Skip to main content

Part of the book series: Law and Philosophy Library ((LAPS,volume 116))

Abstract

In American legal philosophy—even if one narrows one’s focus to careful consideration of the sub-category, American analytical legal philosophy—the ideas of Hans Kelsen are generally ignored. And on the rare occasions when Kelsen’s ideas are not ignored, they are almost always discussed quickly, and, more often than not, erroneously. Part I of this paper gives examples of Kelsen’s works being overlooked, sample misreadings by prominent theorists, and considers some standard explanations for this indifference and ignorance. Part II turns to some more subtle (and controversial) questions of correct and incorrect readings, focusing on Kelsen’s Basic Norm.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 119.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 159.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    I should note that at this conference Scott Shapiro expressed an intention to write about Kelsen at length in a forthcoming work on international law.

  2. 2.

    The “exclusive” entry in that text is by Andrei Marmor; the “inclusive” entry is by Kenneth Einar Himma.

  3. 3.

    Marmor offers a slight variation of Green’s too-quick dismissal: “Instead of telling us something about the foundations of the basic norm, Kelsen simply invites us to stop asking” (Marmor 2011: 146).

  4. 4.

    See, eg, (Kelsen 1992), (Paulson 1992a), (2012), (2013a).

  5. 5.

    See, eg, (Harris 1977) , (1986), (1996); see also (Paulson 2006).

  6. 6.

    See, eg, (Raz 1976) , (1980: 93–120), (1986). Raz’s reading of Kelsen is challenged in (Paulson 2012).

  7. 7.

    See, eg, (Kelsen 2013: 217).

  8. 8.

    This is the Stufenbaulehre that Kelsen adopted from Adolf Julius Merkl . See (Kelsen 1992: § 28, at 57), (Jakab 2007), (Paulson 2013b).

  9. 9.

    There is a common confusion in understanding both Kelsen’s “Basic Norm” and H. L. A. Hart’s analogous concept, the “rule of recognition” (Hart 2012: 94–95, 100–110). While there is an understandable temptation to equate these fundamental norms with foundational texts of a legal system (like the United States Constitution), this equation is at best imprecise. First, as Kelsen points out, the current foundational text may have been created under the authority of a prior foundational text of the same legal system, so the Basic Norm should refer to the historically first foundational text. Second, there remain questions of how to interpret the provisions of the foundational text, and to determine what priority it has in that legal system in relation to other national and international legal norms. Third, at least with the case of Kelsen’s Basic Norm , the norm is an instruction to act in accordance with a particular legal text, a prescription that is in principle separate from the legal text itself.

  10. 10.

    There are, of course, numerous responses in the philosophical and jurisprudential literature to this potential skeptical challenge.

  11. 11.

    Kelsen refers more commonly to “the science of law” (or “legal science”)—“Rechtswissenschaft.” The reference to “science” in Kelsen’s work, and in German generally, means objective academic inquiry, without necessarily implying all the extra baggage that the term “science” carries in English (such that one might comfortably refer to literary theory in German as a “science,” while it would be an unlikely, and certainly controversial, description in English) (Paulson 1992b: 127–129).

  12. 12.

    See also (Kelsen 1949: 116–117): “The basic norm is the answer to the question: how—and that means under what condition—are all these juristic statements concerning legal norms, legal duties, and so on, possible?”

  13. 13.

    I recognize that there may be other passages in Kelsen’s text that support a different reading. For a good overview of the different tenable readings of Kelsen’s writings on the Basic Norm, see (Paulson 2012).

  14. 14.

    In a later edition of the same text, he clarifies that an anarchist who was also a law professor “could describe positive law as a system of valid norms, without having to approve of this law” (Kelsen 1967: 218 n. 82). This idea corresponds with Joseph Raz’s idea of a detached normative statement, or statements from a legal point of view (Raz 2009: 156–157), and is fully consistent with the analysis offered in this article.

  15. 15.

    Kelesen writes:The problem that leads to the theory of the basic norm…is how to distinguish a legal command which is considered to be objectively valid, such as the command of a revenue officer to pay a certain sum of money, from a command which has the same subjective meaning but is not considered to be objectively valid, such as the command of a gangster (Kelsen 1965: 1144).

  16. 16.

    Later in the same passage, Kelsen adds, helpfully: “The concept of normative validity is, rather, an interpretation; it is an interpretation made possible only by the presupposition of a basic norm,” and that such an interpretation is well-grounded “if one presupposes the…basic norm.” (Kelsen 2013: 219 (emphasis in original)) .

  17. 17.

    The omitted text states: “[they] reject natural law as the basis of validity of positive law.…” (Kelsen 1992: §29, at 58). And once more: “This presupposition [of the Basic Norm] is possible but not necessary.…Thus the Pure Theory of Law, by ascertaining the basic norm as the logical condition under which a coercive order may be interpreted as valid positive law, furnishes only a conditional, not a categorical, foundation of the validity of positive law” (Kelsen 1960b: 276).

  18. 18.

    For Hart, “accepting” is accepting the legal system as giving reasons for action. As Michael Steven Green pointed out to me, it is probably too strong to see the normative reading of official action within Kelsen as similarly involving any view that the law gives reasons for action.

  19. 19.

    When one says that one can choose to view the (legal) actions of officials normatively or not, it is important to note that this does not mean that this “choice” is always or necessarily a conscious choice. The reference to “choice” indicates primarily that there is an option; one could do (or think) otherwise.

  20. 20.

    Foot also refers to morality’s purported “inescapability” in the course of her discussion questioning the view of morality as a categorical imperative (as opposed to hypothetical imperative) (Foot 1978: 160–164) ; cf. (Raz 1999: 94–105) , on whether reasons are optional.

  21. 21.

    Gardner here reflects the conventional position, though, of course, thinkers ranging from Philippa Foot to Friedrich Nietzsche have raised exactly the question Gardner’s quotation implies cannot or should not be raised: whether one should follow the dictates of morality. See (Foot 1978: 157–173) (on whether morality is merely a “hypothetical imperative”), (Foot 1978: 181–188) (questioning whether moral considerations are “overriding”), (Nietzsche 1998).

  22. 22.

    Robert Alexy points out similarly that “[o]ne can of course refuse … to participate in the (utterly real) game of law.” (Alexy 2002: 109).

  23. 23.

    Cf. (Schauer 2010) .

  24. 24.

    I am indebted to Frederick Schauer for this suggestion.

  25. 25.

    Cf. (Marmor 2007: 153–181), comparing law and chess.

  26. 26.

    See (Kant 1998). The particular way of phrasing the matter in the text above (eg, the reference to “sense data”) is likely not a way most Kantians would choose, but it should suffice for the rough summary needed here.

  27. 27.

    A comparable point could be made, as earlier mentioned, for a moral or theological normative system, or any other kind of normative system.

  28. 28.

    My reading of Kelsen is very close to J. W. Harris in (Harris 1996), though Harris—like Paulson—expressed concern that this Kelsenian view of legal normativity might leave the theory with limited practical significance.

  29. 29.

    As Paulson shows, indirectly, by his sharp critique of other readings (Paulson 2012).

References

  • Adams, David M. 2013. Philosophical problems in the law, 5th ed. Independence, KY: Cengage Wadsworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Alexy, Robert. 2002. The Argument from Injustice. Trans. B.L. Paulson and S.L. Paulson. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Arthur, John, and William H. Shaw. 2010. Readings in the philosophy of law, 5th ed. Upper Saddle River, NJ: Prentice Hall.

    Google Scholar 

  • Barzun, Jacques. 2000. From dawn to decadence: 500 years of western cultural life, 1500 to the present. New York: HarperCollins.

    Google Scholar 

  • Bix, Brian H. 2015. Rules and normativity in law. In Problems of normativity, rules and rule following, ed. Tomasz Gizbert-Studnicki, Krzysztof Płeszka, Michał Arszkiewicz, and Paweł Banas, 125–146. Dordrecht: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coleman, Jules. 2001. The practice of principle. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Coleman, Jules, and Scott Shapiro (eds.). 2002. The Oxford handbook of jurisprudence & philosophy of law. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Feinberg, Joel, Jules Coleman, and Christopher Kutz. 2014. Philosophy of law, 9th ed. Independence, KY: Cengage Wadsworth.

    Google Scholar 

  • Finnis, John. 2002. Natural law: The classical tradition. In The Oxford handbook of jurisprudence & philosophy of law, ed. Jules Coleman and Scott Shapiro, 1–60. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foot, Philippa. 1978. Virtues and vices. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gardner, John. 2012. Law as a leap of faith. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Green, Leslie. 2003. Legal positivism. In Stanford encyclopedia of philosophy, ed. E.N. Zalta. http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/legal-positivism/. Accessed 24 Nov 2014.

  • Harris, J.W. 1977. Kelsen’s concept of authority. Cambridge Law Journal 36: 353–363.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Harris, J.W. 1986. Kelsen and normative consistency. In Essays on Kelsen, ed. R. Tur and W. Twining, 201–228. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Harris, J.W. 1996. Kelsen’s pallid normativity. Ratio Juris 9: 94–117.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hart, H.L.A. 2012. The concept of law, 3rd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Himma, Kenneth Einar. 2002. Inclusive legal positivism. In The Oxford handbook of jurisprudence & philosophy of law, ed. Jules Coleman and Scott Shapiro, 125–165. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hume, David. 1978. A treatise of human nature. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jakab, András. 2007. Problems of the stufenbaulehre: Kelsen’s failure to derive the validity of a norm from another norm. Canadian Journal of Law and Jurisprudence 20: 35–67.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kant, Immanuel. 1998. In Critique of pure reason, ed. P. Guyer and A. Woods. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Kelsen, Hans. 1949. General theory of law & state. Cambridge, MA.: Harvard University Press. (Transaction Publisher Reprint, 2006).

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelsen, Hans. 1960a. Reine rechtslehre, 2nd ed. Vienna: Deuticke.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelsen, Hans. 1960b. What is the pure theory of law? Tulane Law Review 34: 269–276.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelsen, Hans. 1965. Professor Stone and the pure theory of law. Stanford Law Review 17: 1128–1157.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kelsen, Hans. 1967. Pure Theory of Law. Trans. M. Knight. Berkeley: University of California Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelsen, Hans. 1992. Introduction to the Problems of Legal Theory. Trans. B.L. Paulson and S.L. Paulson. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Kelsen, Hans. 2013. A ‘realistic’ theory of law and the pure theory of law: Remarks on Alf Ross’s on law and justice. In Kelsen revisited: New essays on the pure theory of law, ed. Luís Duarte d’Almeida, John Gardner, and Leslie Green, 195–221. Oxford: Hart Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marmor, Andrei. 2002. Exclusive legal positivism. In The Oxford handbook of jurisprudence & philosophy of law, ed. Jules Coleman and Scott Shapiro, 104–124. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Marmor, Andrei. 2007. Law in the age of pluralism. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Marmor, Andrei. 2011. The conventional foundations of law. In New essays on the normativity of law, ed. Stefano Bertea and George Pavlakos, 143–157. Oxford: Hart Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Morawetz, Thomas. 1999. Law as experience: Theory and the internal aspect of law. SMU Law Review 52: 27–66.

    Google Scholar 

  • Murphy, Jeffrie G., and Jules L. Coleman. 1990. Philosophy of law, rev. ed. Boulder, Colorado: Westview Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1998. On the Genealogy of Morality. Trans. M. Clark and A.J. Swensen. Indianapolis: Hackett Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paulson, Stanley L. 1992a. The neo-Kantian dimension of Kelsen’s pure theory of law. Oxford Journal of Legal Studies 12: 311–332.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Paulson, Stanley L. 1992b. Supplementary notes. In Introduction to the problems of legal theory, ed. Hans Kelsen, Bonnie Litschewski Paulson, and Stanley L. Paulson, 127–137. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paulson, Stanley L. 2006. J. W. Harris’s Kelsen. In Properties of law: Essays in honour of Jim Harris, ed. Timothy Endicott, Joshua Getzler, and Edwin Peel, 3–21. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paulson, Stanley L. 2012. A ‘justified normativity’ thesis in Hans Kelsen’s pure theory of law?: Rejoinders to Robert Alexy and Joseph Raz. In Institutionalized reason: The jurisprudence of Robert Alexy, ed. Matthias Klatt, 61–111. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Paulson, Stanley L. 2013a. A great puzzle: Kelsen’s basic norm. In Kelsen revisited: New essays on the pure theory of law, ed. Luís Duarte d’Almeida, John Gardner, and Leslie Green, 43–61. Oxford: Hart Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paulson, Stanley L. 2013b. How Merkl’s stufenbaulehre informs Kelsen’s concept of law. Revus 21: 29–45.

    Google Scholar 

  • Priel, Dan. 2013. Is there one right answer to the question of the nature of law? In Philosophical foundations of the nature of law, ed. Wil Waluchow and Stefan Sciaraffa, 322–340. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Raz, Joseph. 1976. Kelsen’s general theory of norms. Philosophia 6: 495–504.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Raz, Joseph. 1980. The concept of a legal system, 2nd ed. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Raz, Joseph. 1986. The purity of the pure theory. In Essays on Kelsen, ed. Richard Tur and William Twining, 80–97. Oxford: Clarendon.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, Joseph. 1990. Practical reason and norms. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, Joseph. 1999. Engaging reason: On the theory of value and action. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Raz, Joseph. 2009. The authority of law, 2nd ed. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Schauer, Frederick. 2010. Was Austin right after all?: On the role of sanctions in a theory of law. Ratio Juris 23: 1–21.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Shapiro, Scott J. 2011. Legality. Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Acknowledgement

I am grateful for the comments and suggestions of participants of the Valparaiso University Law School Conference, Hans Kelsen in America. Portions of the second part of this paper were developed from ideas presented in “Rules and Normativity in Law,” in Problems of Normativity, Rules and Rule Following (Bix 2015).

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Brian H. Bix .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Bix, B.H. (2016). Kelsen in the United States: Still Misunderstood. In: Telman, D. (eds) Hans Kelsen in America - Selective Affinities and the Mysteries of Academic Influence. Law and Philosophy Library, vol 116. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-33130-0_2

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics