Skip to main content

Unspoken Ethical Issues in the Climate Affair: Insights from a Theoretical Analysis of Negotiation Mandates

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
The Economics of the Global Environment

Part of the book series: Studies in Economic Theory ((ECON.THEORY,volume 29))

Abstract

Taking climate change as an example, this paper provides new insights on the optimal provision of a long-term public good within and across generations. We write the Bowen–Lindhal–Samuelson (BLS) conditions for the optimal provision of the public good in a world divided into N countries, with two periods, present and future, and we simultaneously determine the optimal response in the first and second periods for a given rate of pure time preference. However, the Negishi weights at second period cannot be determined unambiguously, even under a “no redistribution constraint” within each generation, because they depend on non-observable future incomes; and thus on the answers to two often-overlooked ethical questions: (i) Do rich countries agree on deals which recognize that developing countries may catch up with developed countries in the long run, or do they use their negotiating powers to preserve the current balance of power? And (ii) does each country consider only the welfare of its own future citizens (dynastic solidarity) or does it extend its concern to all future human beings (universal solidarity)? Answers to (i) and (ii)—critical in the debate about how to correct the market failures causing global warming—define four sets of Negishi weights and intertemporal welfare functions, which we interpret as four mandates that countries could give to the Chair of an international negotiation on climate change to find an optimal solution. We find that in all mandates, public good provision expenditures are decreasing functions of income at first period. But each mandate leads to a different allocation of expenditures at second period and to different optimal levels of public good provision at both first and second periods. Finally, we show that only one of these four mandates defines a space for viable compromises.

The authors are grateful to François Bourguignon, Graciela Chichilnisky, Sylviane Gastaldo, Roger Guesnerie, Cédric Philibert, Gilles Rotillon, Zmarak Shalizi, Tarik Tazdait, David Wheeler and anonymous referees for very constructive comments on earlier versions of this manuscript. The authors would also like to thank the participants of workshops and seminars in Kyoto, Bilbao, La Réunion, Washington D.C., and Paris for helpful discussion.

Reprinted with kind permission from the Authors: Originally published in Economic Theory, Volume 49, Number 2, February 2012.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
eBook
USD 139.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Available as EPUB and PDF
  • Read on any device
  • Instant download
  • Own it forever
Softcover Book
USD 179.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Compact, lightweight edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info
Hardcover Book
USD 179.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
  • Durable hardcover edition
  • Dispatched in 3 to 5 business days
  • Free shipping worldwide - see info

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Notes

  1. 1.

    The ethical justification of grandfathering is the absence of retroactive responsibility for decisions made before the reformulation of the international social contract by the climate regime.

  2. 2.

    The UNFCCC is the UN body which oversees international negotiations on climate change. In fact, UNFCCC art. 4 provided a practical translation of the “common but differentiated principle” in the 1992 context by setting up emissions targets for year 2000 for developed countries only (art. 4.2), on the ground that “social development and poverty eradication are the first and overriding priorities of the developing countr[ies]” (art. 4.7). But deeper emissions cuts beyond 2012 require participation of at least major emitters among developing countries. Hence the renewed debate about who should reduce GHG emissions, and by how much.

  3. 3.

    See inter alia multicriteria (Ringius et al. 1998), contraction and convergence (Meyer 2002) or historical responsibilities (Den Elzen et al. 1999).

  4. 4.

    This insight was further developed in Chichilnisky and Heal (1994), and in Chichilnisky et al. (2000). In a related discussion in this volume, Chipman and Tian (2016) characterize the conditions under which, in a two-individual economy with a polluter and pollutee, the optimal level of pollution is independent of the initial assignment of property rights.

  5. 5.

    The Kyoto Protocol was adopted at COP3 in 1997. The ‘application decrees’ of the Kyoto Protocol were adopted at COP7 (2001). Subsequent COPs like the recent COP15 in Copenhagen have focused on negotiating the post-Kyoto framework.

  6. 6.

    E.g., Australia and the U.S. after Kyoto. However, Australia has since ratified the Kyoto Protocol (2007). In the U.S., the House of Representatives passed the American Clean Energy and Security Act of 2009 that would establish an economy-wide, greenhouse gas cap-and-trade system. At time of writing, the legislation is currently under debate in the U.S. Senate.

  7. 7.

    The present paper focuses on the conditions for an international agreement on climate change. Yet, reaching a global agreement is a necessary but not a sufficient condition to effective mitigation as actions at different scales interact Ostrom (2016).

  8. 8.

    In the Kyoto Protocol this condition is not met for most economies in transitions which were given more allowances than projected baseline emissions. But this situation results from tactical concessions made during the negotiations, and it is unlikely to be replicated in post-Kyoto agreements.

  9. 9.

    Obviously, this results into a very unequal weighting of individual utilities. But were all the weights set to unity instead, the planner would recommend a large-scale, politically unrealistic, redistribution of wealth to achieve the equal per capita distribution of income that would maximize social welfare.

  10. 10.

    Developed countries may argue that convergence in per capita incomes may not occur, or at least may not necessarily occur because of institutional failures in developing countries or of mechanisms leading to poverty traps.

  11. 11.

    For an overview of the attitudes vis-à-vis climate change damages, see Ambrosi et al. (2003).

  12. 12.

    We discuss later the ethical rationale and political likelihood of this attitude, which appears in the discourses of many NGOs. For the time being, let us treat it as a pure logical possibility. Let us simply underline that the term solidarity is not synonymous of equity. Its Latin root is very suggestive: solidus means compact, solid, firm, while solidarus means with whom I consider myself to be attached.

  13. 13.

    This index is a simplification of the dynamics of GHG accumulation in the atmosphere since it ignores the carbon cycle, but it is sufficient to capture the stock externality character of climate change.

  14. 14.

    Damage functions d i are twice differentiable. Damages are assumed positive (d i  > 0), decreasing in the amount of abatement (d ' i  < 0), but at a diminishing rate (d i  < 0). Finally, we assume that damages per capita in the absence of abatement remain lower than per capita income (d i (0) < y f i ).

  15. 15.

    Functions C and C f are twice differentiable, and such that C > 0, C′ > 0, C″ > 0, and C(0) = C′(0) = 0 (same assumptions for C f). One can derive aggregate abatement cost functions as follows. Let x i be the national abatement levels relative to business-as-usual, and let C i (x i ) be the national abatement cost functions. The aggregate abatement cost function C(x) is defined as: \( C(x) = {\text{Min}}_{{x_{i} }} \left\{ {\sum\limits_{i} {C_{i} \left( {x_{i} } \right)} \left| {\sum\limits_{i} {x_{i} = x} } \right.} \right\} \). This is as if individual payments for mitigation were aggregated into a fund that would reduce emissions where it is the cheapest to do so. Baseline emissions and abatement costs in region i are independent from abatement in other regions. Thus, there are no leakage across regions in our model (see Burniaux and Oliveira Martins 2016, for a discussion of this issue).

  16. 16.

    To ensure the existence of a solution, we also need that damages be reducible to zero if mitigation expenditures are high enough. Technically, let \( \bar{x} \) be the level of abatement achieved if all available resources (short of maximum damages) were allocated to mitigation, i.e., \( \bar{x} = C^{{{-} 1}} \left( {\sum\nolimits_{i} {l_{i} y_{i} } + C^{{f{-} 1}} \left( {\sum\nolimits_{i} {l_{i}^{f} (a_{i}^{f} {-}d_{i} (0)} } \right)} \right) \). We assume that for all x ≥ \( \bar{x} \) and all regions, d i (x) = 0.

  17. 17.

    Guesnerie (2004), Heal (2007) and Sterner and Persson (2008) show the importance of including a preference for the environment as an argument of the utility function to carry out a cost-benefit analysis of climate policies. In our model this inclusion is made indirectly by subtracting damages from total households’ consumption.

  18. 18.

    U i and U f i are twice differentiable in all variables, with U i  > 0, U i  < 0, and \( \frac{{\partial U_{i}^{f} }}{{\partial d_{j} }} < 0 \).

  19. 19.

    We assume here that there is common agreement about the future distribution of income.

  20. 20.

    The Negishi weights β i could be calibrated on the net per capita income at second period y f i  − d i , i.e., after accounting for the impacts of climate change. We do not retain this option to clearly distinguish between uncertainty about economic growth in the absence of climate change and uncertainty about climate change damages.

  21. 21.

    Future utility functions are unobservable. We take the position that functions U f i represent Parties’ views about their descendants’ utilities.

  22. 22.

    An alternative framework is possible under the ethical condition that individual agents have sustainable preferences taking into account long-term future as well. Chichilnisky (2016). demonstrates that under limited arbitrage, such preferences then lead to a sustainable market equilibrium.

  23. 23.

    Because the main focus of our paper is on the relationships between inter and intra generational distributions, we adopt a two-period model (as opposed to a model with an infinite number of periods), which leaves aside critical discussions about how to include long-term sustainability concerns within intergenerational social welfare functions. The latter debate is addressed in this volume by Asheim et al. (2016), Figuières and Tidball (2016), and Lauwers (2016).

  24. 24.

    Contributions a i can be considered ‘small’ in mathematical terms if they are less than 5 % of y i —which corresponds to an extraordinary large mitigation effort.

  25. 25.

    With a logarithmic utility function, each European should contribute 15–76 times as much as the average Indian depending on the whether purchasing power parities or current exchange rates parities are used to compare real income levels (2000 Gross National Income, World Bank 2004).

  26. 26.

    For diplomatic reasons (see the last-minute statement by the G77 and China mentioned in the introduction), negotiators going to Kyoto had accepted the idea that only developed countries would take commitments. As a result, the Kyoto Protocol follows the UNFCCC (see footnote ‎2) and only embodies a very crude differentiation, i.e., efforts in the North, none in the South, leading to an implicit price of carbon of zero for developing countries, and the critical issue of differentiation remains unaddressed (Chichilnisky 2016).

  27. 27.

    In a cap-and-trade regime, the planner can use the initial allocation of emission quotas to offset the welfare losses that might result from a uniform price of emissions allowances. In a tax system, a distinction has to be made between the industrial sector, where taxes must be equated to avoid distorting international competition, and the domestic sector, where taxes can be differentiated (Hourcade and Gilotte 2000). On the price versus quantity debate, see also in this volume Karp and Zhang (2016).

  28. 28.

    Twenty-three is the 2002 gap in per capita gross national income between high-income countries, and low- and middle-income countries (World Bank 2004).

  29. 29.

    Projections of future world average temperatures by global circulation models have a far higher degree of confidence than projections at local scale. And uncertainty grows by another order of magnitude when local physical impacts are translated into economic damages: Western Europe may experience either warming by 2 °C or more or cooling by several degrees depending on the evolution of the North-Atlantic thermohaline circulation. Russia is often regarded as a potential winner of global warming. But the melting of the permafrost, or dryness in the South of the country might put it among the losers.

  30. 30.

    This warning, often attributed to George H. Bush Sr., would probably be endorsed, albeit in more diplomatic terms, in many quarters of the developed world.

  31. 31.

    It is precisely the lack of clarification that future quotas would not be allocated through grandfathering that led the G77 to veto the rules governing carbon trading in the penultimate day of the Kyoto Conference.

  32. 32.

    A situation analogous to the “veil of ignorance” of Rawls (1971).

  33. 33.

    The self-interest justifications for the universal mandate imposes that \( \frac{{\partial^{2} U_{i}^{f} }}{{\partial c\partial d_{j} }} \ne 0 \), so that damages abroad impact on marginal utilities of consumption (directly or through compensation or security expenditures) and not only on utility levels.

  34. 34.

    The reason is that the marginal utility of the consumption of the public goods is the marginal utility of consumption times the avoided damage. Since the Negishi weights are proportional to the inverse of the marginal utility of consumption, they cancel out, and only the sum of avoided damages remains.

  35. 35.

    If the equilibrium is a corner solution, the optimal level of abatement increases relative to the interior solutions because some countries have a higher WMU than the others. In Table 1, for example, the optimal abatement level in scenario h—in which all damages fall on S—is 1.4 % higher than in scenario a where N and S are equally impacted.

  36. 36.

    Even though in a static one-period framework, a stronger preference for equity may lead to less action on climate change because low-income populations have a lower marginal utility of the environment (Tol), here, whatever the selfish or altruistic character of its motivation, a universal solidarity attitude that includes concerns about the situation of poor populations enhances the need for action.

  37. 37.

    For logarithmic or power utility functions. With more general utility functions, optimal efforts are typically increasing with income.

  38. 38.

    To identify margins of freedom for strategies with no consumption loss for the current generations of rich countries and no slowdown in the take off of developing countries, one needs a multi-goods model to study how investments can be massively redirected (200–400 G$ in 2030 according to World Bank 2009) and how those that lose from this redirection may be compensated. Using a game-theory approach, Dutta and Radner (2010) provide general conditions on how such transfers could be effective.

References

  • Agarwal, A., & Narain, S. (1991). Global warming in an unequal world, a case of environmental colonialism. Delhi: Center for Science and Environment.

    Google Scholar 

  • Aldy, J. E., & Stavins, R. (Eds.). (2007). Architectures for agreement: Addressing global climate change in the post-Kyoto world. Cambridge, UK: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ambrosi, P., Hourcade, J.-C., Hallegatte, S., Lecocq, F., Dumas, P., & Ha-Duong, M. (2003). Optimal control models and elicitation of attitudes towards climate damages. Environmental Modeling and Assessment, 8, 133–147.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Asheim, G. B., Mitra, T. L., & Tungodden, B. (2016). Sustainable recursive social welfare functions. Economic Theory (reprinted in this volume). doi:10.1007/s00199-010-0573-7.

    Google Scholar 

  • Azar, C. (1999). Weight factors in cost-benefit analysis of climate change. Environmental & Resource Economics, 13, 249–268.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Burniaux, J.-M., & Oliveira Martins, J. (2016). Carbon leakages: A general equilibrium view. Economic Theory (reprinted in this volume). doi:10.1007/s00199-010-0579-1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chichilnisky, G. (1994). The abatement of carbon emissions in industrial and developing countries. In T. Jones (Ed.), The economics of climate change (pp. 159–170). Paris: OECD.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chichilnisky, G. (2016). Sustainable markets with short sales. Economic Theory (reprinted in this volume).

    Google Scholar 

  • Chichilnisky, G., & Sheeran, K. A. (2009). Saving Kyoto. London: New Holland Publishers Ltd.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chichilnisky, G., & Heal, G. (1994). Who should abate carbon emissions: An international viewpoint. Economics Letters, 443–449.

    Google Scholar 

  • Chichilnisky, G., Heal, G., & Starrett, D. (2000). Equity and efficiency in environmental markets: Global trade in carbon emissions. In G. Chichilnisky & G. Heal (Eds.), Environmental markets (pp. 46–67). New York: Colombia University Press.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Chipman, J. S., & Guoqiang, T. (2016). Detrimental externalities, pollution rights, and the “Coase Theorem”. Economic Theory (reprinted in this volume).

    Google Scholar 

  • Cooper, R. J. (2000). International approaches to global climate change. The World Bank Research Observer, 15, 145–172.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Den Elzen, M., Berk, M., Schaeffer, M., Olivier, J., Hendriks, C., & Metz, B. (1999). The Brazilian proposal and other options for international burden sharing: An evaluation of methodological and policy aspects using the FAIR Model. RIVM Report No. 728001011, Bilthoven.

    Google Scholar 

  • Dutta, P. K., & Radner, R. (2010). Capital growth in a global warming model: Will China and India sign a climate treaty? Economic Theory (2010, this issue).

    Google Scholar 

  • Figuières, C., & Tidball, M. (2016). Sustainable exploitation of a natural resource: A satisfying use of Chichilnisky criterion. Economic Theory (reprinted in this volume). doi:10.1007/s00199-010-0579-1.

    Google Scholar 

  • Fisher, B. S., Nakicenovic, N., Alfsen, K., Corfee Morlot, J., de la Chesnaye, F., Hourcade, J.-C., et al. (2007). Issues related to mitigation in the long term context. In: B. Metz, O. R. Davidson, P. R. Bosch, R. Dave & L. A. Meyer (Eds.), Climate Change 2007: Mitigation. Contribution of Working Group III to the Fourth Assessment Report of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (pp. 169–250). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Foley, D. K. (2009). The economic fundamentals of global warming. In J. M. Harris & N. R. Goodwin (Eds.), Twenty-first century macroeconomics—Responding to the climate challenge. Northampton: Edward Elgar Publishing.

    Google Scholar 

  • Godard, O. (2000). Sur l’éthique, l’environnement et l’économie. La justification en question. Cahier du Laboratoire d’Econométrie de l’Ecole Polytechnique. Paris: Ecole Polytechnique.

    Google Scholar 

  • Goldemberg, J., Squitieri, R., Stiglitz, J., Amano, A., Shaoxiong, X., & Saha, R. (1996). Introduction: Scope of the assessment. In J. P. Bruce, H. Lee, & E. F. Haites (Eds.), Climate Change 1995: Economic and Social Dimensions of Climate Change, Contribution of Working Group III to the Second Assessment Report of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (pp. 125–144). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Grubb, M., Vrolijk, C., & Brack, D. (1999). The Kyoto protocol, a guide and an assessment. London: Royal Institute of International Affairs.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gupta, S., Tirpak, D. A., Burger, N., Gupta, J., Höhne, N., Boncheva, A. I., et al. (2007). Policies, instruments and co-operative arrangements. In: B. Metz, O. R. Davidson, P. R. Bosch, R. Dave & L. A. Meyer (Eds.), Climate Change 2007: Mitigation. Contribution of Working Group III to the Fourth Assessment Report of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (pp. 745–808). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guesnerie, R. (2004). Calcul économique et développement durable. Rev Econ Paris, 55(3), 363–382.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hallegatte, S., Hourcade, J.-C., & Dumas, P. (2007). Why economic dynamics matter in assessing climate change damages: Illustration on extreme events. Ecological Economics, 62(2), 330–340.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Heal, G. (2007). Discounting: A review of the basic economics. The University of Chicago Law Review, 74, 59–77.

    Google Scholar 

  • Helm, C., & Simonis, U. E. (2001). Distributive justice in international environmental policy: Axiomatic foundation and exemplary formulation. Environmental Values, 10(1), 5–18.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hourcade, J.-C., Ambrosi, P., & Dumas, P. (2009). Beyond the stern review: Lessons from a risky venture at the limits of the cost-benefit analysis. Ecological Economics, 68(10), 2479–2484.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Hourcade, G. F. (2002). The economics of a lost deal: Kyoto—The Hague—Marrakesh. The Energy Journal, 23(3), 1–26.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hourcade, G. L. (2000). Differentiated or uniform international carbon taxes: Theoretical evidences and procedural. In: G. Chichilnisky & G. Heal (Eds.), Environmental markets (pp. 135–168). New York: Colombia University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC). (1994). Radiative forcing of climate change and an evaluation of the IPCC IS92 emission scenarios. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC). (2007). Climate Change 2007: Impacts, adaptation and vulnerability. In Contribution of Working Group II to the Fourth Assessment Report of the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Jacoby, H. D., Prinn, R. G., & Schmalensee, R. (1998). Kyoto’s unfinished business. Foreign Affairs, 77, 54–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Karp, L., & Zhang, J. (2016). Taxes versus quantities for a stock pollutant with endogenous abatement costs and asymmetric information. Economic Theory (reprinted in this volume). doi:10.1007/s00199-010-0561-y.

    Google Scholar 

  • Lauwers, L. (2016). Intergenerational equity, efficiency, and constructibility. Economic Theory (reprinted in this volume).

    Google Scholar 

  • Lecocq, F., & Crassous, R. (2003). International climate regime beyond 2012. Are quota allocation rules robust to uncertainty? World Bank Policy Research Working Paper 3000.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meyer, A. (2002). Contraction and convergence, the solution to climate change. Schumacher Briefing No. 5, Green Books.

    Google Scholar 

  • Negishi, T. (1960). Welfare economics and existence of an equilibrium for a competitive economy. Metroeconomica, 12, 92–97.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nordhaus, W. D., & Yang, Z. (1996). A regional dynamic general-equilibrium model of alternative climate-change strategies. American Economic Review, 86, 741–765.

    Google Scholar 

  • Nordhaus. (2007). A review of the stern review on the economics of climate change. Journal of Economic Literature, 45, 686–702.

    Google Scholar 

  • Organization for Economic Co-operation and Development (OECD). (1993). International economic instruments and climate change. Paris: OECD.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ostrom, E. (2016). Nested externalities and polycentric institutions: Must we wait for global solutions to climate change before taking actions at other scales? Economic Theory (reprinted in this volume). doi:10.1007/s00199-010-0558-6.

    Google Scholar 

  • Posner, E. A., & Sunstein, C. R. (2009). Should greenhouse gas permits be allocated on a per capita basis? California Law Review, 97(1), 51–93.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rawls, J. (1971). A theory of Justice. Cambridge: The Belknap Press of Harvard University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Rezai, A., Foley, D. K., & Taylor, L. (2016). Global warming and economic externalities. Economic Theory (reprinted in this volume).

    Google Scholar 

  • Ringius, L., Torvanger, A., & Holtsmark, B. (1998). Can multi-criteria rules fairly distribute climate burdens—OECD results from three burden sharing rules. Energy Policy, 26(10), 777–793.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sandler, T., & Smith, K. V. (1976). Intertemporal and intergenerational pareto efficiency. Journal of Environmental Economics and Management, 2, 151–159.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Schelling, T. C. (1995). Intergenerational discounting. Energy Policy, 23, 395–401.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Sen, A. K. (1987). On ethics and economics. Oxford: Basil Blackwell Publishers.

    Google Scholar 

  • Shalizi, Z., & Lecocq, F. (2009). To mitigate or to adapt: Is that the question? Observations on an appropriate response to the climate change challenge to development strategies. The World Bank Research Observer. doi:10.1093/wbro/lkp012.

    Google Scholar 

  • Sheeran, K. (2006). Who should abate carbon emissions? A note. Environmental & Resource Economics, 35(2), 89–98.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stern, N. (2007). The economics of climate change: The Stern Review. Cambridge, UK and New York: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Sterner, T., & Persson, U. M. (2008). An even Sterner Review: Introducing relative prices into the discounting debate. Review of Environmental Economics and Policy, 2(1), 61–76.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Stone, C. D. (2004). Common but differentiated responsibilities in International Law. American Journal of International Law, 98(2), 276–301.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • World Bank. (2004). World Development Indicators. Washington D.C: World Bank.

    Google Scholar 

  • World Bank. (2009). World Development Report 2009. Washington D.C: World Bank.

    Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Franck Lecocq .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Appendices

Appendix 1: Model Resolution

We solve a general version of the planner’s problem (‎26)—in which coefficients χ i summarize both S and C mandates (27)—under constraints (‎3), ( 4), (‎5), and (‎6).

$$ {\text{Max}}_{{\{ a_{i} ,a_{i}^{f} \} }} \sum\limits_{i} {\alpha_{i} l_{i} U_{i} \left( {y_{i} {-}a_{i} } \right)} + \varphi \sum\limits_{i} {\chi_{i} l_{i}^{f} U_{i}^{f} \left( {y_{i}^{f} {-}a_{i}^{f} {-}d_{i} \left( {x + x^{f} } \right),d_{j \ne i} } \right)} $$
(26)

With

$$ \chi_{i} = \left\{ {\begin{array}{*{20}l} {\alpha_{i} = \frac{\alpha }{{{\text{U}}_{\text{i}}^{\prime } \left( {y_{i} } \right)}}\;{\text{in}}\;{\text{S}}\;{\text{mandates}},{\text{with}}\;\alpha = \left( {\sum\limits_{i} {\frac{{l_{i} }}{{{\text{U}}_{1}^{\prime } \left( {y_{i} } \right)}}} } \right)^{ - 1} } \hfill \\ {\beta_{i} = \frac{\beta }{{{\text{U}}_{\text{i}}^{\prime } \left( {y_{i} } \right)}}\;{\text{in}}\;{\text{C}}\;{\text{mandates}},{\text{with}}\;\beta = \left( {\sum\limits_{i} {\frac{{l_{i}^{f} }}{{{\text{U}}_{\text{i}}^{{{\text{f}}\prime }} \left( {y_{i}^{f} } \right)}}} } \right)^{ - 1} } \hfill \\ \end{array} } \right. $$
(27)

Let λ, φ μ, l i ξ i and φ l f i ψ i be the Lagrange multipliers attached to constraints (‎3), (‎4), (‎5), and (‎6) respectively. Since (‎5) and (‎6) are inequality conditions, ξ i and ψ i are such that:

$$ \left\{ {\begin{array}{*{20}l} {\xi_{i} = 0} \hfill & {\text{if}} \hfill & {a_{i} > 0} \hfill \\ {\xi_{i} > 0} \hfill & {\text{if}} \hfill & {a_{i} = 0} \hfill \\ \end{array} } \right. $$
(28)
$$ \left\{ {\begin{array}{*{20}l} {\psi_{i} = 0} \hfill & {\text{if}} \hfill & {a_{i}^{f} > 0} \hfill \\ {\psi_{i} > 0} \hfill & {\text{if}} \hfill & {a_{i}^{f} = 0} \hfill \\ \end{array} } \right. $$
(29)

With these notations, the Lagrangean of the problem becomes:

$$ \begin{aligned} L = & \sum\limits_{i} {\alpha_{i} l_{i} U_{i} \left( {y_{i} - a_{i} } \right)} + \varphi \sum\limits_{i} {\chi_{i} l_{i}^{f} U_{i}^{f} \left( {y_{i}^{f} - a_{i}^{f} {-}d_{i} \left( {x + x^{f} } \right),d_{j \ne i} } \right)} \\ & + \,\lambda \left[ {\sum\limits_{i} {l_{i} a_{i} - C(x)} } \right] + \varphi \mu \left[ {\sum\limits_{i} {l_{i}^{f} a_{i}^{f} - C^{f} \left( {x^{f} } \right)} } \right] + \sum\limits_{i} {l_{i} \xi_{i} a_{i} } + \varphi \sum\limits_{i} {l_{i}^{f} \psi_{i} a_{i}^{f} } \\ \end{aligned} $$
(30)

The first-order condition with regard to a i is:

$$ \frac{\partial L}{{\partial a_{i} }} = 0 \Rightarrow \alpha_{i} U_{i}^{\prime } \left( {y_{i} - a_{i} } \right) - \xi_{i} = \lambda $$
(31)

We first demonstrate that (‎31) has a unique solution with strictly positive abatement levels a i . Let us assume without loss of generality that a 1 were zero. Since ξ 1 > 0, α 1 U 1′(y 1 − a 1) − ξ 1 = α 1 U 1′(y 1) − ξ 1 < α 1 U 1′(y 1). If another abatement level, say a 2, were strictly positive, then α 2 U 2′(y 2 − a 2) − ξ 2 = α 2 U 2′(y 2 − a 2) > α 2 U 2′(y 2) since marginal utilities are strictly decreasing functions. Yet by definition of the Negishi weights, α 1 U 1′(y 1) = α 2 U 2′(y 2). Thus, we would have α 1 U 1′(y 1 − a 1) − ξ 1 < α 2 U 2′(y 2 − a 2) − ξ 2, contradicting Eq. (31). Thus, if one of the abatement expenditures is zero, all abatement expenditures are zero.

But if all a i were zero, Eq. (3) and the fact that C(0) = 0 would imply that x = 0, and thus that marginal costs of abatement C′ are zero. Equalization between marginal costs of abatement and marginal damages at optimum (Eq. ‎36) would then imply that all marginal damages d i ′(x + x f) be zero, and thus (via Eq. 33) that the marginal costs of mitigation at second period be zero, and thus that the level of abatement at second period x f = 0. But this would contradicts the assumption that no abatement leads to strictly positive marginal damages of climate change. First-period abatement levels a i are thus all strictly positive, and since marginal utility functions are strictly decreasing, they are uniquely defined.

Similarly, derivation of L with regard to a f i yields:

$$ \frac{\partial L}{{\partial a_{i}^{f} }} = 0 \Rightarrow \chi_{i} U_{i}^{f\prime } \left( {y_{i}^{f} - a_{i}^{f} - d_{i} \left( {x + x^{f} } \right),d_{j \ne i} } \right) - \psi_{i} = \mu $$
(32)

The second part of the argument above can be replicated to demonstrate that at least one of the second-period abatement expenditures a f i is strictly positive. But the first part of the argument above cannot be applied as is, and thus there is no guarantee that all second-period abatement expenditures be strictly positive.

In C mandates, this is because marginal utilities before abatement and after damages \( \chi_{i} U_{i}^{f\prime } \left( {y_{i}^{f} {-}d_{i } \left( {x + x^{f} } \right)} \right) \) have no reason a priori to be equal. We only know that marginal utilities of consumption before abatement and before damages \( \chi_{i} U_{i}^{f\prime } \left( {y_{i}^{f} } \right) \) are equal (by construction), and thus that the aggregate climate bills a f i  + d i (and not just the abatement expenditures component) are all strictly positive.

In S mandates, even that weaker property does not hold because even marginal utilities of consumption before abatement and before damages \( \chi_{i} U_{i}^{f\prime } \left( {y_{i}^{f} } \right) \) have no reason a priori to be equal across regions.

Derivation of L with regard to x f yields:

$$ C^{f\prime } \left( {x^{f} } \right) = \sum\limits_{i} {l_{i}^{f} } \pi_{i} \left[ { - d_{i}^{\prime } \left( {x + x^{f} } \right) + \rho \sum\limits_{j \ne i} {\frac{{\frac{{\partial U_{i}^{f} }}{{\partial d_{j} }}}}{{U_{i}^{f\prime } }}d_{j}^{\prime } \left( {x + x^{f} } \right)} } \right] $$
(33)

With

$$ \pi_{i} = \frac{{\chi_{i} }}{\mu }U_{i}^{f\prime } \left( {y_{i}^{f} - d_{i} \left( {x + x^{f} } \right) - a_{i}^{f} ,d_{j \ne i} } \right) = \frac{{\chi_{i} U_{i}^{f\prime } }}{{\chi_{i} U_{i}^{f\prime } - \psi_{i} }} $$
(34)

Given the assumptions made about marginal damages and marginal abatement costs, (33) has a unique solution. Coefficients π i are the ratios of χ i U f i ′ the weighted marginal utility of consumption of country i, and of μ the weighted marginal utility of consumption of the countries that abate at second period (as per Eq. ‎32) (μ can also be interpreted as the shadow price of abatement at second period, expressed in marginal utility terms). When country i contributes to abatement at second period, these two terms are equal and π i  = 1. When country i does not contribute to abatement—either because it does not grow rapidly enough, or because domestic damages are too high—π i  > 1.

In other words, when a country has a weighted marginal utility of consumption that is too high relative to the others, not only will it not contribute to abatement, but damages falling on this country will be weighted higher than damages falling on others because they cause higher utility losses at the margin.

When all countries contribute—which, as discussed above, occurs mostly in the C mandates—(‎34) simplifies in (35), which is the standard BLS condition.

$$ C^{f\prime } \left( {x^{f} } \right) = {-}\sum\limits_{i} {l_{i}^{f} d_{i}^{\prime } \left( {x + x^{f} } \right)} $$
(35)

Finally, derivation of L with regard to x yields:

$$ C^{\prime } (x) = \varphi \sum\limits_{i} {l_{i}^{f} } \omega_{i} \left[ { - d_{i}^{\prime } \left( {x + x^{f} } \right) + \rho \sum\limits_{j \ne i} {\frac{{\frac{{\partial U_{i}^{f} }}{{\partial d_{j} }}}}{{U_{i}^{f\prime } }}d_{j}^{\prime } \left( {x + x^{f} } \right)} } \right] $$
(36)

with

$$ \omega_{i} = \frac{{\chi_{i} }}{\lambda }U_{i}^{f\prime } = \frac{{\chi_{i} U_{i}^{f\prime } \left( {y_{i}^{f} - d_{i} \left( {x + x^{f} } \right) - a_{i}^{f} ,d_{j \ne i} } \right)}}{{\alpha_{i} U_{i}^{\prime } \left( {y_{i} - a_{i} } \right)}} $$
(37)

Coefficients ω i capture the change in weighted marginal utility of consumptions between the first and the second period. Comparing Eqs. (‎33) and (36‎), the term φ ω i can be interpreted as the region-specific discount rate that applies to climate change damages. In C mandates, this term becomes

$$ \varphi \omega_{i} = \varphi \frac{\beta }{\alpha }\frac{{U_{i}^{\prime } \left( {y_{i} } \right)}}{{U_{i}^{\prime } \left( {y_{i} - a_{i} } \right)}}\frac{{U_{i}^{f\prime } \left( {y_{i}^{f} - d_{i} \left( {x + x^{f} } \right) - a_{i}^{f} ,d_{j \ne i} } \right)}}{{U_{i}^{f\prime } \left( {y_{i}^{f} } \right)}} $$
(38)

When abatement expenditures and damages remain small with regard to income, the last two terms are close to one, and regional discount factors are all equal to \( \varphi \frac{\beta }{\alpha } \). Hence coefficient ρ in Eq. (‎23). For example, with logarithmic utility functions, ρ = \( \varphi \frac{\beta }{\alpha } = \varphi \frac{1}{{(1 + r)^{N} }} \) where r is the aggregate growth rate of the economy over the first period. In D mandates, on the other hand, regional discount rates become

$$ \varphi \omega_{i} = \varphi \frac{{U_{i}^{f\prime } \left( {y_{i}^{f} - d_{i} \left( {x + x^{f} } \right) - a_{i}^{f} ,d_{j \ne i} } \right)}}{{U_{i}^{\prime } \left( {y_{i} - a_{i} } \right)}} $$
(39)

which vary depending on the regional growth rate between the two periods. For example, with logarithmic utility functions, ρ i  = \( \varphi \frac{1}{{\left( {1 + r_{i} } \right)^{N} }} \) where r i are the regional growth rates over the first period.

Appendix 2: Data and Modeling Framework of Numerical Experiments

The world is divided in two regions: “North” (N) comprises high-income countries, as per World Bank (2004) definition, and “South” (S) low and middle income countries. The first period is 2000–2049, and the second 2050–2099. Initial income and population data are from World Bank (2004). Average annual economic growth in N is assumed to be 2.5 % between 2000 and 2050, against 3 % in S. World population is assumed to grow by 2 billions in that period of time, all of them in S (Table 4). For simplicity’s sake, we use 2000 (resp. 2050) figures as averages for period 1 (resp. 2).

Table 4 Key assumptions in numerical example

Without abatement, World CO2 emissions are assumed to be 513 GtCO2 during the first period, and 688 GtCO2 during the second, as in the IPCC IS92a scenario (IPCC 1994).

Abatement costs at first and second period are assumed quadratic with respect to total abatement levels. We also assume that mitigating all the emissions in the world economy would cost at the margin $1,500/tC during the first period, and $1,000/tC during the second. After easy manipulations, Eqs. (‎3) and (‎4) become:

$$ x = 1482 \times \sqrt {\frac{{l_{N} a_{N} + l_{S} a_{S} }}{{l_{N} y_{N} + l_{S} y_{S} }}} $$
(40)
$$ x^{f} = 4066 \times \sqrt {\frac{{l_{N}^{f} a_{N}^{f} + l_{S}^{f} a_{S}^{f} }}{{l_{N}^{f} y_{N}^{f} + l_{S}^{f} y_{S}^{f} }}} $$
(41)

Damages are assumed cubic with total emissions.

$$ d_{i} \left( {x + x^{f} } \right) = y_{i}^{f} \theta_{i} \left( {1 - \frac{{x + x^{f} }}{1201}} \right)^{3} $$
(42)

Coefficients θ i represent the maximum damage—expressed as a share of per capita GDP—that each region may sustain because of climate change. If there were no mitigation at all, damages would be \( d_{i} = y_{i}^{f} \theta_{i} \) We use several values for coefficients θ i to represent various assumptions about the distribution of impacts of climate change across regions—keeping the aggregate maximal damage \( l_{S}^{f} y_{S}^{f} \theta_{S} + l_{N}^{f} y_{N}^{f} \theta_{N} \) constant. Finally, all utility functions are assumed logarithmic, and the rate of pure time preference φ is set to 1 %.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2016 Springer International Publishing Switzerland

About this chapter

Cite this chapter

Lecocq, F., Hourcade, JC. (2016). Unspoken Ethical Issues in the Climate Affair: Insights from a Theoretical Analysis of Negotiation Mandates. In: Chichilnisky, G., Rezai, A. (eds) The Economics of the Global Environment. Studies in Economic Theory, vol 29. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-31943-8_15

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics