thereby takes himself to have a reason for action in the sense relevant for practical deliberation (Paulson 2012; Delacroix 2004; Wilson 1982).

  14. 14.

    Although Kelsen described his philosophy of law as positivist (Kelsen 1960a: 217), he is not a positivist in the sense that I define it, for he does not think law is ultimately reducible solely to social facts about a community.

  15. 15.

    See also Kelsen 1934, 60 (“[A] normative system to which reality no longer corresponds to a certain degree will necessarily lose its validity. The validity of a legal system…depends in a certain way…on the efficacy of the system.”).

  16. 16.

    Marmor is not as careful as he could be in describing what efficacy is for Kelsen. The question is not merely whether those subject to the mandatory norms of the legal system generally comply with them but also whether relevant officials apply the norms of the system (Navarro 2013: 79 n.12). In Marmor’s defense, he might understand such application as officials “following” the norms, however.

  17. 17.

    Marmor quotes A General Theory of Law and State: “[A]n anarchist, for instance, who denied the validity of the hypothetical basic norm of positive law…will view its positive regulation of human relationships…as mere power relations.” (Kelsen 1945: 413). It is worth noting that Kelsen later explicitly rejected this reading of the anarchist. He concluded that the anarchist, despite rejecting the law politically, could still presuppose the basic norm and therefore understand it as a system of valid norms (Kelsen 1960a: 218 n.82). This is a reason to conclude that Kelsen did not think that someone who treats the law as valid thereby also treats it as providing practical reasons for action. See note 13 above.

  18. 18.

    Monism as described here is different from a homonymous term used by international lawyers. If a nation’s law is monist in this other sense, international law has a direct effect upon the legal rights and obligations of individuals under national law (Waters 2007; 641). A citizen may, for example, successfully challenge the validity of a statute on the grounds that it is contrary to a treaty entered into by the nation. If a nation’s law is dualist, by contrast, such a challenge cannot succeed, unless there is a particular national law that has given the treaty such an effect. In the absence of such a law, the statute is binding on the individual, even though the nation might recognize the treaty’s validity as a matter of international law—for example, by acknowledging that the statute’s conflict with the treaty makes sanctions against it by other nations legally permissible. Thus, it is sometimes said that under dualism national and international law form two separate systems, with international law’s effect confined to the relationship between nations (Henkin 1987: 864).

    These positions are not the monism and pluralism described here. Monism, as Kelsen understands it, is compatible with legal phenomena that are described by international lawyers as “dualist.” The fact that a treaty recognized by a nation provides individuals with no grounds to challenge the validity of a statute simply speaks to the legal relationship between those two types of law. It does not mean that international law and the domestic laws of each nation are not part of the same legal system.

    Likewise, pluralism is compatible with legal phenomena that are described by international lawyers as “monist.” Assume that under a nation’s law an individual can invoke a treaty against the validity of a statute. The pluralist can still insist that the international and the national legal systems are separate. Facts about the nation’s law, she can argue, are reducible to facts about the national community, whereas facts about international law are reducible to facts about an international community (the community of nations or officials of those nations, considered collectively). The individual arguing that the treaty invalidates the statute is making an argument under national law, not international law. Social facts about the national community are ultimately the reason that the statute’s conflict with the treaty makes it invalid. To be sure, the fact that the statute conflicts with the treaty is a matter of international law, determined by social facts about the international, not the national, community. But simply because a criterion for the validity of national law refers to international law does not mean that the national and international legal systems are one.

  19. 19.

    That the principle must be one of efficacy is questionable. Because the principle is itself a matter of positive law (Kelsen 1945: 121), there is no reason why it would have to have that particular content.

  20. 20.

    Kelsen’s view that monism did not entail the primacy of international law was the focus of a debate among Austrian legal scholars back in the 1920s (von Bernstorff 2010: 104–107).

  21. 21.

    Curiously, American subsystem law would also reappear within the unitary American legal system, because American law as a subsystem would also be recognized by international law.

  22. 22.

    A national monist might take the position that the law of no other nation is valid. But I doubt that Marmor would be inclined to find that position, under which only American law is valid, any more attractive.

  23. 23.

    A legal norm, Kelsen argues, “does not exist in space and time, for it is not a fact of nature” (Kelsen 1934: 12).

  24. 24.

    For example, Kelsen repeatedly speaks of the basic norm as transcendental-logical (Kelsen 1960a: 201–02, 218, 223, 226). Kelsen’s Neo-Kantian approach is even more explicit in passages from the German version of the second edition, omitted in the English translation, eg Kelsen 1960b: 208 n.**, where he explicitly draws an analogy between his method and Kant’s.

  25. 25.

    For Kelsen’s reliance on Cohen, see Paulson 1992, 2013; Green 2003: 389–402; Edel 1999.

  26. 26.

    A quietist might speak about the knowing subject creating her objects of knowledge as a means of foreclosing Platonist theories in which the objects of knowledge are given independent metaphysical status. For a discussion of how the quietist must walk a fine line between subjectivism on the one hand and metaphysical realism on the other, see Green 2003: 396–398, 2009: 367–368.

  27. 27.

    Paulson has argued that the first approach fails, on the ground that Kelsen has not shown that the basic norm is the only means of explaining what is presumed, namely cognition of objective legal norms (Paulson 1992, 2013: 55–57).

  28. 28.

    My argument supports the international rather than the national version of monism. Indeed, like a number of Kelsen’s Austrian critics in the 1920s—such as Alfred Verdross and Josef Kunz (von Bernstorff 2010: 105) —I find the national version of monism questionable. To the extent that one treats other national legal systems as having validity under principles of international law, I cannot see how one could not consider one’s own national legal system as fundamentally subject to those same principles.

  29. 29.

    The Court of Appeals reversed the trial court’s dismissal of a second cause of action, according to which the defendant failed to abide by a provision in the contract that stated that “in the event the plaintiff should die or become unable, without fault on his part, to serve during the period of the contract the defendants would pay to him or his heirs the sum of 120,000 marks, in discharge of their obligations, under the hiring aforesaid.”

  30. 30.

    When conflicts rules are understood as rules of scope, one must then confront the question of whether other jurisdictions ought to respect them. (This is commonly called the problem of renvoi or désistement.) If New York officials have said, through their conflicts rules, that the facts are beyond the scope of New York law, it would appear that other jurisdictions are not permitted to apply New York law to the facts. I argue, however, that this reasoning is mistaken at Green 2013: 869–884.

References

  • Ackerman, Bruce, and Neal Katyal. 1995. Our unconventional founding. University of Chicago Law Review 62: 475–573.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Delacroix, Sylvie. 2004. Hart’s and Kelsen’s concepts of normativity contrasted. Ratio Juris 17: 501–520.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, Ronald. 1986. Law’s empire. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dworkin, Ronald. 2006. Justice in robes. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Edel, Geert. 1999. The hypothesis of the basic norm: Hans Kelsen and Hermann Cohen. In Normativity and norms: Critical perspectives on Kelsenian themes, ed. Stanley L. Paulson and Bonnie L. Paulson, 195–220. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Enoch, David. 2011. Taking morality seriously: A defense of robust realism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Green, Michael Steven. 2003. Hans Kelsen and the logic of legal systems. Alabama Law Review 53: 365–413.

    Google Scholar 

  • Green, Michael Steven. 2009. Kelsen, quietism, and the rule of recognition. In The rule of recognition and the United States constitution, ed. Matthew D. Adler and Kenneth E. Himma, 351–378. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Green, Michael Steven. 2013. Law’s dark matter. William and Mary Law Review 54: 845–884.

    Google Scholar 

  • Greenberg, Mark. 2004. How facts make law. Legal Theory 10: 157–198.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Henkin, Louis. 1987. The constitution and United States sovereignty: A century of Chinese exclusion and its progeny. Harvard Law Review 100: 853–886.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Janik, Allan, and Stephen Toulmin. 1973. Wittgenstein’s Vienna. New York: Simon and Schuster.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelsen, Hans. 1920. Das Problem der Souveränität und die Theorie des Völkerrechts. Beitrag zu einer Reinen Rechtslehre. Tübingen: J.C.B. Mohr.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelsen, Hans. 1922. Der Soziologische und Juristische Staatsbegriff. Tübingen: J.C.B. Mohr.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelsen, Hans. 1926. Das Wesen des Staates. Revue Internationale de la Theorie du Droit 1: 5–17.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelsen, Hans. 1934. Introduction to the problems of legal theory. A translation of the first edition of the Reine Rechtslehre or pure theory of law. Trans. B.L. Paulson and S.L. Paulson, 1997. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelsen, Hans. 1945. General theory of law and state. Trans. A. Wedberg. Cambridge: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelsen, Hans. 1960a. Pure theory of law, 2nd edn. Trans. M. Knight 1967. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelsen, Hans. 1960b. Reine Rechtslehre: Mit einem Anhang: Das Problem der Gerechtigkeit. Tubingen: Mohr Siebeck.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelsen, Hans. 1999. Foreword to the second printing of the main problems in the theory of public law. In Normativity and norms: Critical perspectives on Kelsenian themes, ed. Stanley L. Paulson and Bonnie L. Paulson, 3–22. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kramer, Larry. 1991. Return of the renvoi. New York University Law Review 66: 979–1044.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marmor, Andrei. 2010. The pure theory of law. The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. http://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2010/entries/lawphil-theory. Accessed 22 Jan 2015.

  • Marmor, Andrei. 2011. Philosophy of law. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, Jeffrie G., and Jules L. Coleman. 1990. Philosophy of law: An introduction to jurisprudence. Boulder: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Navarro, Pablo E. 2013. The efficacy of constitutional norms. In Kelsen revisited: New essays on the pure theory of law, ed. Luis Duarte d’Almeida, Gardner John, and Green Leslie, 77–100. Oxford: Hart Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paulson, Stanley L. 1992. Introduction. In Introduction to the problems of legal theory. A translation of the first edition of the Reine Rechtslehre or pure theory of law. Trans. B.L. Paulson and S.L. Paulson, 1997. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paulson, Stanley L. 2012. A ‘justified normativity’ thesis in Hans Kelsen’s pure theory of law? Rejoinders to Robert Alexy and Joseph Raz. In Institutionalized reason: The jurisprudence of Robert Alexy, ed. Klatt Matthias, 61–111. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Paulson, Stanley L. 2013. The great puzzle: Kelsen’s basic norm. In Kelsen revisited: New essays on the pure theory of law, ed. Luis Duarte d’Almeida, John Gardner, and Leslie Green, 43–62. Oxford: Hart Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Roosevelt, Kermit. 2005. Resolving renvoi: The bewitchment of our intelligence by means of language. Notre Dame Law Review 80: 1821–1891.

    Google Scholar 

  • von Bernstorff, Jochen. 2010. The public international law theory of Hans Kelsen: Believing in universal law. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Waters, Melissa A. 2007. Creeping monism: The judicial trend toward interpretive incorporation of human rights treaties. Columbia Law Review 107: 628–705.

    Google Scholar 

  • Wilson, Alida. 1982. Joseph Raz on Kelsen’s basic norm. American Journal of Jurisprudence 27: 46–63.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgments

Thanks for helpful comments from the participants in the Kelsen in America Conference, organized by Jeremy Telman. Thanks for further aid to Brian Bix, David Enoch, Andrei Marmor, Stanley Paulson, and Lars Vinx

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Michael S. Green .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Green, M.S. (2016). Marmor’s Kelsen. In: Telman, D. (eds) Hans Kelsen in America - Selective Affinities and the Mysteries of Academic Influence. Law and Philosophy Library, vol 116. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-33130-0_3

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics